AGENDAS AND SINCERITY: A SECOND RESPONSE TO SCHWARTZ

Similar documents
Agendas and sincerity: a second response to Schwartz

Agenda trees and sincere voting: a response to Schwartz

University of Utah Western Political Science Association

Sincere versus sophisticated voting when legislators vote sequentially

Social welfare functions

Sincere Versus Sophisticated Voting When Legislators Vote Sequentially

Voting. Suppose that the outcome is determined by the mean of all voter s positions.

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

The Manipulability of Voting Systems. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1

Supporting Information for Competing Gridlock Models and Status Quo Policies

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

PROBLEM SET #2: VOTING RULES

Answers to Practice Problems. Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism.

12.2 Defects in Voting Methods

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Name Date I. Consider the preference schedule in an election with 5 candidates.

Exercises For DATA AND DECISIONS. Part I Voting

Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Kenneth Arrow. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Strategically vulnerable

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE

Lecture 12: Topics in Voting Theory

Complexity of Manipulating Elections with Few Candidates

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND VOTING Jac C. Heckelman and Nicholas R. Miller, editors.

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

Voting Criteria April

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/36

The Impossibilities of Voting

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

A PROBLEM WITH REFERENDUMS

Social Choice & Mechanism Design

Voting and preference aggregation

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

VOTING SYSTEMS AND ARROW S THEOREM

c M. J. Wooldridge, used by permission/updated by Simon Parsons, Spring

Introduction. Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes

Approaches to Voting Systems

Buying Supermajorities

Brexit Referendum: An Incomplete Verdict

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/31

Problems with Group Decision Making

American Government Unit 3 Rules were made to be broken or at least interpreted

Fairness Criteria. Review: Election Methods

: It is mathematically impossible for a democratic voting method to satisfy all of the fairness criteria was proven in 1949.

Election Theory. How voters and parties behave strategically in democratic systems. Mark Crowley

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Voting and preference aggregation

Introduction to Game Theory

Many Social Choice Rules

Write all responses on separate paper. Use complete sentences, charts and diagrams, as appropriate.

Syllabus update: Now keeping best 3 of 4 tests

Social Choice: The Impossible Dream. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

Safe Votes, Sincere Votes, and Strategizing

VOTING BY VETO: MAKING THE MUELLER-MOULIN ALGORITHM MORE VERSATILE

From Argument Games to Persuasion Dialogues

Goods, Games, and Institutions : A Reply

NEW YORK UNIVERSITY Department of Politics. V COMPARATIVE POLITICS Spring Michael Laver Tel:

1 Aggregating Preferences

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

Political Science 274 Political Choice and Strategy

Problems with Group Decision Making

answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice

Algorithms, Games, and Networks February 7, Lecture 8

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued. Voting II 1/27

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued

Math for Liberal Studies

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

MATH 1340 Mathematics & Politics

The Integer Arithmetic of Legislative Dynamics

THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE AND COOMBS RULE VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST: A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF SIMULATED DATA BASED ON ENGLISH ELECTIONS,

F851QP GOVERNMENT AND POLITICS. Unit F851: Contemporary Politics of the UK Specimen Paper. Advanced Subsidiary GCE. Time: 1 hour 30 mins

THE GEOMETRY OF VOTING CYCLES: THEORETICAL DEVELOPMENTS

Voting. Hannu Nurmi. Game Theory and Models of Voting. Public Choice Research Centre and Department of Political Science University of Turku

Rationality & Social Choice. Dougherty, POLS 8000

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

THE FUTURE OF ANALYTICAL POLITICS...

MATH 1340 Mathematics & Politics

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

Fairness Criteria. Majority Criterion: If a candidate receives a majority of the first place votes, that candidate should win the election.

