Complex Futures. Palonen, Mia Emilia Elisabeth

Similar documents
Chantal Mouffe On the Political

Chantal Mouffe: "We urgently need to promote a left-populism"

Discourse Analysis and Nation-building. Greek policies applied in W. Thrace ( ) 1

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Rhetoric of Populism: How to Give Voice to the People?

Populism is a Form of Anti- Pluralism

CHANTAL MOUFFE GLOSSARY

BOOK REVIEWS. Raffaella Fittipaldi University of Florence and University of Turin

Preface Is there a place for the nation in democratic theory? Frontiers are the sine qua non of the emergence of the people ; without them, the whole

Populism: theoretical approaches, definitions. POL333 Populism and political parties

National identity and global culture

Media system and journalistic cultures in Latvia: impact on integration processes

NETWORKING EUROPEAN CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION

Preface: Capitalism, Climate Change, and the Rhetorical Challenge

Democracy as a Non-Hegemonic Struggle? Disambiguating Chantal Mouffe s Agonistic Model of Politics

Review of Teubner, Constitutional Fragments (OUP 2012)

The Populist Persuasion: An American History

Dealing with Difference/Antagonism: Pancasila in the Post-Suharto Indonesia

Title of workshop The causes of populism: Cross-regional and cross-disciplinary approaches

Populism as a historical development. Emilia Palonen, Senior Lecturer

Anna Feigenbaum, Fabian Frenzel and Patrick McCurdy

Some critical remarks on the introduction Citizenship, Democracy and Pluralism by Chantal Mouffe in Felix Meritis in Amsterdam on 1 October 2010.

Introduction: Populism in the 21 st Century: Critical reflections on a global phenomenon

What Is Contemporary Critique Of Biopolitics?

Anti-immigration populism: Can local intercultural policies close the space? Discussion paper

Beneyto Transcript. SP: Sandra Porcar JB: Jose Mario Beneyto

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

What is populism and what is its role within far-right politics? Tomáš Nociar

Paul Collier: Wars, Guns, and Votes: Democracy in Dangerous Places

The Constitutional Principle of Government by People: Stability and Dynamism

The purpose of this article is to examine under what conditions the disruptive character of

Violent Conflicts 2015 The violent decade?! Recent Domains of Violent Conflicts and Counteracting February 25-27, 2015

The Politics of Emotional Confrontation in New Democracies: The Impact of Economic

Ideology COLIN J. BECK

- Call for Papers - International Conference "Europe from the Outside / Europe from the Inside" 7th 9th June 2018, Wrocław

Political Science 423 DEMOCRATIC THEORY. Thursdays, 3:30 6:30 pm, Foster 305. Patchen Markell University of Chicago Spring 2000

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

Marco Scalvini Book review: the European public sphere and the media: Europe in crisis

THE AGONISTIC CONSOCIATION. Mohammed Ben Jelloun. (EHESS, Paris)

Elites, elitism and society

POLS 1201 Introduction to Canadian Politics 3 ch (3C/T) [W] Survey course focusing on Canadian government and politics at the national level.

DIFFERENT TYPES OF CAPITALS MOBILIZED TO STRENGTHEN LOCAL POLITICAL LEADERSHIP

"Armed with Expertise: The Militarization of American Social Research During the Cold War (Book Review)" by Joy Rohde

Strategic Review for Southern Africa, Vol 36, No 1. Book Reviews

Introduction: conceptualizing social movements

Economic Autonomy and Democracy: Hybrid Regimes in Russia and Kyrgyzstan by Kelly M. McMann, Cambridge University Press, 2006, 278 pp.

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

Challenge to the Nation-State: Immigration in Western Europe and the United States

The future of Europe - lies in the past.

Democratic decision-making processes

Viktória Babicová 1. mail:

Dreaming big: Democracy in the global economy Maliha Safri; Eray Düzenli

John Benjamins Publishing Company

Ideology or cherry-picking? The issue opportunity structure for candidates in France

D R. B E N J A M I N M O F F I T T

Hegemony and Education. Gramsci, Post-Marxism and Radical Democracy Revisited (Review)

Ideas for an intelligent and progressive integration discourse

Vrije Universiteit Brussel. Populism and nationalism De Cleen, Benjamin. Published in: Handbook of populism. Publication date: 2017

