MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY

Similar documents
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

Two concepts of equality before the law

Congressional Investigations:

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Social and Political Philosophy

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Lighted Athletic Fields, Public Opinion, and the Tyranny of the Majority

Direct Voting in Normative Democratic Theories

Subverting the Orthodoxy

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged

John Stuart Mill ( ) Branch: Political philosophy ; Approach: Utilitarianism Over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Consequentialist Ethics

Relationship between Islam world and Democracy. Jafar Kabiri Sarmazdeh 1 davod kiany (ph.d) 2

Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism. Dr. Clea F. Rees. Centre for Lifelong Learning Cardiff University.

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION. 1.1 Introduction to Citizenship

Phil 115, May 25, 2007 Justice as fairness as reconstruction of the social contract

Regional Autonomies and Federalism in the Context of Internal Self-Determination

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Freedom in a Democratic Society

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

The Enlightenment. European thinkers developed new ideas about government and society during the Enlightenment.

Direct Democracy. A philosophical point of view. 11 April 2016

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Political Culture in America

Andrew Blowers There is basically then, from what you re saying, a fairly well defined scientific method?

The State of the Union under a failed Constitution. June 14, 1997

In my brief presentation I would like to touch upon some basic liberal principles and link

Teacher lecture (background material and lecture outline provided); class participation activity; and homework assignment.

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Political Norms and Moral Values

Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers )

ENTRENCHMENT. Wealth, Power, and the Constitution of Democratic Societies PAUL STARR. New Haven and London

THE ARITHMETIC OF VOTING

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice.

A-Level POLITICS PAPER 3

Part III Presidential Republics: Their Past and Their Future Introduction

Chapter 1 Sociological Theory Chapter Summary

preserving individual freedom is government s primary responsibility, even if it prevents government from achieving some other noble goal?

1. Why has the official tolerance for corruption declined during the past decade, in so many countries and institutions around the world?

NATIONAL HEARING QUESTIONS ACADEMIC YEAR

REDEMPTION, FAITH AND THE POST-CIVIL WAR AMENDMENT PARADOX: THE TALK

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

Political Parties. The drama and pageantry of national political conventions are important elements of presidential election

Key Questions. Organization. Federalist Papers: Institutions, policy-making, and the public interest

The Enlightenment & Democratic Revolutions. Enlightenment Ideas help bring about the American & French Revolutions

Phil 232: Philosophy and Multiculturalism spring 14 Charles Taylor, The Politics of Recognition (sections I and II)

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

Submission to the Independent Media Inquiry

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here?

Constitutional Democracy and World Politics: A Response to Gartzke and Naoi

Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures*

Is democracy the best form of government? By Leo Rogers

STATE HEARING QUESTIONS

Voting Criteria April

Why Government? Activity, pg 1. Name: Page 8 of 26

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

Chapter One ONE REPUBLIC TWO AMERICAS? Copyright 2014 Cengage Learning

Lecture 17 Consequentialism. John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism Mozi Impartial Caring

Chapter 1, Governments. What is government? Why governments exist Types of governments

KAI DRAPER. The suggestion that there is a proportionality restriction on the right to defense is almost

Why. Government? What are the pros & cons of a government? Why do we need one? What is it for? Could we do without?

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

Quong on Proportionality in Self-defense and the Stringency Principle

Chapter 5. The State

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

119 Book Reviews/Comptes Rendus

The Madisonian System

AMBASSADOR THOMAS R. PICKERING DECEMBER 9, 2010 Subcommittee on the Constitution, Civil Rights, and Civil Liberties of the House Committee on the

RESPONSIBILITIES OF LAND-GRANT UNIVERSITIES IN PUBLIC AFFAIRS EDUCATION

Ohio High School We the People State Hearing Questions

Harry S. Truman Inaugural Address Washington, D.C. January 20, 1949

Utilitarianism Revision Help Pack

CAMBRIDGE IELTS 4 - TEST 4 - READING

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

n Where Democracy is Unsuitable n Who Should & Should Not Vote n Subsidiarity: A Way Forward? n Problems of Bureaucracy n Role of the State

Constitutional Self-Government: A Reply to Rubenfeld

CHAPTER 2 -Defining and Debating America's Founding Ideals What are America's founding ideals, and why are they important?

