Leisure, Virtue, Politics, and Work: An Aristotelian Excursus. J. L. Hemingway

Similar documents
C1,J Oxbridge Essays. Aristotle s Political Philosophy

PLATO ( BC) Mr. Thomas G.M., Associate Professor, Pompei College Aikala DK.

Aristotle (Odette) Aristotle s Nichomachean Ethics

VII. Aristotle, Virtue, and Desert

Aristotle ( BCE): First theorist of democracy. PHIL 2011 Semester II

(E)Racing the Citizen: The Contradictions of Citizenship. Bernal, Martin. Black Athena: The Afroasiatic Roots of Classical. 2 vols.

Politics By Aristotle (Written 350 B.C.E) By Benjamin Jowett, Aristotle

DEMOCRACY AND POLITICAL KNOWLEDGE IN ANCIENT ATHENS

The Ancient Greece & why Aristotle can cause problems for contemporary economists?

POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner

TWO DIFFERENT IDEAS OF FREEDOM: DEMOCRACY IN THE HISTORICAL CONTEXT OF GREEK POLEIS AND FREEDOM OF MODERN TIMES

Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy with Aristotle s. Political Philosophy

ARISTOTLE S POLITICS :

DEMOCRACY. Takamaro Hanzawa Tokyo Metropolitan University, Japan

POLI 355 Political Philosophy: Plato to Machiavelli. Athabasca University. Detailed Syllabus. Course Objectives

SUMMARY: ARISTOTLE POLITICS BOOK 1

Classical Civilizations of the Mediterranean & Middle East. Persia, Greece & Rome

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

Aristotle and the Voucher System. Jake Shanley, Baylor University

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

School of Law, Governance & Citizenship. Ambedkar University Delhi. Course Outline

QUEEN'S UNIVERSITY Department of Political Studies POLS 350 History of Political Thought 1990/91 Fall/Winter

POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner

POS 103, Introduction to Political Theory Peter Breiner

Democratic Theory 1 Trevor Latimer Office Hours: TBA Contact Info: Goals & Objectives. Office Hours. Midterm Course Evaluation

Plato s Concept of Justice: Prepared by, Mr. Thomas G.M., Associate Professor, Pompei College Aikala DK

Texts & Ideas: Mixed Constitutions CORE-UA Tuesday/Thursday, 2:00-3:15 PM Location: Meyer 121

Brunswick School Department: Grades 9-12

Is Democracy is the Best Form of Government System?

Københavns Universitet. Legitimacy and Democracy Rostbøll, Christian F. Published in: Introduction to Political Sociology. Publication date: 2013

Democracy at Risk. Schooling for Ruling. Deborah Meier. School's most pressing job is to teach the democratic life.

The Periclean Citizenship Law of 451/0 B.C.

III. Democracy. BDO: Nearly every ideological framework claims to further the cause of freedom.

Political Science The Political Theory of Capitalism Fall 2015

Instructor: Prof. Pasquale Pasquino

Athens. Chapter 5 Section 2 Warring City-States

Feng Zhang, Chinese Hegemony: Grand Strategy and International Institutions in East Asian History

Conferences marking the anniversary and related publications

Aristotle s Just Theory on the Exclusive Right to Property. One of the most rudimentary debates concerning civilization is that of the ownership of

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

EFFECTIVE LEADERSHIP BY CAPACITIES OF VIRTUES: A NEW ANALYSIS OF POWER OF POLITICAL LEADERSHIP IN CONFUCIAN PERSPECTIVE

Is 'Part of Justice' Just At All? Reconsidering Aristotle's Politics III.9

Aristotle Ricardo Crespo

Mark Joseph Lutz Curriculum Vitae September 1, 2014

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

On the Education of Youth in America By Noah Webster 1788

PHLB16H3S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY: ANCIENT GREECE AND MIDDLE AGES STUDY QUESTIONS (II): ARISTOTLE S POLITICS. A. Short Answer Questions

Scots, Wha Hae North Sea Gas

Theory Comprehensive January 2015

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

1.Myths and images about families influence our expectations and assumptions about family life. T or F

Topic Page: Democracy

NATIONAL HEARING QUESTIONS ACADEMIC YEAR

Foundations of American Government

Federica Carugati. Stanford University, Stanford, CA Program Director, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences (2018-present)

Citizenship-Rights and Duties

Herman, Gabriel Morality and Behaviour in Democratic Athens: A Social History

PSC 5323 Political Inquiry Approaches and Methods

History Extension Complete Notes - What is History & JFK

Can Patriotism Survive Democracy? The title is misleading. If you are. Reviews. summer 5763 /

