Non-global social contracts: A note on inefficient social institutions*

Similar documents
D. There are both positive and normative branches of the public choice literatures

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

I. Identify and or Define. III. Diagrams, Games, and Puzzles. II. Matching exercise: link the following philosophers with their ideas.

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE!

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

P1: aaa SJNW N stylea.cls (2005/11/30 v1.0 LaTeX Springer document class) January 2, :37

Postscript: Subjective Utilitarianism

I. Identify and or Define. III. Games and Puzzles

Political Science Introduction to American Politics

PLSC 118B, THE MORAL FOUNDATIONS OF POLITICS

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

1 Aggregating Preferences

III. PUBLIC CHOICE AND GOVERNMENT AS A SOLUTION

Constitutional Political Economy 1

Hobbes, Locke, Montesquieu, and Rousseau on Government

Lecture 11: The Social Contract Theory. Thomas Hobbes Leviathan Mozi Mozi (Chapter 11: Obeying One s Superior)

James M. Buchanan The Limits of Market Efficiency

Game Theory and Philosophy

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction

Do Voters Have a Duty to Promote the Common Good? A Comment on Brennan s The Ethics of Voting

Oregon Social Sciences Standards Grade 8

A Correlation of. Prentice Hall America: History of Our Nation Beginnings to To the. Oregon Social Sciences Standards.

Agendas and Strategic Voting

Rent Seeking and Constitutional Political Economy: Organizations, Rules, and the Control of Rent-Seeking Losses

Modeling Conflict. Thomas Chadefaux Chair of Sociology, in particular of Modeling and Simulation

Meeting Plato s challenge?

Waltz s book belongs to an important style of theorizing, in which far-reaching. conclusions about a domain in this case, the domain of international

Chapter 8: The Use of Force

Topic Page: Hobbes, Thomas,

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

The Origins of the Modern State

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

1. Introduction. Baruch de Spinoza, Political Treatise (1677)

Solving the "Tragedy of the Commons": An Alternative to Privatization*

Thomas Hobbes v. John Locke

Prof. Dr. Bernhard Neumärker Summer Term 2016 Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg. Constitutional Economics. Exam. July 28, 2016

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

JUSTIFICATION OF THE COMPOUND REPUBLIC: James M. Buchanan

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Social Contract Theory

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

In Defense of Liberal Equality

Focal Points and the Evolution of Social Coordination

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules

Social Contract Theory

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

VI. Rawls and Equality

Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question *

INTERPRETING THE RIGHT TO LIFE

Property Rights and the Rule of Law

The origins of public finance, as a field of study though most certainly not

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Problems with Group Decision Making

Bargaining Power and Dynamic Commitment

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

Morals by Convention The rationality of moral behaviour

RATIONAL CHOICE AND CULTURE

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

An example of public goods

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Problems of collective action

Game-Theoretic Remarks on Gibbard's Libertarian Social Choice Functions

Distributive vs. Corrective Justice

The constitutional dilemma of European integration

Evolutionary Game Path of Law-Based Government in China Ying-Ying WANG 1,a,*, Chen-Wang XIE 2 and Bo WEI 2

The Integer Arithmetic of Legislative Dynamics

Buchanan on Ethics and Self-Interest in Politics: A Contradiction or Reconciliation?

THE BEST OF THE OLL #10

Social and Political Philosophy

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Mr. Rarrick. John Locke

Adam Smith and Government Intervention in the Economy Sima Siami-Namini Graduate Research Assistant and Ph.D. Student Texas Tech University

PLSC 118B, THE MORAL FOUNDATIONS OF POLITICS

The Aggregation Problem for Deliberative Democracy. Philip Pettit

Pos 419Z Seminar in Political Theory: Equality Left and Right Spring Peter Breiner

HOBBES, LOCKE, MONTESQUIEU, ROUSSEAU ON GOVERNMENT

Global Aspirations versus Local Plumbing: Comment: on Nussbaum. by Richard A. Epstein