Chapter 14. Constitutions, the Law and Judiciaries

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of

John Stuart Mill. Table&of&Contents& Politics 109 Exam Study Notes

answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice

Bioethics: Autonomy and Health (Fall 2012) Laura Guidry-Grimes

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in a paragraph. (25 points total)

Immigration and freedom of movement

During the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, the. Book Review. The Captured Economy: How the Powerful WINTER 2017 VOL. 20 N O.

Planning for Immigration

CHAPTER 2: MAJORITARIAN OR PLURALIST DEMOCRACY

Lysander Spooner, An Essay on the Trial by Jury (1852) 1

AMY GUTMANN: THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES DOES GUTMANN SUCCEED IN SHOWING THE CONSTRUCTIVE POTENTIAL OF COMMUNITARIAN VALUES?

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

CAPACITY-BUILDING FOR ACHIEVING THE MIGRATION-RELATED TARGETS

EUROPEISKA KONVENTET SEKRETARIATET. Bryssel den 27 februari 2003 (28.2) (OR. en) CONV 585/03 CONTRIB 261 FÖLJENOT

ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE

Transcription:

MAJORITARIAN DEMOCRACY AND CULTURAL MINORITIES Bernard Boxill Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe ONE OF THE MAJOR CRITICISMS of majoritarian democracy is that it sometimes involves the totalitarianism of the majority over the minorities. This problem is even more pronounced if a minority is a permanent minority, that is, if it is not a case where minority is based on issues which may differ from time to time. For instance, one may be in a minority group regarding the issue of whether to increase taxes but may be in the majority when it comes to the issue of whether to resurface the freeway. The contemporary American philosopher Bernard Boxill explores this issue about majoritarian democracy in relation to a culturally plural society where one cultural group is a majority and other cultural groups are minorities. He argues that cultural ties may lead to a majority joining together as a way to secure their interest against the interest of the minority, in which case we may find a situation where the cultural majority imposes their values and ways of life on the minority such that the minority is not given equal opportunity to participate in government. Boxill argues that democracy has tried to prevent the tyranny of the majority by guaranteeing certain rights in a constitutional system, which can be changed only by an overwhelming majority that one cultural group may not be able to amass on an issue. He argues this may be unsatisfactory because although the majority may not be able to violate such basic rights, the majority may only tolerate the minorities but may not allow them to flourish. Boxill extends Mill s argument that in order for a true representative democracy to exist there must be adequate representation of all groups in a legislative body, including minorities. Boxill argues that it is not simply enough to give voting rights to minorities if such voting rights do not ensure the ability of the minority group to flourish. In order for a group to flourish they must have representatives who make public policies which will ensure that the minority groups are able to flourish. This point assumes that given the cultural ties that bind the majority, their representatives will be reluctant to make policies that will allow the minorities to flourish. It is more likely that a representative who shares a cultural affinity with the minorities will understand the kind of policies that will help the minorities to flourish. He