Education as Regime Change in Aristotle's Politics

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

UNM Department of History. I. Guidelines for Cases of Academic Dishonesty

marguerite deslauriers and pierre destrée

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Forming a Republican citizenry

Ancient and Modern Democracy

NEO-CONSERVATISM IN THE USA FROM LEO STRAUSS TO IRVING KRISTOL

Democracy, Exile and Revocation: a reply to Patti Lenard. David Miller

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac

DEGREES IN HIGHER EDUCATION M.A.,

Political Science: An Introduction, 11e

Republican Government

Department of Political Science Fall, Political Science 306 Contemporary Democratic Theory Peter Breiner

A History of Regimes. Groups of Political Systems

Archetypal Biographical Template Pluribus Unum: From Many, One

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in a paragraph. (25 points total)

12. Which foreign religious tradition was absorbed into China during the classical period? A) Hinduism B) The Isis cult C) Buddhism D) Christianity

Aristotle's Ideal Regime as Utopia

DOWNLOAD PDF A TREATISE ON GOVERNMENT, OR, THE POLITICS OF ARISTOTLE

CHAPTER 2: MAJORITARIAN OR PLURALIST DEMOCRACY

Paley s Paradox: Educating for Democratic Life

Hobbes, Locke, Montesquieu, and Rousseau on Government

Three essential ways of anti-corruption. Wen Fan 1

21W.747 Class September Figures removed due to copyright restrictions (from several slides).

Rousseau, On the Social Contract

University of Texas Gov 314 (38580)/CTI 303 (33895)

Book Prospectus. The Political in Political Economy: from Thomas Hobbes to John Rawls

Political Science 306 Contemporary Democratic Theory Peter Breiner

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

This is not a book of exegesis of Aristotle s political development, nor a contribution to and attempt at

The Kelvingrove Review Issue 2

WS/FCS Unit Planning Organizer

Aristotle and the Scope of Justice

Industrial Society: The State. As told by Dr. Frank Elwell

WS/FCS Unit Planning Organizer

Does The Dao Support Individual Autonomy And Human Rights? Caroline Carr

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

justice, nobility, and other ideas. He was a citizen of Athens, a Greek city-state, and a student of

Transcription:

: An Aristotelian Excursus J. L. At the start of his Nichomachean Ethics, Aristotle declares politics to be the most sovereign and most comprehensive master science (1094a). For contemporary readers this is perhaps an unexpected move, to open a treatise on ethics by discussing politics, but for Aristotle it is at once natural and logical way of talking. Aristotle views all human activities (politics and leisure very much included) as guided by characteristic ends in which they naturally culminate. Differences among these ends are the basis for establishing a hierarchy among human activities. An activity whose characteristic end (telos) is pursued for its own sake has (at least potentially) greater merit or excellence (aretē) than an activity whose characteristic end is only to serve as a means to a different, further end. Greater excellence is associated with pursuit of ends involving the higher and defining human capacities (e.g., Nichomachean Ethics, 1098a). These are, according to Aristotle, the ability to reason and the desire to know (e.g., Metaphysics, 980a; Nichomachean Ethics, 1177a; Politics, 1323b). The excellence of an activity therefore depends on three criteria: first, the form(s) of reason it entails (Nichomachean Ethics, 1098a; on the forms of reason, see Bk. VI generally); second, the ends at which its aims (Nichomachean Ethics, 1177a, 1102a); 1 and third, the extent to which actual reason and actual ends embody their ideal qualities. The ideal is the final cause of the actual, toward which the actual develops naturally if uncorrupted and unimpeded (see Sabine, 1961, ch. 6, esp. pp. 115 122, for nontechnical discussion of this complex issue). The ideal serves, then, as a standard guiding the actual and against which the actual can be assessed. Excellence is a matter not only of purpose but also of success. Intention must be combined with reason, and then carried into effective action. This close linkage of the ideal and the ethical what we might call the normative and the empirical is characteristic of Aristotle s work, not least his political studies. It is in fact the conjunction of human capacities as ideals and as actualities that constitutes politics as a most sovereign and most comprehensive master science. Politics, considered for the moment in their ideal sense, are for Aristotle the pursuit of excellence through the development and refinement of practical reason (praxis). If action based on reason is necessary to achieve excellence (Nichomachean Ethics, 1179a b, 1177a b), the arena for action based on practical reason is the city state (polis, pl. poleis). Aristotle argues that the polis is the highest and most complete human association, in which all other partial associations (e.g., the household, oikos) achieve their fullest realization (Politics, 1252b). Only within the political association formed by polis can the human excellences be most fully developed. This applies particularly to the excellence most characteristic of citizenship, moral and practical wisdom (phronesis). Moral and practical wisdom requires integrating experience with and reflection on the constant and the contingent elements in human activity, a combination that can be achieved only through engagement in the affairs of the polis. The phronimos, the person characterized by moral wisdom who seeks excellence through virtuous activity in the polis, is the highest development of citizenship. For this reason, Aristotle characterizes human beings not only as rational by nature but also as by nature meant to live in a polis (and not, as often thought, simply as political by nature; see Politics, 1253a; see also Nichomachean Ethics, 1170a, 1097b). The civic virtues enabled by political association in the polis generate a specific way of life otherwise impossible. Indeed, Aristotle holds that any being living outside the polis must necessarily be either less or more than human because such a being is either unable to achieve the human excellences or is already so superior as not to need them. The final synthesis (Hamburger, 1951, p. 175) of these excellences made possible by political association in the polis is a complex virtue best labeled felicity (eudaimonia), not to be confused with more ordinary happiness (see Ackrill, 1974). A single act may bring glory and fame, a fortunate series of events may lead to prosperity, but only a lifetime of reflection on and engagement in virtuous action within the polis may culminate in the final and self sufficient virtue of eudaimonia (Nichomachean Ethics, 1097b). It is this fragile telos at which politics in its ideal sense aims. The fragility of virtue, and with it the delicate linkage of the ideal and the actual, is hardly lost on Aristotle. His own tenuous status as a resident noncitizen in Athens would be enough to ensure this. Perhaps 2009 by J. L.. All rights reserved. 1