2. Populist Political Communication. Toward a Model of Its Causes,Forms, and Effects

Indhold Abstract... 1 Chapter 1: Introduction... 4 Chapter 2: Method : Interpretivism : Constructionism

Applying principles of agonistic politics to institutional design

paoline terrill 00 fmt auto 10/15/13 6:35 AM Page i Police Culture

Like many other concepts in political science, the notion of radicalism harks back to the

ISSA Proceedings 2006 The Rhetoric Of Emotions In Political Argumentation

Introduction. in this web service Cambridge University Press

EXPERT INTERVIEW Issue #2

On the New Characteristics and New Trend of Political Education Development in the New Period Chengcheng Ma 1

German Historical Institute London BULLETIN

Sociology of corruption

Utopia or Auschwitz by Hans Kundnani

Empirical Studies and Political Discourse Theory: A Critical Analysis of Resistance from an Organizational Perspective

Research on the Education and Training of College Student Party Members

Summary. A deliberative ritual Mediating between the criminal justice system and the lifeworld. 1 Criminal justice under pressure

Power and Social Communication

Enlightenment of Hayek s Institutional Change Idea on Institutional Innovation

THE PLURALISM OF AGONISTIC PLURALISM. Mouffe in discussion with Erman, Dryzek and Knops

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI)

CONNECTIONS Summer 2006

Themes and Scope of this Book

Experience of Tehran : Image of Tehran in the Films of Today s Cinema of Iran

Delegation and Legitimacy. Karol Soltan University of Maryland Revised

Jeroen Warner. Wageningen UR

Reviews. Inclusion and Democracy, Iris Marion Young (New York: Oxford UP, pages). Reviewed by Christy Friend, University of South Carolina

College of Arts and Sciences. Political Science

DANIEL TUDOR, Korea: The Impossible Country, Rutland, Vt. Tuttle Publishing, 2012.

Globalization and European Integration: Threat or Opportunity?

Re-constructing the West: Beyond the Prophecies of Globalization. Matteo Stocchetti. The West: Concept, Narrative and Politics

INTL NATIONALISM AND CITIZENSHIP IN EUROPE

SURVIVAL OR DEVELOPMENT? Towards Integrated and Realistic Population Policies for Palestine

Articulations of Populism. Herkman, Juha.

The Limits of Political Contestation and Plurality. The Role of the State in Agonistic Theories of Democracy

Centro de Estudos Sociais, Portugal WP4 Summary Report Cross-national comparative/contrastive analysis

CONTEMPORARY SOCIETIES AND CULTURES: FOUNDATIONS OF THE STATE AND SOCIETY

Agendas: Research To Policy on Arab Families. An Arab Families Working Group Brief

POLI 359 Public Policy Making

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

As might be expected, the two panels were different in their approaches to the question about the methodological and institutional implications of

7th Slovenian Social Science Conference

The rise of right-wing extremism in Europe

POLITICAL SCIENCE 566 POLITICAL INTEREST GROUPS Spring 2009 Andrew McFarland

Transcription:

https://helda.helsinki.fi Complex Futures Palonen, Mia Emilia Elisabeth 2017-03-01 Palonen, M E E 2017, ' Complex Futures : Problems and Performance of Populism ' Redescriptions: Yearbook of political thought, conceptual history and feminist theory, vol. 20, no. 1, pp. 144-150. https://doi.org/10.7227/r.20.1.9 http://hdl.handle.net/10138/238988 https://doi.org/10.7227/r.20.1.9 Downloaded from Helda, University of Helsinki institutional repository. This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail. Please cite the original version.

