The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

Similar documents
Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

John Rawls. Cambridge University Press John Rawls: An Introduction Percy B. Lehning Frontmatter More information

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

The character of public reason in Rawls s theory of justice

A THEORY OF JUSTICE. Revised Edition JOHN RAWLS

Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy I

VI. Rawls and Equality

Business Ethics Journal Review

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Public Reason and Political Justifications

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Distributive vs. Corrective Justice

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Individualism. Marquette University. John B. Davis Marquette University,

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

University of Alberta

The Morality of Conflict

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

The Rawlsian way of doing history of political philosophy

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

The Social Contract Class Syllabus

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

Social Contract Theory

Justice as fairness The social contract

Book Prospectus. The Political in Political Economy: from Thomas Hobbes to John Rawls

(Draft paper please let me know if you want to circulate or quote)

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice Lecture 4: Rawls and liberal equality

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

Democratic Rights and the Choice of Economic Systems

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

Theories of Social Justice

IMPARTIAL JUSTICE: CONDITIONS AND IMPLICATIONS

Rawls and Deliberative Democracy. Michael Saward

Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question *

The Tyranny or the Democracy of the Ideal?

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

John Rawls ( )

In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Phil 115, May 25, 2007 Justice as fairness as reconstruction of the social contract

SOCIAL JUSTICE AND THE MORAL JUSTIFICATION OF A MARKET SOCIETY

Western Philosophy of Social Science

The political problem of economic inequality and the perils of redistribution.

The London School of Economics and Political Science. A Critique of Pure Public Reason. Esha Senchaudhuri

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Jeppe von Platz. Curriculum Vitae

Rawls, Reasonableness, and International Toleration

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

The (Many) Models of Rawls and Harsanyi

Social Justice and Democracy

MGT610 2 nd Quiz solved by Masoodkhan before midterm spring 2012

Jeppe von Platz. Curriculum Vitae

A Rawlsian Idea of Deliberative Democracy

The Original Position

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Key words: basic liberties; social basis of self-respect; theory of justice.

Kant and Rawls on Rights and International Relations. Faseeha Sheriff. Thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies

Policy & precarity what are people able to do and be? Helen Taylor Cardiff Metropolitan

Experimental Computational Philosophy: shedding new lights on (old) philosophical debates

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

The Importance of Philosophy: Reflections on John Rawls. In spring 1974, I was 22 years old, and a first-year graduate student in the

MAIN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ISSUES IN THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

John Rawls: anti-foundationalism, deliberative democracy, and cosmopolitanism

Towards a Global Civil Society. Daniel Little University of Michigan-Dearborn

On a Moral Right to Civil Disobedience

The Democracy/ Contractualism Analogy

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

Chapter 4. Justice and the Law. Justice vs. Law. David Hume. Justice does not dictate a perfect world, but one in which people live up

Meena Krishnamurthy a a Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Associate

Political Obligation 3

STEVEN WALL. Associate Professor. Department of Philosophy, University of Connecticut (2008 to 2010)

Two Models of Equality and Responsibility

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held

4AANB006 Political Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year

Political Liberalism and Its Feminist Potential. Elizabeth Edenberg

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Transcription:

University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 2017 The Jeppe von Platz University of Richmond, jplatz@richmond.edu Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.richmond.edu/philosophy-facultypublications Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Von Platz, Jeppe. "The." In The SAGE Encyclopedia of Political Behavior, edited by Fathali M.. Moghaddam, 889-92. Los Angeles, CA: Sage Reference., 2017. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact scholarshiprepository@richmond.edu.