2 no lesson had been impressed more forcefully on the ancient Greeks than the precariousness of human existence, exhaustively explored in Greek tragic drama while from the Homeric tradition the Greeks knew that As is the generation of leaves, so is that of humanity (Iliad, VI.146). Thucydides s dispassionate history is organized to a significant extent around the increasing distance between a civic ideal and the follies and cruelties in which the Athenians increasingly engaged (see Ober, 1994). 2 Aristotle, then, is not one either to mistake the ideal for the actual or to accept the actual as the limit of the ideal. Grounded in the philosophical principles governing his inquiry as whole, Aristotle s analysis of the polis is also a study of the incessant factional and social strife (stasis) that wracked the Greek poleis. It is in some ways an intervention in that strife. His partisanship is clear. It lies with an aristocracy that would use the independence allowed by landed wealth and social status to cultivate the civic virtues he values most highly. Yet Aristotle understands that even an approximation of this ideal had become increasingly rare. The limits set by nature on the pursuit of wealth (see Politics, 1256b) were more often transgressed as citizens focused more on living, and gratifying their inclinations, than on living well (Politics, 1257b 1258a). If the polis is a form of human association intended to enable the development of the excellences culminating in eudaimonia, how is it that citizens have become more engaged in the excessive pursuit of wealth (pleonexia and chrematistike) and less in the cultivation of moral and practical wisdom (phronesis)? Aristotle searches for the answers by exploring the constitutional structures of the Greek poleis. 3 In Aristotle s conception of politics as a most comprehensive master science, a constitution establishes institutions and procedures but extends beyond these to create in a polis a particular ethos, a characteristic way of life embodying underlying valuations of human activity (see Euben, 1978). The quality of a polis depends on the character generated within this ethos. Since it is the nature of human beings to pursue excellence and since they do so best in a polis, a well-governed polis is defined as one that not only enables its citizens to develop the excellences culminating in eudaimonia but one in which they actually do so (Nichomachean Ethics, 1099b). Aristotle thus focuses his political studies on two questions: first, whether actual constitutions are well or poorly conceived when assessed against this definition; second, what forces corrupt the operation of actual constitutions. He asks, in other words, what traits of character actual constitutions encourage and by what the development of civic excellence is thwarted. In answering this question, Aristotle forges an indissoluble link between politics, leisure, and work. 4 The good citizen (as distinct from the good person) requires a good polis (Politics, 1333b), one in which citizens are free to cultivate excellence. Aristotle therefore regards the provision of leisure to its citizens as a fundamental and generally acknowledged component of any well-governed polis (Politics, 1269a). This is a rather breathtaking claim for late moderns to absorb, so it bears repeating: Provision of leisure for its citizens is necessary if a political association is to be well governed. Aristotle takes the political centrality of leisure quite seriously. Its presence is necessary in a well-governed polis because, according to Aristotle (Politics, 1337b), the right use of leisure is the basis of all our life (Barker translation), the first principle of all action (Jowett), or the first principle of all things (Rackham). It is in the leisure provided by a wellgoverned polis that its citizens have the freedom necessary to develop the human excellences. To whom and how leisure as freedom is provided, and how it is used, are thus fundamental distributive questions in the constitution of any polis, for they determine much about the specific combinations and distributions of virtues that may exist within it. Aristotle cautions that it is far more difficult to answer these questions in practice than in theory (Politics, 1269a) and indeed they are the roots of much political conflict. The freedom Aristotle identifies with leisure (and so often misunderstood in leisure studies) is in the first instance freedom from specific kinds of work. It is thus associated with specific factions in any polis. In ancient Greece the relevant aspect of work was not whether one worked (most Greeks engaged by necessity in some form of work; Ober, 1989, p. 272) or even whether that work was physically strenuous, but whether one worked independently of someone else s control (M. Austin & Vidal-Naquet, 1977, pp. 15 16). One s work was inseparable from one s character. Servile work indicated servile character; to depend on another for one s livelihood was servile. Independent agricultural work on one s own land tended always to be more highly valued, while manual occupations were suspect (Finley, 1981, p. 5). Finance, trade, and manufacturing carried associations with lower social status and were often directed by resident non-citizens. In the end, however, it was the citizen s