Redescriptions, 2017. The definitive, peer reviewed and edited version of this article is published in Redescriptions, 20, 1, 2017, Complex futures: problems and performance of populism, 144-150, DOI:10.7227/R.20.1.9 Emilia Palonen Book review Moffitt and Müller Complex futures: problems and performance of populism To compare these two books is a challenge, as one is a pamphlet by an established scholar of European history, and the other is based on a doctoral thesis of a young political scientist hailed as one of the most important up and coming authors on populism. To start, I would agree with these judgements. Both have already made their name on their new books even if they are addressed to different audiences. Jan-Werner Müller s book is titled What is Populism? (For this review I have read the original German version Was ist Populismus? Ein Essay). Benjamin Moffitt s book seeks to answer the same question. Although its title is not equally conclusive or manifest, this book neither shies away with its title: The Global Rise of Populism. The crucial distinction between the two books is visible in the titles. It is on the nexus of essentialism and anti-essentialism. One sees populism as a question of what is and what not, while the other deals with its dynamics. The Global Rise has the subtitle: Performance, Political Style, and Representation. Populism is not a question of is or not but about articulation and representation. It is something performative rather than a state of affairs. In his essay, Jan-Werner Müller is interested in establishing a concept and moral stance of populism rather than exploring its historical basis or articulations. Examples of populism are presented as support for the thesis. Meine These is in short that populism is an anti-establishment attitude with exclusive claim to be representing the people. The evidence, that in a pamphlet is more anecdotal than rigorous, is interesting, well argued and clever. I share much of Müller s concerns. But I worry that, perhaps in his need to define populism in a particular way, he is actually remystifying rather than demystifying what is going on under the heading of populism. The People (Volk) is a dangerous word, as he points out with reference to Claude Lefort and the French Revolution (Müller 2016, 86). Müller introduces the reader to different perspectives to populism that range from the crisis of representation to the various symptoms of populism, and to different empirical cases of populism. It is exciting to read how he rolls one argument after another and refutes them. Finally, what matters is his thesis or reading of populism. Populismus, so meine These, ist eine ganz bestimmte Politikvorstellung, laut der einem moralisch reinen, homogenen Volk stets eine unmoralische und parasitäre Elite gegenüberstehen wobei diese Art von Eliten eigentlich gar nicht wirklich zum Volk gehören. (Müller 2016, 42) For him, populism is something beyond mere criticism of the elite (26), but an articulation of the people as moral and the elite as immoral. At times reading What is Populism I wonder if Müller s heading is wrong. What Müller actually seems to be talking about is ethno-nationalism. While he defines populism as the confrontation between morally pure homogeneous People and immoral parasitic Elites, he continues with examples of ethnic purity and homogeneity. He gives as an example the Finns Party, for whom this has only been a side-discourse until now. However, Timo Soini, the leader of the party during

1997 2017, has repeatedly defined himself and his movement as populist and even written his Master s thesis on populism. Müller engages in the fashionable trend of studying populism and draws his scholarly identity around that. Yet, it is the worrying aspects of nationalism, xenophobia, ethnic purity and fascism that are hidden behind his title and definition of populism. As the author of books of Memory and Power in Post-War Europe (2002) and Constitutional Patriotism (2007), Jan-Werner Müller is blending the distinct character of populism with a different historical phenomenon (ethno-nationalism) that he has studied for long. Unlike Müller, Moffitt is more focused on populism as a phenomenon of its own. That said, the first chapter of his book is also entitled The Problems with Populism. He acknowledges that there are indeed problems with populism but that there are also multiple understandings of populism, which do not really come across in Müller s book. At the heart of these problems is a struggle over the definition of populism. Moffitt draws from Ernesto Laclau s theory, where often populism is equated with politics, in a problematic way. Moffitt sets out as his task to find ways to expand on Laclau s theory rather than to reject or overcome it. He sees Laclau s famous definition of populism as a logic as perhaps the most innovative and not to mention, most formally developed theory of populism. And adds that to be used for empirical analysis, it must be brought down to earth in some regards. Here I cannot but agree. So, instead of trying to find a singular definition for populism, Moffitt points to the variety of cases of populism in the world. He even acknowledges that populism today may have shifted and evolved from its previous iterations and thus needs new thinking to reconsider it, re-describe it, and bring it up to date in a way that is sensitive to its time and space context. (Moffitt, 27) The comparison between Moffitt and Müller brings about an important distinction about populism: some take populism as a definable object to study, others look at the phenomenon through its multiple aspects rather than its embodiments. Müller seeks to highlight how there is this thing called populism that is anti-democratic and even in its progressive forms not very useful. As a result, it is a misunderstanding to consider that populism would be a corrective to democracy, he stresses. Populists are not interested in participation of citizens as such. (Müller 2016, 44). He bases his examples on populist figures such as Orbán, the leader of Fidesz in Hungary and Soini s Finns Party in Finland who incidentally both have assumed support for democracy in their own ways. Müller also discusses views by other scholars including the left populist theorists Chantal Mouffe and Ernesto Laclau. Müller s response is simply left hanging on his rhetorical question of what is the added value of the peopling in in politics understood as conflict: Politik ist Konflikt, aber was genau ist durch diese volkschaften ich sage bewusst nicht : völkischen Unscreibungen gewonnen? (123) For Laclau and Mouffe populism is something relevant in politics and for democracy as it addresses the people that should be the centre of democratic politics by definition but Müller does not understand what s the value of the focus on the people. So he decides to morally oppose such articulations, as populism is an inbuilt danger in modern representative democracy (28) and the people is fiction (58). In an ambivalent way Laclau acknowledges this possibility but would still find volkshaft important. What is it indeed? Müller seems not to grasp the one thing that is crucial to populist articulations: the capacity of populism to generate bonds among the people through the chains of equivalence