Authority versus Persuasion

And so at its origins, the Progressive movement was a

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

Thoughts on Deliberative Democracy Through the Lenses of the Economics Approach

Thomas Hobbes. Source: Thomas Hobbes, The Leviathan, published in 1651

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

PLSC 118A, THE MORAL FOUNDATIONS OF POLITICS

William Riker s Liberalism Against Populism. CMSS seminar, Tuesday 15 October

VOTING RULES AND REDISTRIBUTION: THE CASE OF THE RECENT ECONOMIC CRISIS

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

LECTURE NOTES LAW AND ECONOMICS (41-240) M. Charette, Department of Economics University of Windsor

John Locke. Source: John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government published 1689

This fear of approaching social turmoil or even revolution leads the middle class Progressive reformers to a

WORLD ECONOMICS. The New Economics of the Brain Drain. Volume 6 Number 2 April - June By ODED STARK. Reprinted from

Transcription:

Public Choice 41: 441-448 (1983) O 1983 Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in ihe Nerherlands Non-global social contracts: A note on inefficient social institutions* ROBERT A. BLEWETT and ROGER D. CONGLETON** Abstract This paper explores some perverse features that can emerge when social contracts are moved from a social vacuum to a setting of social interdependence. In particular we note incentives that might exist in conjunction with externality problems that yield situations in which: (1) social contracts reduce social wealth; (2) sub-global social contracts are Pareto inferior to the absence of social contracts; (3) there are no incentives for global social contracts. While previous works emphasized the benefits of contracts, this paper focuses on their costs. A conclurion reached is that perhaps justice and efficiency demand not a single global social contract but rather a rich melange of sub-global contracts with appropriate interstices of anarchy. Thomas Hobbes is generally regarded as the originator of the contractual explanation of the emergence of society. Hobbes' (1909: 96-97) characterization of the pre-contractual society is both pessimistic and well known: Whatsoever therefore is consequent to a time of Warre, where every man is Enemy to every man; the same is consequent to the time, wherein men live without other security, than what their own strength, and invention shall furnish them withal. In such condition,... the life of man [will be] solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short. Hobbes saw the social contract as the means by which individuals escape the harsh environment of anarchy and realize the fruits of a more civilized order. In the past two decades, renewed interest in social contractarianism has been spurred by the work of John Rawls (1971) and James Buchanan *An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Public Choice Society Meetings, San Antonio, Texas, March, 1982. **Assistant Professors of Economics at St. Lawrence University and Clarkson College, respectively. The authors wish to thank J.M. Buchanan for his comments and suggestions. The School of Management, Clarkson College, Potsdam, NY 13676.

(1975). Rawls has argued that the process of social negotiation should proceed from behind what he calls a 'veil of ignorance' in order to ensure that the resulting social contract will be just. Buchanan, while sympathetic to this view, suggests that the process of social negotiation can not ignore existing institutions nor their accompanying distributions of wealth and power. He suggests that just changes to institutions may be made through qualified Wicksellian unanimity. Thus, while Hobbes emphasizes the civilizing tendencies of social contracts, Rawls and Buchanan emphasize the justness of the results of social negotiation. There are several well known criticisms of the positions taken by social contractarians (see Mueller, 1979). There is, for example, the matter of whether the process of social negotiation yields an explicit document or generates a broad consensus consisting of shared intuitions rather than a particular concrete set of rules. Some doubt the possibility of widespread agreement on terms of a social contract that are abstract yet sufficiently specific to be meaningful. Others raise the question of whether a process of social negotiation can ever be brought to a conclusion - perhaps only 'agreements' to disagree will be reached (i.e., acquiescence to the Hobbesian Jungle). In this paper we address a weakness that seems to have been overlooked by both proponents and opponents of social contractarianism. Namely, we will address the question of whether or not social contracts must be global to be Pareto optimal, a measure of performance embodied in both the Rawls and Buchanan notions of just contracts. It might be said that Hobbes, Rawls and Buchanan all suppose the societal contract to be global in that there is not explicit mention of individuals left outside the process of social negotiation. However, we consider this a simplifying assumption made to facilitate their analysis and exposition. Clearly, Hobbes had in mind an explanation of the emergence of kingdoms and other precursors of the nation-state well known to be less than global in domain. Buchanan seems similarly concerned with constitutions and constitutional reform, problemscommonplaceat national and state levels but less so at the truly global level. The Rawlsian theory of distributive justice also seems to have been aimed at national matters of redistribution as well as global concerns. Transplanting the process of social negotiation from a social vacuum into a world of social interdependencies greatly weakens the contractarian norms. While it will still tend to be true that social contracts benefit those individuals who directly enter the agreement, externalities imposed on nonmembers may tend to vitiate the efficiency properties of social contracts as well as their ethical desireability. The social contractarian's response to such externalities might be to extend the social contract so as to internalize the externalities of concern. However, in many cases it is precisely these spillovers that make the social contract worthwhile to its membership. As a result, there may be no incen-