suggests that one alternative way to ensure that a minority gets a representative since such representation requires majority vote is for the minority to segregate so that they can pull their votes together to form a majority vote. This suggestion, Boxill argues, is unsatisfactory because it may involve the use of coercion to make people move or prevent people from moving to an area. This is unfair and may lead to conflict. Boxill argues that it is reasonable and perhaps in the interest of the majority to give representation to minorities because they may be able to contribute something that the majority may not be able to contribute. Boxill draws on Mill s argument for proportional representation and the idea that every idea or view be given a voice because you never know where the best idea may come from. All cultures may have something to offer regarding the best way to live. Adequate participation is best captured and achieved by allowing everyone to bring forth their view for critical examination. He argues that cultures are experiments in living. Giving opportunities to all cultures in terms of allowing them to have representatives is a way to critically evaluate the ideas that each culture has to offer. Such opportunity will be helpful to all because a culture may learn from another a better way of living, which will then culminate in that culture s making improvements in their view about how human beings should live. This may be a way to get a number of ideas that legislators can synthesize into the best laws or public policies. Boxill concludes by suggesting that one way to prevent the totalitarianism of a majority culture in a culturally plural society is to have proportional representation, where minorities cultures are represented in proportion to their numbers such that the need for segregation does not arise. He suggests that a single transferable vote system may be a good way to start in order to avoid the problem of majoritarianism in a culturally plural society. As you read Boxill, consider and reflect on the following questions: In what way does majority rule imply the totalitarianism of the majority? How can proportional representation help to avoid a situation where the majority dominates the minorities? Why is it always important to consider the views of minority cultures?

The classic problem of majoritarian democracy is that it enables the majority to tyrannize minorities. This problem is less serious if different majorities tend to form on different issues, for in that case no minority is likely to be a permanent minority. It is more serious in culturally plural societies where one of the cultural groups is an absolute majority. The cultural ties binding the members of such a majority will incline them to stand together on many different issues, to use the principle of majority rule to secure their interests at the expense of the minority cultures, and to impose their values and way of life on them. Members of the majority culture may claim that they should be free to impose their values and way of life on minorities. To support this claim they may appeal to the dangers of culturally plural societies and to the benefits of culturally homogeneous societies. Culturally plural societies are said to be prone to murderous conflict, and culturally homogeneous societies are said to contribute to community, fraternity, and a sense of belonging. But even if these claims are true, a cultural majority may act wrongly in imposing its values and way of life on cultural minorities. People may have rights to retain their culture and to pass it on to their children, which forbid their forcible acculturation, even if that would make the society culturally homogeneous and a better society. Democracies have standardly tried to solve the problem of the tyranny of the majority by enshrining certain rights in a constitution that can be changed only by an overwhelming majority. This device can be applied to the particular problem of a majority culture trying to impose its values and way of life on minorities. But it is not altogether satisfactory. For one thing, even rights enshrined in a constitution can be revoked if the majority that wants them revoked is large and determined enough. More importantly, the device only forces the majority to tolerate minorities. It may prevent a majority from violating minorities most basic interests, but it need not give minorities opportunity to flourish or to contribute to the society. In this essay I develop this objection to majoritarian democracy and suggest briefly one possible solution to the problem it points to. I begin with the argument that the usual rights enshrined in the Constitution for the protection of minorities need not give them an opportunity to flourish. My argument is based on an argument proposed by Mill in Representative Government. In that book Mill argued that true democracy Majoritarian Democracy and Cultural Minorities, by Bernard Boxill, from Multiculturalism and American Democracy, University of Kansas Press, 1998, pp. 112 119.

required provisions to ensure that minorities were represented in the legislative body. Since the usual systems of majoritarian rule keep minorities out of the legislative body, Mill called them false democracy and argued that their inevitable consequence was the complete disfranchisement of minorities even if they had the vote. 1 Mill s conclusion is too strong. Although he was right that the usual systems of majoritarian rule do not ensure that minorities are represented in legislative bodies, he was wrong to conclude that they lead to the disfranchisement of minorities. People are not disfranchised because their favorite candidate for office is not elected, they are disfranchised when their right to vote is violated; but the usual systems of majoritarian rule guarantee minorities the right to vote. Still, there is something to Mill s complaint about majoritarian democracy. Part of this, I argue, is that majoritarian democracy may not give cultural minorities an equal opportunity to flourish. I assume that Mill s claim about majoritarian democracy and minorities in general implies a similar claim about majoritarian democracy and cultural minorities. That claim, that majoritarian democracy keeps members of cultural minorities out of legislative bodies, is the main premise of my argument. It does not imply by itself that majoritarian democracies do not give people of minority cultures an equal opportunity to flourish; arguably, to flourish in such democracies people must be represented by politicians who pass legislation to help them flourish, and such politicians may be drawn from the majority culture. My argument therefore appeals to two further considerations: first, that, given the usual assumptions of majoritarian democracy, politicians will normally be reluctant to pass legislation specifically to enable people of minority cultures to advance; second, that politicians who care about such people s interests and understand the kind of legislation necessary to enable them to thrive will probably share their culture. Despite some utopian thinkers, it may not be possible to design policies that enable all cultural groups to advance and to do so at the same rate. In particular, legislation that enables people of minority cultures to advance may very well slow the advance of those of the majority culture. Further, because human beings usually seem to want to have others to feel superior to, people of the majority culture often feel threatened by legislation that enable people of minority cultures to gain on them. Since voters do not support politicians who introduce legislation they see as threatening and politicians want voters support, politicians usually do not even discuss legislation that would obviously enable people of minority cultures to advance.