3 moral condition, not his economic condition that mattered. Although leisure as a cultural value continued to be elevated above work (Austin & Vidal-Naquet, pp. 16, 151), independent work was not devalued in itself unless it sank into the pursuit of wealth or high profits for their own sake (pp. 11 12, 13; see also Balme, 1984; Wood, 1988). Aristotle s evaluations of work run counter to this cultural tradition and have aristocratic political implications. The freedom in leisure to be provided by the polis was not from a general necessity to labor (Barker) but from the necessity to work at menial occupations (Rackham) or from the necessity of providing for one s daily wants (Jowett). Such freedom is necessary for the development of virtuous character because, as Aristotle makes plain in his Rhetoric, it is not noble to practice any sordid craft, since it is a mark of a free man not to live at another s beck and call (1367a). The distributive question raised by Aristotle regarding the provision of leisure in the well-governed polis is also about the distribution of work, and thus of the burdens associated with undesirable yet necessary forms of work. In the context of ancient Greece, these burdens were borne not only by slaves, the practice of slavery being widely accepted, but also by ostensibly free citizens. 5 The internal logic of Aristotle s argument forces a confrontation with the moral and political consequences of the distribution of work and leisure within the political association. His conception of the well being necessary for the development of excellence through virtuous action is not austere; it assumes a certain minimum threshold material security has been crossed (Politics, 1256b, 1257b 1258a; Nichomachean Ethics, 1099a). Citizens must be furnished with the conditions with the conditions of virtuous action (Barker, 1959, p. 285) in order to eliminate threats posed by material want to the cultivation of excellence. Although not requiring wealth as such, this threshold does exceed the level of material resources available to most citizens in ancient Greece. The political consequence is that the supposed burdens of menial occupations and of practicing a sordid craft are imposed unevenly within the citizenry of a polis, with the further moral consequence that those on whom these burdens are imposed are precluded from developing precisely the excellences of character their work frees more fortunate citizens to cultivate. This character is indifferent to the necessity or usefulness of such work. Whatever the criteria for citizenship imposed by the constitution or institutional support for political participation (e.g., pay for jury duty, attending the assembly, or holding administrative office; see Finley, 1981, pp. 58, 86; Hignett, 1952, pp. 215 221; Ostwald, 1986, passim; de Ste Croix, 1975), of more importance to Aristotle is the distribution of leisure s privileges and work s burdens (which lies at the heart of his political sociology ; see Ober, 1991). It is this distribution that determines who within the citizenry will actually be able to engage in the virtuous activity leading to excellence of character. There is nothing inevitable for Aristotle about the achievement of excellence. Although it is an ideal toward which human beings by their nature tend, actual excellence depends on the arena created for human activity by a polis through its constitutional institutions and procedures. His analysis of actual constitutions is intended to reveal which in fact do so. A polis must not only provide leisure but also properly educate its citizens for its right use, that is, for virtuous action (Nichomachean Ethics, 1094a, 1099b; Politics, 1333a, 1338a). Aristotle understands that the actual educations citizens receive and the uses to which they are put often destroy precisely those excellences ideally developed in leisure. He condemns such failure in the strongest terms, arguing that a special measure of moral shame falls to those who fail to use leisure rightly (Politics, 1334a). To have access to the goods of life but not to employ them in virtuous action is a profound moral failure, a weakness of character that destroys both polis and citizen. Thus it is, for example, that the Spartans, bred and reared as warriors whose iron discipline made them feared and admired throughout ancient Greece, were defeated not by an enemy in war but by the deterioration of their own character in the peace their strength had won them. The Spartan ethos created fortitude and strength, yet had no place for politics unconstrained by war, a politics of citizens rather than warriors. The Spartans, writes Aristotle (Politics, 1271b), were defeated by leisure.