and the generation of demands, as they articulate the antagonistic and constitutive frontier in politics, as described by Laclau. His liberal view draws mainly on numbers and voting, but not on what makes people vote in the ways they do. These decisions are not only related to rationality or interests, but also on passions and identifications. For Müller representing the people is not a legitimate claim. Through rhetoric and structural linguistics or drawing on Saussure s distinction between the syntagmatic and paradigmatic (associative) axes of language Laclau makes the distinction between logics of substitution and combination in politics (see e.g. Rhetorical Foundations of Society 2014). In fact, this same distinction lies at the core of Müller s argument: the metonymic replacement of the people with the populist movement is not allowed in democracy, what is allowed is a substitution in relation to the paradigmatic extension of the signifying chain. What is legitimate for Müller is the format we too are the people, but not we are the people (21). Following Habermas, Müller argues that the people is only about plurality ( [Das Volk] tritt nur im Plural auf, 19). He imagines the people as a composition of an ever-expanding set of segments of society. It is composed of socio-economic groups, and is not whole. Any expression of totality appears for Müller to be a sign of totalitarianism. This is understandable, given his interest in European history, WWII memory and his German background. And, in the face of increasing populism which in Europe has been strongly linked with right-wing populism it appears rather scary. And this is the interpretation in this book, too. Indeed, curiously, Müller s thesis is compatible with the logic of populism conceptualized by Ernesto Laclau, according to which antagonism and exclusion dominate politics. He argues that the democratic we is not a fact per se but that the state of belonging is always renewed in a process, which precisely fits the thesis of Laclau and Mouffe. Yet, this leads him to a different conclusion than them: populists for Müller are against democracy because they claim to represent the people. Like Laclau and Mouffe, Müller bases his argumentation on Claude Lefort. But contrary to them Müller reads Claude Lefort literally: if the space of power should be empty, as the French theorist claimed, then it should be empty. He omits contingency. Sadly, in the pamphlet besides repeating his These, Müller does not engage with this logic. He engages with the contents. And hence, loses the anti-essentialist character that was crucial to Laclau s formulation. More specifically, he fails to understand the performative and constitutive logic of populism that for Laclau and Mouffe is aligned with Lefort s idea of the empty space of power; for them identity is always a fleeting relation in the need of re-articulation. At the time of writing this review, the contingency and emptiness was well encapsulated in Emmanuel Macron s solemn march to the position of power on the election day at the ceremony of the French president at Louvre. And Macron, as is common, knew to address both his own supporters, and those of his rival Marine Le Pen, and even those not voting at all. His presence at the highest office in France does not mean that the activists of his movement En Marche! would now be synonymous with power. Ironically, Macron challenged the traditional political establishment and old parties, too: and could fit to the category of populism but probably not following Müller. Müller discusses populism and anti-populism and also the bipolar opposition of technocracypopulism, which he refutes: technocracy can also be void of ideas and focused on policy so it is more similar to populism than generally thought of (Müller 2016, 115). Here again, he simply brackets away a contesting claim.