It is an invidious assumption that people from the majority culture cannot care about the interests of those in minority cultures and cannot possibly understand and devise the kind of legislation that would enable them to thrive. But two considerations suggest that, all else equal, people of minority cultures are more likely to be well represented by those who share their culture than by others. First, people who share their culture are more likely to identify with them, and consequently to love and care for them, than are outsiders. Supposing that this is usually the case, politicians from a minority culture are likely to be more strongly motivated to design and pass legislation aimed at helping their cultural group advance than are politicians from the majority culture. The second argument that people of minority cultures are better represented by those who share their culture than by outsiders is that people who share their culture are likely to better understand their culture than outsiders, and consequently likely to better understand what legislation will help them to thrive. This may seem false on the ground that an outsider, standing outside a culture, may better understand a culture s strengths and weaknesses than does a cultural insider. I grant that one must be able to stand outside a culture in order to appreciate its strengths and weaknesses. But politicians from the minority culture will often be able to stand outside their own culture, because they live in a society dominated by the majority culture and are therefore often compelled to step outside their own culture and to operate in the majority culture. Consequently, they will be able to gain the perspective necessary to assessing its strengths and weaknesses. Assuming that they are likely to be among their culture s more mobile and energetic members, they will be especially able to have an informed outsider s view of it, although most members of the culture will enjoy this advantage to some degree. Further, standing outside a culture enables one to appreciate its strengths and weaknesses only if one knows the culture intimately. But politicians from the majority are not likely to know the minority culture intimately. Their culture dominates the society and they do not need to know much about minority cultures. Consequently, unlike politicians from minority cultures, they are unlikely to have an informed outsider s view of minority cultures. It may be objected that minority cultures do not have to be represented by people who understand their peculiarities and who care about them specifically. I will be reminded of the Japanese and Jews, who have done remarkably well in the United States although they are usually represented by Caucasians and Christians who neither understand them nor particularly

care for them. These cases, and others that could be cited, show that it is not a necessary condition that a cultural minority be represented by its members, or even those who understand and care about it, in order to thrive. The cultural minority may feel itself invisible or may believe that the majority will not take the trouble to devise legislation detrimental to it; or it may have qualities that enable it to advance, given the legislation that the politicians elected by the majority pass, even if this legislation is not passed in order to enable it to advance. Considerations such as these probably account for the success of the Japanese and Jews, though it is arguable that the Japanese might have avoided some disasters I have in mind their internment during the Second World War if they had not kept such a low political profile. But we cannot generalize from these exceptional cases and conclude that cultural minorities ordinarily do not need to represent themselves politically in order to flourish. In many cases a cultural minority s qualities will not enable it to advance given the legislation that the politicians elected by the majority pass. Normally, to thrive it must be represented by those who understand and care about it, and usually such people will come from its own ranks. This is the basic point about political life that the American revolutionaries learned, and that justified their separation from Great Britain; and it explains why cultural groups invariably seek political representation and power as soon as they become too numerous or too successful to be invisible. My argument that the usual apparatus of democratic procedures need not give minority cultures opportunity to thrive assumes that members of minority cultures will not be elected to office. This is a reasonable assumption, given the principle of majoritarian democracy that the candidate elected to office gets the most votes and that people tend to vote for candidates from their own cultural group. But it is not always true. A cultural group can constitute a majority in several voting districts even if it is a small minority in the country as a whole. In these districts it will probably be represented by those who share its culture, precisely because people tend to vote for candidates of their own cultural groups, and the candidates elected to office are those who get the most votes. Such representation is better than no representation. It gives the minority culture some measure of self-government and ensures that its representatives have an opportunity to urge policies for its advancement in legislatures made up of representatives of many voting districts, even if the policies they urge are unlikely to be adopted, given that the principle of majority rule holds in the legislature as well as in the competition for office. Nevertheless,