tive for this process of internalization to take place. These externalities imposed on non-members may also promote the development of social contracts by those affected which in turn impose externalities on the original alliance. Such intersocial externalities may imply that two social contracts are worse than none, yet the absence of social contracts, by its very nonconlractual nature, can not be negotiated. The most common sort of social contract that will exhibit these properties are alliances formed to exploit those outside the alliance. Examples of such include the outlaw raiding party and its counterpart the posse, military alliances, and the broad assortment of coalitions commonplace among politicians at all levels of government. In order to illustrate some of the possible perverse features of sub-global contracts, we will abstract from the plethora of complex motivations and arrangements typical of real-world alliances and examine a simple, but revealing, case involving four persons. Assume that these individuals are wholly independent of one another in their original setting where they each possess, or rather utilize, identical stocks of resources (perhaps four individuals on four separate islands with C.A.R.E. packages). Let us suppose that superior numbers alone determine the success or failure of a 'raiding party' and that equal numbers result in a standoff. In the original setting, no raiding party can be successful since one against one yields a standoff. However, an alliance of two allows successful raids against the remaining two isolated individuals. Suppose that the raids themselves cost nothing, but that creating and maintaining an alliance has positive costs which increase with the number of individuals who directly participate in the social contract.' Let us assume that within each possible alliance the costs and benefits are distributed equally across all members as a consequence of their unanimous consent. Thus, to those directly under the social contract, the decision-making method and outcome will satisfy both the Buchanan and Rawlsian definitions of procedural and distributive justice. Table 1 lists the five social outcomes that are possible. They include: I. the original setting with no social contracts; 11. an alliance of two against two isolated individuals; 111. an alliance of two against another alliance of two; IV. an alliance of three against a single isolated individual; V. an alliance of all four - a global social contract.

While nothing can be said about the particular membership of any social contract, the incentives indicated in Table 1 are of interest. It should be noted that, within the setting examined, the societal overhead of forming social contracts is such that social wealth is maximized in the original state of nature. The absence of social contracts frees individuals from having to bear any of the costs associated with creating and maintaining effective alliances. However, in spite of the advantages of the original state, it is rational for every pair of individuals to attempt to achieve state 11, since the benefits of a social contract yielding that state, exceed the accompanying costs to charter members. However, were state I1 about to be realized, it would behoove the two isolated individuals to band together to defend themselves in order to realize state 111. The successful defense made possible by this new social contract makes it a welfare enhancing proposition to its membership. However, the original group would be worse off since the purpose of their collective action is now frustrated. Note that in state 111 everyone is worse off than they were with the complete absence of social contracts and that any attempt to disband one of the coalitions would leave the isolated individuals at the mercy of the remaining alliance. In our moves from state I to I1 to 111, each social contract has improved the position of its members, but the overall result is collectively disheartening since social wealth is reduced by each successive social contract. State I11 may also be unstable, as the possibility of joining the opposition (yielding state IV) becomes an attractive option for each member of both coalitions. The rewards of even a cumbersome social contract may exceed those of ineffective ones. However, there is no incentive to move from state IV to state V, the global contract. No matter how large the group, it always Table I State Coalitions Payoffs Where: A is each individual's initial endowment. T2, T3, T4 are the costs of maintaining operational social contracts of two, three, and four persons, respectively. T2 < T, < T, < A. (A - T4/4) < (A - T2/2) < A < [(4A - T3)/3] < [(4A - T2)/2].