889 have no knowledge about particular facts that could lead them to prefer principles of justice partial to those they represent. The veil of ignorance is thus an important part of Rawls's argument that his conception of justice-justice as fairness-is the best conception for a democratic society. The OriginalPosition VEIL OF IGNORANCEIN RAWLSIANTHEORY As part of his effort to answer the question "What is the best conception of justice for a democratic society?" philosopher John Rawls constructed a thought experiment called the original position. In the original position, representatives of members of society choose principles of justice for society in light of limited interests and with limited information. Situated behind the veil of ignorance, the parties in the original position Taking a closer look at the terms of Rawls's question provides a number of clues to its answer. From a closer look at the idea of justice, we get ideas of the role, subject, circumstances, and formal constraints of justice. From a closer look at the idea of a democratic society, we get the ideas of social cooperation between free and equal citizens, reciprocity, and fairness. The best conception of justice for a democratic society is the conception of justice that best satisfies and expresses these many ideas. Different conceptions of justice do better at satisfying different ideas; some better satisfy the formal constraints of justice-generality, publicity, and stability-while others do better at capturing the notions of fairness, reciprocity, and equality. How can we find a way to rank candidate conceptions of justice that allows us to say that one of these does better than the rest at satisfying and expressing these ideas? Rawls's answer to the problem of how to rank conceptions of justice is the original position. The original position is constructed to turn the scatter of ideas about justice for a democratic society into a device that ranks conceptions of justice according to how well they satisfy and express them. In this manner, the original position models what we generally believe and hope for when we think about justice for a democratic society-in other words, our normative beliefs on this subject. The original position is inspired by the social contract tradition. In this tradition, the legitimacy and obligating power of political authority stems from the wills of those who are subjected to it as their will either was or could be expressed in a social contract. The social contract tradition draws on two powerful strands in Western moral philosophy: first, the principle that no person has natural authority over another person and that interpersonal coercion, therefore, is permissible only when exercised according to reasons acceptable to the coerced; second, that consent and promises carry obligation: if I voluntarily consent to some agreement, then this consent creates new rights and obligations. If we bring these two ideas together, we get the idea that all political authority must be generated by the acts of those party to the authority

890 relation-in short, by people coming together in a social contract in which they agree to create and respect political authority that legislates and enforces laws on behalf of all. Rawls draws on the social contract tradition, but the ranking of principles of justice that issue from the original position is not a social contract. The original position is a thought experiment that helps us think clearly about what justice requires. The hypothetical agreement of the original position is not the source of political authority or political obligation-it does not produce laws and institutions or any agreement to obey laws and institutions. Instead, Rawls's contractualism is found in his endorsement of the liberal principle of legitimacy, which says that the exercise of political authority must take place in accordance with principles that all those subjected to it could agree to in a situation that respects their status as free and equal moral persons. The original position helps us identify what these principles are and shows what we can agree to as free and equal moral persons. The aim of the original position is to answer the question: What is the best conception of justice for a democratic society? It does so by modeling what we already believe about justice and democratic society. The original position is not meant to introduce any additional materials into the argument but to take the materials we already have at hand and use them to construct a way to make clear what they imply. In a sense, the original position is simply a device that helps us think through our commitments and considered convictions about democratic society and be clear about what we already believe.. In the_tho~ght experiment that is the original position, we 1magme that representatives of all members of s?ciety come together and choose a conception of justice that those they represent will live by. The parties are given a list of candidate conceptions and rank them by running a pairwise comparison-a is better than B but C is better than A, and so on-until they hav; a_rrived~t a_de~inite order. The highest-ranking conception of Justice ts the best one for a democratic society. The original position, accordingly, plays an epistemic role in Rawls 's argument for principles of justice: it helps us think about what justice requires. Further, the force of the original position argument is a function of the force of the assumptions that go into it. If Rawls has identified the right ideas about justice for a democratic society, and if these ideas are well expressed in the original position, and if the parties would prefer justice as fairness to any other candidate conception of justice, then we can confidently say that justice as fairness is the best conception of justice for a democratic society. The Veil of Ignorance The original position models our beliefs about justice for a democratic society by defining the knowledge and interests of the parties and by requiring that all candidate conceptions of justice satisfy the formal constraints of the concept of right. The veil of ignorance defines the knowledge of the parties; it shields them from knowledge of particular facts that they could use to favor particular members of society while at the same time allowing them knowledge of general facts that are helpful for thinking about justice in general. The veil of ignorance thus expresses a commitment to a sort of imparti ality that is needed to ensure that the principles we select express our commitments to fairness and equal citizenship. To ensure this impartiality, the veil of ignorance shields the parties from knowledge about the people they represent: about their gender, race, religious beliefs, wealth, and similar facts. The parties are also ignorant of particular facts about the society those they represent live in, such as how religious beliefs are distributed, what natural resources their society has access to, and the distribution of wealth and opportunities. While the veil of ignorance shields the parties from knowledge that could lead them to propose unfair terms of social cooperation, it lets them know enough about the general conditions of democratic societies to rank candidate conceptions of justice. So the parties know that those they represent have a conception of the good (but not what it is); they know general facts about human needs and psychology; that they are in circumstances of justice (where social cooperation is both necessary and possible); they know theories of sociology and economics and that their society contains a plurality of philosophical, religious, political, and social doctrines. That the veil of ignorance leaves the parties without any knowledge about the interests of those they repre~en~or even about the distribution of interests in society mv~tes.the question of how they can rank conceptions of Justice-for what interests do they have that could lead them to have preferences between different candidate conceptions? Interestsof the Parties:PrimaryGoods Rawls's answer is that the parties know that those they represent have some conception of the good, that circumstances of justice are present, and what the general needs of human beings are. In light of this knowledge the parties will try to procure for those they represen; certain all-purpose means that are generally needed by members of a democratic society. Rawls calls these all-purpose means primary goods.