4 Notes 1. Contradictions within Aristotle s discussions of the types of reason and their values, most famously between Bk. X of the Nichomachean Ethics and the remainder of that work and the Politics, have generated endless debate. See, e.g., Ackrill (1974; 1981, ch. 10), Kraut (1989), Rorty (1980), and Stocks (1939). For discussion of this issue in relation to Aristotle s conception of leisure, see (1988). 2. The Thucydidean Pericles s boast that in Athens whoever takes no part in politics is regarded neither as retiring or unambitious, but as useless (II.40) reflects this ideal. The nature, extent, and content of political participation in the historical Athens (the polis about which we know most) remain, however, subject to considerable disagreement. Actual participation seems likely to have varied considerably and seldom to have conformed to the ideals as presented either by the Athenians themselves or by their later admirers. For critical assessments, see (among others in a vast literature) Ober, 1989; and Sinclair, 1988, ch. 5.2. See also Carter, 1986; and Saxonhouse, 1996. This is the place to note that the average citizen (who was quite different from the average resident, being an adult native male required to verify his legitimate descent at least from a citizen father and often from a native mother as well) probably participated less frequently in the central government and administration of his polis and more often in smaller districts or neighborhoods (see Whitehead, 1986). 3. The ancient Greeks had a well-developed constitutional tradition, grounded in codes of law and long established custom. For discussions of the Greek constitutional tradition, see Hignett, 1952; Hansen, 1983, 1991; Ober, 1996; Ostwald, 1969, 1986; Sealey, 1987; Shaw, 1991. Aristotle and his students collected the constitutions of something like 158 poleis. The sole remaining text is the Constitution of Athens, more probably written by a student than by Aristotle himself. The Politics includes findings from this research project. 4. Sylvester has recently (1999) called attention to the importance of analyzing work if we are to understand more fully classical and modern conceptions of leisure. By emphasizing how these conceptions are embedded in specific historical contexts entailing social values with specific political implications, Sylvester provides a useful correction to the occasionally overly enthusiastic appreciations of classical leisure found in leisure studies. 5. The practice of slavery is a haunting presence in any discussion of ancient Greece, not least in considering Aristotle s conceptualization of leisure. He takes it as axiomatic that some people have characters by nature fit for nothing more than slavery (Politics, 1255a); this cavalier view is extreme even for the Greeks. Although the full extent of slavery is strenuously debated, this much seems clear. First, slavery existed and was important particularly in the wealthier poleis, including Athens. Second, slaves tended to be non-greeks except for those Greeks taken captive in war or enslaved as punishment (e.g., for nonpayment of debts, but note that debt slavery was banned in Athens by Solon s reforms). Third, slave and free labor coexisted side by side in almost all spheres of ancient Greek work (see, e.g., Hansen, 1991, p. 62 63) except for the most brutal, from which free citizens were excluded (e.g., the Athenian silver mines), or the most sensitive, from which slaves and (in general) non-citizens were barred (e.g., the military). Interestingly, slaves were employed in the Athenian police force, including those who dragged the famous red-painted rope through the agora to drive citizens to the assembly. The grounds for this seem to have been that it was degrading for one citizen to lay his hands forcefully on another citizen. Fourth, the aristocratic ideal could not become actuality without the presence of slave labor, nor should the importance of resident non-citizens (the metics) in trade and commerce be forgotten. There can be no doubt that living well as Aristotle conceives it depends on slavery as well as the submissive labor of non-aristocratic citizens. For discussions of slavery in ancient Greece, see Finley, 1981, pp. 97 100; Jameson, 1977/78; Martin, 1996, pp. 65 66; de Ste Croix, 1981; Wood, 1983.