Desirable properties of social choice procedures. We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures:

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

Math for Liberal Studies

9.3 Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates

Flanagan s Status Quo. Lindsay Swinton. April 12, 2007 ISCI 330

Mathematical Thinking. Chapter 9 Voting Systems

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

Voting Systems for Social Choice

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007

Political Science 201 Political Choice and Strategy. 115 Ingram Hall, Mondays/Wednesdays 2:30 to 3:45 p.m.

DHSLCalc.xls What is it? How does it work? Describe in detail what I need to do

Manipulative Voting Dynamics

Transcription:

AGENDAS AND SINCERITY: A SECOND RESPONSE TO SCHWARTZ Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore MD 21250 nmiller@umbc.edu July 2010 Abstract An Ordeshook-Schwartz agenda tree requires a voting theorist to assign a unique ostensive alternative to each node, but under some non-pairwise agendas there is no evident principle by which to do this. Therefore Ordeshook-Schwartz sincere voting is not clearly defined under all types of agendas. Farquharson-style agenda trees sidestep this problem and allow one or more definitions of sincere voting under every type of agenda.

AGENDAS AND SINCERITY: A SECOND RESPONSE TO SCHWARTZ The representation of voting agendas in Schwartz (2008) follows that set out in Ordeshook and Schwartz (1987) by associating a single ostensive alternative (to use the terminology of Groseclose and Krehbiel, 1993) with each node in the agenda tree, in the manner of Figures (1a) and (1d) in Miller (2010). It then follows naturally for OS to say that a sincere voter votes for his preferred ostensive alternative at the two successor nodes. Miller (1995 and elsewhere), following Farquharson (1969), associates a single alternative with each bottom node, in the manner of Figure 1(c), on the basis of which sets of alternatives are associated with nonbottom nodes, in the manner of Figure 1(b). In my first response to Schwartz, I did indeed concede the three points that he notes at the outset of his Reply (Schwartz, 2010), but with the following stipulations. (1) As an analytical construction, an Ordeshook-Schwartz agenda tree contains more information than a Farquharson- Miller tree, but this additional information is imputed by a voting theorist and may not be evident to voters. (2) The OS definition of sincere voting is simpler and more direct than FM s, 1 but it is defined only for OS agenda trees, which entail the problem just noted. (3) Farquharson s maximax definition of sincerity (also adopted by Miller) is not essential to a broader the notion of sincere voting, so Miller has no (single) definition of sincere voting; indeed, we should recognize that, under some procedures, there may be different types of sincere voting (as we certainly recognize for Approval and Cumulative Voting, for example). Furthermore, Schwartz is correct in saying that I restrict my attention to (effectively) pre-set agendas known to all voters, as is required for the standard analysis of strategic voting. With respect to the agenda trees depicted in Figure 1 in Miller (2010), our remarks have been at cross-purposes, since our interpretations of them have differed. On my interpretation (Miller, 2010, p. [5]), all agenda trees in Figure 1 represent a situation in which a bill b has been proposed along with an amendment a and a backup amendment c to be considered only if a is rejected. Let s call this Agenda 1. Farquharson represents Agenda 1 in the manner of (c) and Miller (1995) in the manner of (b), though (b) contains no information not implied by (c). I interpreted (a) and (d) as two different OS representations of the same Agenda 1. The representations obviously differ but, I claimed, they differ only in a way that does not show up in the parliamentary situation given by Agenda 1. However, Schwartz s Reply makes clear that his intention was to present (a) and (d) as representations of two different agendas: (a) representing Agenda 1 and (d) representing the different Agenda 2 in which the roles of b and c are switched. (The fact that b and c are switched in the top nodes may signal this, though Schwartz elsewhere says the labeling of the top node is arbitrary.) On this interpretation, Schwartz correctly claims that my Question 1 is substantively different in Agendas 1 and 2, since different bills (b and c) are up for amendment, and voters certainly would know whether they are voting on Agenda 1 or 2. 1 Moreover, OS sincere voting is easier to analyze than FM sincere voting, since the former depends only on the majority preference relation while the latter depends on the underling preference profile.