The primary goods serve three general interests of democratic citizens: first, their interest in developing their capacity for a conception of the good (their first moral power); second, their interest in developing their capacity for a sense of justice (their second moral power); and, third, their interest in having adequate allpurpose means for pursuing their conception of the good-no matter what it is. This account of the three basic interests of democratic citizenship supports the following list of primary goods: 1. Basic rights and liberties 2. Freedom of movement and free choice of occupation 3. Power and prerogatives and opportunities for access to positions and offices 4. Income and wealth 5. The social bases of self-respect The parties are interested in securing for those they represent basic rights and liberties necessary for the development of their moral powers; opportunities for access to offices and positions; and as large a share of income and wealth as they can get. Note that the parties are "mutually disinterested": they care only to maximize the position of those they represent without regard for the position of others. This mutual disinterestedness expresses their equal claim to the fruits of cooperation and a rejection of envy as indicator of injustice. The fact that others have more than oneself is not a reason to suspect injustice in the system-what matters is whether the distribution wherein they have more (or less) arose from fair cooperation. If the system of rules (the basic structure) is just, then the fact that others have more than oneself offers no reason for complaint. The parties also are interested in choosing a conception of justice that can be stable, meaning that it generates its own support over time. If, for example, a conception of justice tends to create distrust or resentment among citizens, this undermines its ability to support a stable system of institutions-in effect, making it harder to have a society that is ordered by this conception of justice-and this then counts as a reason against this conception. The Limited Usefulness of the Veil of Ignorance There is no actual situation like the original position. The original position is not some legislative assembly that might happen or could have happened. The veil of 891 ignorance is not something that we could create in the real world (and even if we could, it is not clear why we would do it). Again, the original position is a thought experiment with imaginary characters that think about justice using only knowledge and interests relevant for the question-this could not happen. It is better to think of the original position as a device that sorts conceptions of justice according to how well they fit the basic ideas of democratic society and democratic citizenship than as a bargaining situation in which parties negotiate for principles. That the original position and the veil of ignorance it employs are hypothetical, imaginary, and impossible is not an objection to it. If it truly expresses the fundamental normative commitments of democratic society and helps us sort candidate conceptions of justice according to how well they satisfy these commitments, then it is useful for thinking clearly about justice for a democratic society. Since the veil of ignorance models ideas about justice and not a particular view of human nature or human psychology, it is supposed to stand free of commitments to any particular metaphysics of personhood-for example, that people were or were not created by God-and particular theories of personal or collective psychology. Instead, the view of the person that informs the original position and the veil of ignorance is normative: the veil of ignorance is constructed from ideals of democratic citizenship and democratic society. These ideals do, of course, suppose certain facts about human nature, human society, and human psychology-that we have needs, that we are modestly rational, that we are social creatures, that we are in circumstances of justice and thus can cooperate with others on fair terms-but the original position and the veil of ignorance are not directly modeling these assumptions. Instead, the veil of ignorance models only the point of view relevant for thinking about justice for a democratic society, and the intent, at least, is that this can be done without assuming any controversial metaphysics of personhood or theory of individual or political psychology. Rawls's veil of ignorance is designed to deal with a specific question: What is the best conception of justice for a democratic society? It is a mistake to think that the same veil would be helpful for answering other questions. If one wants to investigate justice in the workplace, or family, or environmental justice, one could construct an original position with a veil of ignorance suitable to these aims (just as Rawls designed another veil for the original position relevant to international justice), but the veil of ignorance that Rawls designed for the case of domestic justice should not be used for these questions. Again, in Rawlsian theory, the original position with its veil of ignorance and interests of the