5 References Ackrill, J. L. (1974). Aristotle on eudaimonia. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Aristotle. (1941). Metaphysics (W. Ross, Trans.). In R. McKeon (Ed.), The basic works of Aristotle (pp. 682 926). New York: Random House. Aristotle. (1944). Politics (H. Rackham, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Aristotle. (1948). Politics (E. Barker, Ed.) (corrected ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Aristotle. (1984). Nichomachean ethics (W. D. Ross & J. O. Urmson, Trans.). In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (Vol. 2, pp. 1729 1867). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Aristotle. (1984). Politics (B. Jowett, Trans.). In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (Vol. 2, pp. 1986 2129). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Austin, M. M., & Vidal-Naquet, P. (1977). Economic and social history of ancient Greece: An introduction (M. M. Austin, Trans.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Balme, M. (1984). Attitudes to work and leisure in ancient Greece. Greece and Rome, 33, 140 152. Barker, E. (1959). The social and political thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Dover Publications. (Original work published 1906) Carter, L. B. (1986). The quiet Athenian. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Euben, J. P. (1978). Political equality and the Greek polis. In M. J. G. McGrath (Ed.), Liberalism and the modern polity (pp. 207 228). New York: Marcel Dekker. Finley, M. I. (1981). Economy and society in ancient Greece. New York: The Viking Press. Hamburger, M. (1951). Morals and law: The growth of Aristotle's legal theory. New Haven: Yale University Press. Hansen, M. H. (1983). The Athenian ecclesia. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press. Hansen, M. H. (1991). The Athenian democracy in the age of Demosthenes (J. A. Crook, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell., J. L. (1988). Leisure and civility: Reflections on a Greek ideal. Leisure Sciences, 10, 179 191. Hignett, C. (1952). A history of the Athenian constitution. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Homer. (1951). The Iliad (R. Lattimore, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Jameson, M. (1977 78). Agriculture and slavery in ancient Greece. Classical Journal, 73, 122 145. Kraut, R. (1989). Aristotle on the human good. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Martin, T. R. (1996). Ancient Greece: From prehistoric to hellenistic times. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Ober, J. (1989). Mass and elite in democratic Athens: Rhetoric, ideology, and the power of the people. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Ober, J. (1991). Aristotle's political sociology: Class, status, and order in the Politics. In C. Lord & D. O'Connor (Eds.), Essays in the foundations of Aristotelian political science (pp. 112 135). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Ober, J. (1994). Civic ideology and counterhegemonic discourse: Thucydides on the Sicilian Debate. In A. L. Boegehold & A. C. Scafuro (Eds.), Athenian identity and civic ideology (pp. 102 126). Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Ostwald, M. (1969). Nomos and the beginnings of Athenian democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ostwald, M. (1986). From popular sovereignty to the sovereignty of law: Law, society, and politics in fifth-century Athens. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

6 Rorty, A. O. (Ed.). (1980). The place of contemplation in Aristotle s Nichomachean Ethics. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), Essays on Aristotle's ethics (pp. 377 94). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Sabine, G. H. (1961). A history of political theory (3rd ed.). New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Saxonhouse, A. W. (1996). Athenian democracy: Modern mythmakers and ancient theorists. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Sealey, R. (1987). The Athenian republic: Democracy or rule of law? University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press. Shaw, B. (1991). The paradoxes of people power. Helios, 18, 194 214. Sinclair, R. K. (1988). Democracy and participation in Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ste Croix, G. E. M., de. (1975). Political pay outside Athens. Classical Quarterly, 25, 48 52. Ste Croix, G. E. M., de. (1981). The class struggle in the ancient Greek world. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Stocks, J. L. (1939). Schole. In Reason and intuition, and other essays (D. M. Emmet, Ed.) (pp. 181 187). London: Oxford University Press. Sylvester, C. D. (1999). The classical ideal of leisure: Cultural ideal or class prejudice? Leisure Sciences, 21, 3 16. Thucydides. (1993). History of the Peloponnesian War (W. R. Connor, Ed.; R. Crawley, Trans.). London: Everyman/J. M. Dent. Whitehead, D. (1986). The demes of Attic 508/7 ca. 250 B.C.: A political and social study. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Wood, E. M. (1983). Agricultural slavery in classical Athens. American Journal of Ancient History, 8, 1 47. Wood, E. M. (1988). Peasant-citizen and slave: The foundations of Athenian democracy. London: Verso.