requiring cultural groups to segregate themselves in particular voting districts in order to make themselves majorities in those districts has unacceptable consequences. The segregation involved is not likely to be only the innocent result of like-minded people freely choosing to live together. It will probably also require coercion. In order to remain, or to become, a majority in a voting district, a cultural group may have to prevent those of different cultures from moving into the district, or even compel them to leave if they are already there. Since this is unjust and likely to lead to conflict between cultural groups, representation achieved by cultural segregation probably comes at too high a price. I now take up the argument that majoritarian democracies also fail to give people of minority cultures an equal opportunity to contribute to their societies by taking part directly in legislation. This does not mean, of course, that majoritarian democracies altogether prevent members of cultural minorities from contributing to their societies. There are ways to contribute to one s society besides being elected to office. The argument that majoritarian democracies do not give members of minority cultures an equal opportunity to contribute directly to the legislation of their society is in a sense a trivial implication of the fact, already established, that majoritarian democracies give members of minority cultures little opportunity to be elected to office. But members of cultural minorities who are excluded from political office by the mechanisms of majoritarian democracy are not likely to feel that their exclusion is trivial. Elected officials design and pass legislation and consequently are able to contribute to their societies in peculiarly powerful and effective ways. I also want to make the stronger point that members of minority cultures may have something to contribute to legislation in their society that members of the majority culture may not be able to contribute. It relies on the kind of considerations that John Stuart Mill used to justify his claim that society should value freethinkers, eccentrics, and intellectuals. Mill did not simply urge mechanisms and policies like systems of entrenched rights that would help to prevent the majority from overwhelming freethinkers, eccentrics, and intellectuals. More generally, he did not want the majority only to tolerate these minorities. He believed that it should value them because they could have something to teach it. His best-known argument is stated in On Liberty. In that work Mill maintains that unless people harm others they should be allowed to live as they decide. Some of his arguments for this claim justify only toleration. I have in mind where he argues that a

person s own mode of laying out his existence is best, not because it is best in itself, but because it is his own mode. 2 But other arguments stress that allowing others to live as they please can contribute to the discovery of ways to live that are objectively best. This is the well-known experiments in living argument. Mill s idea was that people who try unconventional ways of living may well hit on practices that the majority can learn from and adopt to its benefit. As he wrote, It is important to give the freest scope possible to uncustomary things, in order that it may in time appear which of these are fit to be converted into customs. 3 If Mill s argument is sound, valuable and useful ideas about how to live probably derive from all cultures, and consequently from minority cultures. I believe this to be the case because cultures are experiments in living. People do not normally think of their own culture as an experiment in living. They do not suppose that their culture s mores and practices are hypotheses about how life should be lived and that in following these mores and practices they are behaving somewhat like scientists subjecting hypotheses to empirical tests. Normally they act as their culture dictates because they don t think about it, or because they believe that alternatives are wrong, or sometimes because they cannot conceive of alternatives. Still a culture is an experiment in living in the sense that things happen as a result of people following its mores and practices, and people do learn from how and why these things happen. This is why cultures change. People see what the consequences of living according to the mores and practices of their culture are, and as a result some of the more sensitive or imaginative or daring among them are moved from time to time to do things differently themselves or to urge their fellows to do things differently. When their example is followed, or their suggestions are accepted and only rarely does either happen quickly their culture slowly changes. I say changes advisedly, and not improves. An enterprising knave may hit on a way to circumvent an important cultural convention for his personal advantage. If others follow his example, the overall result could be retrogression. Of course, in time people will learn from that experiment, and some of them may introduce reforms, though again we cannot conclude that these reforms will be altogether successful or that they will not have unforeseen and undesirable side effects. Still, if Mill is right that a majority may stand to learn from the experiments in living of freethinkers and eccentrics, it probably stands to learn much more from the experiments in living of minority cultures. The experiments in living of freethinkers and eccentrics are usu-