The performative aspect of populism is visible in the history of various forms of populisms and it is this salutary aspect of populism that Moffitt emphasizes in his book. He has written an excellent study that challenges mainstream understandings on populism. What could be explored further, however, is the constitutive role of populism in politics and the consequences of serial temporary attempts to generate it through the use of syntagmatic-metonymic rhetoric. While the work is moving to that direction, concepts such as audience do not encapsulate sufficiently what takes place in populist mobilization and rhetoric: that an uneven multiplicity becomes, even if temporarily, the people. But following Laclau, Moffitt seems to argue that what matters for populism is not its content that should be discussed in other instances but its form. Hence, he investigates populism as a political style (Ch. 3); as performance of the leader (Ch. 4); through the role of the media (Ch. 5) and the audience the people (Ch. 6); with regard to the role of crisis in populism (Ch. 7), and populism s relationship with democracy (Ch. 8). Each of these aspects presents an interesting study of the ways in which populism has been and could be explored. He also singles out the relevant topoi of populist rhetoric: the people-versus-the-elite, bad manners that the populists have and crisis that capture much of the focus. Moffitt s stance is that populism is neither clearly democratic nor antidemocratic as Kaltwasser and Mudde (Populism in Europe and the Americas, 2012) have argued. He enumerates a list of arguments both for the democratic ethos of populism and against it, and exemplifies them through a link to specific political figures. He is not convinced about the processes of othering that are at the heart of empirical descriptions of populism such that imply the annihilation of the enemies of the people, or more generally deny the complexity produced by a homogenizing articulation of the unified people. Also he sees problems in personifying the phenomenon, because it dichotomizes the political space into two antagonistic camps and assumes a monopoly of power in the hands of the leader. Yet again, I cannot but agree, as when the antagonistic divide that the populist movement generates, following Laclau s theory populism, becomes its own anti-thesis: institutionalization. After all, for Laclau the opposite of populist identifications are institutional identifications based in pre-given political interests or identities derived from structural positions without articulation. These attempts to reduce populism to a simple phenomenon often shadow over the potential of populism to include previously excluded groups or identities in the performance of the people, or to enable people to understand complex political phenomena; or to reveal the dysfunctions of the contemporary democratic systems ; or finally to offer alternative influencing tools than mere voting (Moffitt 2016, 144, 142-149). While it might be nice to state clearly that populism is or is not democratic, it is only by acknowledging the complexity of the relationship between the two phenomena, and noting populism s both democratic and antidemocratic tendencies, that we do it justice. (Moffitt 2016, 151). Perhaps the binary separation of populism and democracy should be abandoned altogether, he suggests. The dominant trend in the literature, particularly in political science, is to consider populism as an ideology that is thin-centered (cf. Mudde & Kaltwasser 2012), and has a non-normative dimension. Moffitt rejects this. From Müller s position, however, populism is übernormative and the only normative stand is to refute it. Populism is a danger to democracy, he argues (Müller 2016, 28). Like Moffitt, he does not embrace the concept of ideology. In fact, even though his argumentation may be ideological, and even though populism presents an essentialisable object of study, Müller s examples articulate instances of populism. He still needs to present cases to illustrate his normative claim. For him, populism is a view of politics (Müller 2016, 42). For Moffitt, it is a way of performing politics. While exploring the constitutive role of populism, we should also look at the

how this is happening. According to Moffitt (2016, 151): there will be a need to pay close attention to the way that populism, as a style, manifests across different political contexts and how it adapts and reconfigures democracy s performative tropes and repertoires in its own image. The two books operate more or less on the same level of abstraction, and showcase a rigorous analysis that highlights the complexity of the argument that is present in both books. In Moffitt s book, the author manages to highlight the complexity of the phenomenon both in theoretical terms and through the engagement with the multiplicity of illustrated cases. Still, the engagement with the topic could be more detailed and rigorous, but I will wait for the sequel(s) to appear. While many liberal critics have been welcoming a down turn in rightwing populism after the French and Dutch elections, Moffitt (2016, 151) argues differently: populism is likely to be a reoccurring and possibly more common phenomenon across the global political landscape, given that democracy and populism share this central political subject and audience. He suggests types of populism for future research. These would indeed be fruitful to consider alongside the overused focus on the degrees of populism or the scales of democracy. Exploring populist articulations among the mainstream actors is also something I have a personal take on. Leaving behind any illusions of being able to associate populism (in singular) with a particular definition is the next task for the research field on populism. According to me, Müller s definition, which stresses that populism gets entangled with the purity of the people and the immorality of elites, is rather a type of fringe populism : it moves to the center from the position at the edges of the political field. This type of populist movements may either influence existing parties through changes on their agendas or break through the party system themselves. Furthermore, to study populism in the future, we might have to end up exploring mainstream actors ever more often. Where and how can we recognize the spillovers of populism if we only focus on the explicitly populist movements and authors? The crucial question is: how can we grasp the changing character of populism, as Moffitt (2016, 161) aptly stresses. Engaging with the very concepts at play, their use and the game of naming to discuss new aspects of populism that capture themanifestations of new dimensions of old phenomena, is not only a task for political praxis but also for political science. Emilia Palonen, University of Helsinki