892 Voter Disenfranchisement parties are constructed from the particular question that it helps us answer-to use it for other questions is to misunderstand what it is and does. Other Veils By limiting the knowledge of the parties in the original position, the veil of ignorance expresses an ideal of impartiality. As such, it stands in a long tradition of similar notions and thought experiments such as Bishop Butler's court of conscience, Adam Smith's impartial spectator, David Hume's judicious spectator, and Immanuel Kant's standpoint of pure practical reason. The idea of taking an impartial perspective-and of limiting the first-personal preferences as a way of securing impartiality-has been perfected in utilitarian ethics, where the moral point of view is one that counts the subjective well-being of all persons equally. Though neither used the same name as Rawls, John Harsanyi developed a utilitarian version of a veil of ignorance in the 1950s, and Friedrich August von Hayek used a similar device in his derivation of principles of justice in the Constitution of Liberty, published in 1960. Rawls did not invent the veil of ignorance; rather, he appropriated and adapted an available idea. A utilitarian veil of ignorance allows the parties complete information about their society, including the preferences of individual members of society, but deprives them of information about what position they occupy (or the position of those they represent). The result is that they choose principles that maximize average utility. Such a utilitarian veil of ignorance is thinner than the one employed by Rawls because it allows the parties more information. Other theories of justice might defend a thicker veil of ignorance than the one employed by Rawls. For example, if one believes that justice should not be influenced by general facts about human psychology, then the veil should shield the parties from these facts ( Gerald A. Cohen and others who share his views on the nature of justice could go in this direction). Deliberate democrats might follow Jurgen Habermas and argue that debates about politics should take place with full information. These disagreements about the thickness of the veil of ignorance express underlying disagreements about the nature of justice-about what question we are using the veil of ignorance to answer and of the assumptions within the question. Utilitarians and socialists would not be persuaded by Rawls's original-position arguments, for they would reject his characterization of the veil of ignorance (and perhaps also of the interests of the parties), but this simply shows that their assumptions about justice differ. Again, the veil of ignorance, and the original position more generally, only work as arguments for the principles of justice as fairness for those who accept that Rawls has identified both the right question and the assumptions built into the question and that these are properly expressed by the original position. Different arguments are needed to show that the question, assumptions, and construction are as Rawls saw them. Perhaps disappointingly, the veil of ignorance in Rawlsian theory only works as an argument for those already committed to the basic assumptions of Rawlsian liberalism, and it cannot serve as an independent argument against utilitarianism, socialism, or other theories of justice that do not accept these assumptions. Jeppe von Platz See also Citizenship; Democracy; Distributive Justice; Equality of Opportunity; Liberalism; Political Deliberation; Procedural Justice; Social Contract Further Readings Cohen G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Freeman, S. (2007). Rawls. London, England: Routledge. Habermas, J. (1995). Reconciliation through the public use of reason: Remarks on John Rawls's political liberalism. Journal of Philosophy, 92(3), 109-131. Harsanyi, J.C. (1953). Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risk-taking. Journal of Political Economy, 61(5), 434-435. Harsanyi, J.C. (1955). Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy, 63(4), 309-321. Hayek, F. A. V. (1960). The constitution of liberty. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Mandie, J., & Reidy, D. (2014). The Cambridge Rawls lexicon. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Rawls, J. (2001). The law of peoples: With "the idea of public reason revisited." Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2005). Political liberalism (Expanded ed.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Rawls, J., & Freeman, S. (Eds.). (2001). Collected papers (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J., & Kelly, E. (Eds.). (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.