ally conducted on a small scale and for a short time. This should make a large society that wants to reproduce itself extremely wary of taking them seriously, however attractive they may seem. A culture, on the other hand, is always the result of an exceedingly long series of related experiments in living in which each experiment is designed in the light of what was learned in earlier experiments. More than that, it is also partly a series of interrelated reflections on the series of experiments in living. People do not only learn from their mores and practices; they also reflect on what they have learned, on the possibilities and impossibilities it reveals to them, and consequently on what they can and cannot reasonably hope to achieve. Each of these reflections is made in the light of previous reflections and influences the direction the series of experiments in living takes. As a result the experiments in living of a culture become an attempt to work out a point of view of how to live, and every culture contains a commentary on the difficulties and possibilities of working out that point of view. Now it is highly unlikely that every culture has the same point of view on how to live and the same commentary on the difficulties and possibilities of working it out. The protean nature of human inventiveness and the variety of circumstances in which cultures evolve ensure this. Assuming that the majority has not discovered all there is to know about how to live, and that minorities have not gotten it all wrong, I conclude that minority cultures may well contain moral and political ideas that would help legislatures make better laws if they were presented there. The main conclusion of the preceding sections is that the classic problem of majoritarian democracy, the tyranny of the majority, is likely to be especially pertinent and costly in culturally plural societies where one of the cultural groups is an absolute majority. In such societies, majoritarian democracy denies cultural minorities opportunities to flourish and to contribute directly to legislation. Since people feel alienated from their societies when they are denied such opportunities, it is hardly surprising that the standard democratic apparatus of measures and provisions often fails to foster a sense of community and belonging in culturally plural societies. This suggests that culturally plural societies should begin to consider seriously alternatives to the standard procedures of majoritarian democracy. One alternative is especially attractive because it has much to recommend it apart from the fact that it seems a promising way to correct the tendency of majoritarian democracy to exclude cultural minorities from public office. This is Thomas Hare s system of the single transferable vote, which Mill hailed as among the greatest improvements yet made in the theory and

practice of governments. 4 Mill was enthusiastic about Hare s system because it ensured that his favorite minorities freethinkers and intellectuals would get represented in proportion to their numbers without having to live in any particular part of the country. But it would also ensure that cultural minorities were represented in proportion to their numbers without having to segregate themselves in particular voting districts. 5 Majoritarians have strongly criticized the single transferable vote system and have questioned Mill s motives for endorsing it. 6 These criticisms have to be taken seriously. But the single transferable vote system seems a good place to start the search for a way to avoid the weakness of majoritarian democracy in culturally plural societies. ENDNOTES 1 John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Representative Government (New York: Dutton, 1951), 345. 2 Mill, 167. 3 Mill, 167. 4 Mill, 354. 5 Arthur Lewis made this point when he recommended proportional representation to the culturally plural societies of West Africa. See his Politics in West Africa (New York: Oxford University Press, 1965). 6 See, for example, Paul B. Kern, Universal Suffrage Without Democracy: Thomas Hare and John Stuart Mill, Review of Politics 34 (1972): 306 22; and Gideon Doron and Richard Kronick, Single Transferable Vote: An Example of a Perverse Social Choice Function, American Journal of Political Science 21 (1977): 303 11.