This paper has explored some perverse features that can emerge when social contracts are formed in a setting of social interdependence. In particular we have noted incentives that tend to generate outcomes in which: pays to have someone left over to exploit. In this particular case, any potential wealth-enhancing properties of a global social contract are more than offset by an increase in societal overhead. So what otherwise might be regarded as socially undesirable exploitations may actually enhance social wealth though equity, of course, suffers. It should be noted that once state IV is achieved, it is in the interest of subsets of the alliance to drive one member out of the alliance so that state I1 might be reali~ed.~ (It is for this reason that moves from state I1 to state IV are unlikely to be direct ones). Thus, there is no core to this game of alliance and conquest. Every possible combination is dominated by some other, even though each social contract is just in the senses advocated by Buchanan and Rawls. In contrast to the outcomes emphasized by previous efforts, social contracts here become a means of transforming a Rousseau- like natural state into a Hobbesian Jungle. Hogarty (Tullock, 1972: Ch. 5) provides some cases that tend to mirror our example. Using examples from literature (both fiction and nonfiction), Hogarty attempted to show the jungle-like results of anarchy. Instead, his cases reveal the instability of anarchy and how formation of coalitions may lead to a Hobbesian jungle. For example, in the Confederate prisoner-of-war camp known as 'Andersonville,' the formation of raiding parties lowered welfare and led to the formation of other coalitions to counter the raiding parties. There were certainly costs to forming and maintaining these groups. No doubt the miserable condition of these prisoners would have been somewhat improved if there were no coalitions whatsoever. Collective action, not anarchy, led to their Hobbesian j~ngle.~ Such jungle-like results are by no means uncommon. Terrorist groups, urban youth gangs, and prison gangs all provide economic, social and psychological benefits to group members under what are essentially social contracts. These groups have spoken and unspoken rules and norms of behavior as well as formal and informal means of collective decisionmaking. Further, there are obvious internal costs to maintaining these social contracts in that there are restrictions on the behavior of individual members as well as certain required duties. While the benefits realized by group members no doubt exceed their costs, few would consider the overall social wealth or quality of life to be greater as a result of such groups as the Red Brigades, the Devil's Disciples, or El R~kn.~

(I) social contracts reduce social wealth; (2) sub-global contracts are Pareto inferior to the absence of social contracts; and (3) there are no incentives for global social contracts to be negotiated. Our analysis indicates that even were a state of individualistic anarchy desirable, the spontaneous formation of sub-global social contracts may make the state unobtainable. In this context, social contracts can be viewed as regrettable necessities. However, our study has ignored the wide variety of internally productive endeavors that might be undertaken under the umbrella of social contracts. By doing so, we have sacrificed universality in order to more clearly focus on a narrow aspect of social contractarianism. The works of Hobbes, Rawls and Buchanan emphasize the benefits of social contracts while this paper has concentrated on their costs. Given the diversity of both individuals and cultures, the costs of social negotiation may not be trivial. In many cases, the social costs of operational alliances will exceed their benefits at both local and global 1evels.j Neither global nor sub-global social negotiation can guarantee that a resultant social contract is Pareto efficient. Given both the costs and benefits of social contracts, the corner solutions of anarchy and one-world government may be neither obtainable nor necessarily desirable.6 To the extent that history may be characterized as a series of alliances, conquests and 'unifications,' our portrayal of social negotiation should not be ignored.' Social contracts are less than global in scope and generally costly to negotiate and maintain. However, an awareness of the costs of some social contracts should not keep us from being aware of the instances in which their advantages exceed their costs. Perhaps justice and efficiency demand not a single global contract but rather a rich melange of sub-global contracts with appropriate interstices of anarchy. NOTES 1. Such costs could include constraints on individual behavior necessary for a successful alliance. Collective decision making costs also increase with the number of participants involved in the process of social negotiation. (Buchanan and Tullock, 1962: Ch. 6). 2. This model is very similiar to a 'minimum winning coalition' game in elections (Riker, 1962). However, in reality this game may not be as unstable as depicted here (Riker and Ordershook, 1973: Ch. 7; Tullock, 1981b). 3. Hogarty uses another example derived from William Golding's Lord of the Flies. This case was not one of anarchy, but rather the case of one social contract replacing another. 4. A leader of the notorious El Rukn (formally the Blackstone Rangers) of Chicago's South Side claimed that his organization provided many public services and actually improved community life (Sale, 1971: 76). However, within the Stateville prison where El Rukn and other gangs have had more power than the nominal state authorities, the quality of life was such that non-affiliated inmates voluntarily remained locked in their cells (Beck with Monroe, 1979). 5. Tullock (1974) suggests that there may be further problems with societal reforms in that