Agendas and Sincerity page 3 However, Schwartz s objection is still to the point, because in fact FM do represent both Agenda 1 and Agenda 2 by the same tree. This implies that FM believe that Agenda 1 and Agenda 2 are essentially the same agenda and that voters with given preferences would vote the same way in either case under any fixed behavioral assumption. The question is whether this implication is to be viewed as an analytic defect (the OS view) or an analytic insight (the FM view). There is no dispute between us about the validity of this implication if the behavioral assumption is that voters are strategic. However, OS sincere voters vote differently in (a) and (d), while those who vote sincerely in the Farquharson maximax manner (or, for that matter, in the more prudent minimax manner) vote the same way. As I observed in my first response, sincere voters who rank a between c and b are confronted with something of a dilemma at the first node under Agenda 1, and I now observe now that exactly the same voters are confronted with exactly the same dilemma under Agenda 2. Let s consider several voting agendas over just three alternatives a, b, and c, which I think more emphatically indicate what I believe are problems in the OS approach. It may be helpful to have a substantive example in mind, so let s use the DePew amendment example to which Schwartz refers in his Reply. These are the alternatives: a b c Popular election of Senators with voting qualifications set by Congress Popular election of Senators with voting qualifications set by states Selection of Senators by state legislatures One way choose among these alternatives is to use Plurality Voting. There is no difference between OS and FM on how to represent the agenda or how to define sincere voting in this case here we can all agree with Schwartz s principle that a sincere voter votes for his most preferred of the alternatives available for voting. But in a parliamentary setting voting is binary and requires two separate votes. Alternative c would not be explicitly introduced as it represents the status quo. Let s suppose a motion is introduced to provide for the popular election of Senators with voting qualifications set by states (i.e., alternative b), and then a (DePew) amendment to the motion is proposed to give Congress the power to set voting qualifications, giving alternative a. Figures (1a) and (1b) show the resulting FM and OS agenda trees under Anglo-American (or Congressional) procedure. Because this agenda is pairwise, the FM and OS definitions of sincere voting are equivalent. On the initial question of accepting the amendment, OS say that a sincere voter votes for his preferred of the two ostensive alternatives a and b, while FM say that a sincere voter votes for his preferred of the two challenged alternatives a and b. Now let s consider Euro-Latin procedure (or Sequential Procedure and Agenda Example 9 in Miller, 1995), which is essentially the same example shown in Figure 1 of Miller (2010) but with the fourth alternative q removed. Let s suppose the first question to be voted is whether to have popular election of Senators with voting qualification set by Congress, i.e., whether to accept alternative a. If the yeas have it, a wins and that s the end of it; otherwise, the second question is whether to have popular election of Senators with voting qualifications set by states, i.e., whether to accept alternative b. If the yeas have it, b wins; otherwise, c wins by default. Figure (2a) shows