changes typically confront public goods problems. 6. Moss (1980) arrives at conclusions similiar to ours. However, his analysis is based on the technical aspects of public goods provision while we base ours on the costs of negotiation and maintenance of social contracts. These costs are analogous to the collective decision costs of Buchanan and Tullock (1962). Other related work includes Kafoglis and Cebula (1981) and Blewett (1980: Ch. 4) which apply collective decision costs to the determination of optimal group sizes. 7. Tullock (l98la: 904) suggests in passing that states probably emerged as means to coerce redistribution and the socially beneficial aspects of states emerged as by-products. Our piece suggests that competitive efforts at redistribution via social contracts may be socially wasteful. REFERENCES Beck, M., with Monroe, S. (1979). Prisons: Retaking Stateville. Newsweek 93(19 March): 44. Buchanan, J.M. (1975). Limits to liberty: Between anarchy and Leviathan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Buchanan, J.M., and Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor, Mich.: University of Michigan Press. Blewett, R.A. (1980). The law and economics of suburban residential growth controls. Ph.D. dissertation, Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University. Hayek, F.A. (1976). Law legislation and liberty, Volume 2: The mirage of social justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hobbes, T. (1909). Hobbes's Leviathan: Reprinted from theedition of 1651. London: Oxford University Press. Kafoglis, M.Z., and Cebula, R.J. (1981). The Buchanan-Tullock model: Some extensions. Public Choice 36(1): 179-186. Keiser, R.L. (1969). The vice lords: Warriors of the streets. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Moss, L.S. (1980). Optimal jurisdictions and the economic theory of the state: Or anarchy and one-world government are only corner solutions. Public Choice 35(1): 17-26. Mueller, D.C. (1979). Public Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Press, A,, with Monroe, S. (1981). Gangs of Chicago, 1981. Newsweek 97(12 January): 88. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Riker, W.H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Riker, W.H., and Ordershook, P.C. (1973). Introduction to positive political theory. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. Rousseau, J.J. (1952). The Social Contract, Volume 38: Great books of the western world. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica. Sale, R.T. (1971). The Blackstone Rangers. New York: Random House. Short, J.F., Jr. (1974). Youth, gangs and society: Micro- and macro-sociological processes. The Sociological Quarter& 15(Winter): 3-19. Tullock, G. (Ed.) (1972). Explorations in the theory of anarchy. Blacksburg, Va.: University Publications. Tullock, G. (Ed.) (1974). Further explorations in the theory of anarchy. Blacksburg, Va.: University Publications. Tullock, G. (1974). The social dilemma: The economics of war and revolution. Blacksburg, Va.: University Publications.

Tullock, G. (1981a). The rhetoric and reality of redistribution. Southern Economic Journal 47(April): 895-907. Tullock, G. (1981b). Why so much stability? Public Choice 37(2): 189-202.