Agendas and Sincerity page 4 the FM agenda tree, while Figure (2b) shows (what I believe Schwartz would consider to be) the OS agenda. Because this agenda is not pairwise (all three alternative being challenged at the first vote), the FM and OS definitions of sincere voting conflict for some voters. On the initial question of accepting alternative a, FM say that a sincere voter must somehow choose between a and the set {b,c}. This leaves a sincere voter in something of a dilemma if a is his middle preference. Farquharson resolves this dilemma by defining sincerity in maximax terms, i.e., a sincere voter votes nay (i.e., for {b,c}) if either b or c is his first preference, and Miller (1995 and elsewhere) follows Farquharson in this respect. OS avoid this dilemma by stipulating that c is the ostensive alternative with which a is paired in the first vote. If pressed, I would probably also designate c as the ostensive alternative rather than b, but I m not sure what general principle rationalizes this designation, and in my earlier response I suggested that a sincere voter might plausibly view the first vote either as a choice between a and b or between a and c. Next let s consider another procedure for which the agenda tree has the same structure as that for Euro-Latin procedure but, reflecting the different way in which questions are posed, differs with respect to how alternatives are assigned to bottom nodes. (This is Successive Procedure and Agenda Example 8 in Miller, 1995, and this is also how Farquharson himself interpreted successive procedure in Farquharson, 1966) Here the first vote is on the question of principle of whether the Senators should be popularly elected. If the nays have it, c wins and that s the end of it; otherwise legislative selection is rejected in favor of popular election, and the mode of popular election is decided at the second vote. Figure (3a) shows the FM agenda tree, while Figure (3b) attempts to show the OS agenda tree. But here it seems even less clear how to assign the ostensive alternative that sincere voters are to compare c with at the first vote. Finally, let s consider an issue-by-issue agenda, such as Agenda Example 7 in Miller (1995). Members of a club must decide what kind of banquet to give and two questions have been raised: Question 1: Question 2: Shall the dress be formal or informal? Shall the cuisine be French or Mexican? These two questions generate four alternatives: a: formal dress with French cuisine; b: informal dress with French cuisine; c: formal dress with Mexican cuisine; and d: informal dress with Mexican cuisine. If the questions are voted on in numerical order, the FM agenda is (4a) in Figure 1. (If the questions were voted on in reverse order, the tree structure would be the same but the assignment of alternatives to bottom nodes would change.) FM s maximax sincere voting is clearly defined (as is more prudential minimax voting). But, given that voters may have preferences that are nonseparable by issues, I have no idea what the ostensive alternatives are at either intermediate node in (4b), so (it seems to me that) OS sincere voting in this case is not defined at all I conclude with two points. In my view, sincere voters vote as if they are entirely ignorant of the preferences of other voters. But this does not preclude a voter from voting sincerely (or in

Agendas and Sincerity page 5 some other way that is neither sincere nor strategic) even if he knows the preferences of other voters, in order to please his constituents or conscience. Second, I want to highlight but also qualify the characterization of insincere voting that I previously relegated to a footnote: a sincere voter votes as if he were a dictator in the social choice sense or, more generally, as if he believes his vote will (somehow) be decisive at every division and who therefore does not need to know anything about the preferences of other voters. I said that such a dictator is sincere in the FM sense, not the OS sense. This characterization identifies a unique voting strategy under any partition agenda (in which every surviving alternatives is challenged at every vote) like (2a), (3a), and (4a) in Figure 1, and this is sincere voting in the FM sense. But under a non-partition amendment agenda like (1a), the dictator characterization may not identify a unique voting strategy, since some outcomes (e.g., c) can be reached by different voting paths, but it always includes sincere voting in the FM sense. And of course, under such pairwise agendas, the FM and OS definitions of sincere voting are equivalent NOTE. There is an error in Miller (2010). The last line of the paragraph that continues onto p. [7] should say maximax fashion, not minimax fashion. References Farquharson, R. (1966). On the Application of Game Theory to Committee Procedure, in Operational Research and the Social Sciences, ed. by J. R. Lawrence. London: Tavistock Publications. Farquharson, R. (1969). Theory of Voting. New Haven: Yale University Press. Groseclose, T., and K. Krebiel (1993). On the Pervasiveness of Sophisticated Sincerity, in Political Economy: Institutions, Competition, and Representation, ed. by W. A. Barnett, M. J. Hinich, and N. J. Schofield. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Miller, N. R. (1995). Committees, Agendas, and Voting. London: Harwood Academic Publishers. Miller, N. R. (2010). Agenda Trees and Sincere Voting: A Response to Schwartz. Public Choice, 145, xx-xx Ordeshook, P. C., and T. Schwartz (1987). Agendas and the Control of Political Outcomes. American Political Science Review, 81: 179-199. Schwartz, T. (2008). Parliamentary Procedure: Principal Forms and Political Effects. Public Choice, 136: 353-377. Schwartz, T. (2010). Reply to Miller on Agendas and Sincerity. Public Choice, 145: yy-yy.

Agendas and Sincerity page 6