John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

Similar documents
John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Reconciling Educational Adequacy and Equity Arguments Through a Rawlsian Lens

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

VI. Rawls and Equality

Assignment to make up for missed class on August 29, 2011 due to Irene

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

In Defense of Liberal Equality

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

Distributive vs. Corrective Justice

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

Pos 419Z Seminar in Political Theory: Equality Left and Right Spring Peter Breiner

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

The Veil of Ignorance in Rawlsian Theory

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

Great Philosophers: John Rawls ( ) Brian Carey 13/11/18

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Economic Perspective. Macroeconomics I ECON 309 S. Cunningham

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY

Chapter 02 Business Ethics and the Social Responsibility of Business

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality

Distributive Justice Rawls

Political Obligation 3

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

ECON 4270 Distributive Justice Lecture 4: Rawls and liberal equality

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

1 Aggregating Preferences

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Do we have a moral obligation to the homeless?

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

At a time when political philosophy seemed nearly stagnant, John Rawls

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

Theories of Justice to Health Care

University of Alberta

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Ross s view says that the basic moral principles are about prima facie duties. Ima Rossian

Social Contract Theory

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

Justice as fairness The social contract

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Justice as Fairness. John Rawls RESTATEMENT HARVARD U N I V E R S I T Y PRESS

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac

Libertarianism and the Justice of a Basic Income. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri at Columbia

1. Free trade refers to a situation where a government does not attempt to influence through quotas

3. Because there are no universal, clear-cut standards to apply to ethical analysis, it is impossible to make meaningful ethical judgments.

1100 Ethics July 2016

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

JUSTICE, NON-VIOLENCE, AND THE PRACTICE OF POLITICAL JUDGMENT: A STUDY OF RICOEUR S CONCEPTION OF JUSTICE YANG-SOO LEE

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

What is the Relationship Between The Idea of the Minimum and Distributive Justice?

Theories of Justice. Is economic inequality unjust? Ever? Always? Why?

Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings, and Contemporary Issues Third Edition Bruce N. Waller. Copyright 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.

Political Justice, Reciprocity and the Law of Peoples

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

19 ECONOMIC INEQUALITY. Chapt er. Key Concepts. Economic Inequality in the United States

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

The political problem of economic inequality and the perils of redistribution.

Are Second-Best Tariffs Good Enough?

MAXIMIZING THE MINIMAL STATE: TOWARD JUSTICE THROUGH RAWLSIAN-NOZICKIAN COMPATIBILITY. Timothy Betts. Submitted in partial fulfillment of the

Topic 1: Moral Reasoning and ethical theory

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

AN ASSESSMENT OF COHEN'S CRITIQUE ON RAWLS: IS THE EGALITARIAN ETHOS EMBEDDED IN THE RAWLSIAN SOCIETY?

Towards a Global Civil Society. Daniel Little University of Michigan-Dearborn

Transcription:

From the SelectedWorks of Greg Hill 2010 John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition Greg Hill Available at: https://works.bepress.com/greg_hill/3/

The Difference Principle and the Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition I. Introduction II. The Difference Principle and the Strains of Commitment III. Utilitarianism IV. Libertarianism V. The Psychology of Reciprocity VI. Conclusion

2 I. INTRODUCTION Teaching philosophy to students majoring in physics, chemistry, computer science, or even economics poses unique challenges. Difficulties can arise when trying to convey philosophical ideas that bear little relation to the work these students are doing in their other courses. There are, however, some concepts in our discipline that can be conveyed in ways that draw on the skills acquired by students who are comfortable employing the methods of math and science, and, with luck, these young scientists may find themselves in a position to make a distinctive contribution to their fellow students (and perhaps to their teachers as well). One such concept is John Rawls s notion of the strains of commitment, which plays an important, if little analyzed, role in Rawls s critique of Utilitarianism and in his argument for the Difference Principle. In this essay, I present Rawls s argument through a series of diagrams displaying the relationship between the distribution of income, on the one hand, and the strains of commitment among various groups of citizens under alternative conceptions of justice, on the other. In addition, I show how strains-of-commitment-type considerations can be brought to bear in evaluating Utilitarianism and Libertarianism using this same diagrammatic device, an exercise that brings into clearer view some important aspects of justice as fairness and its principal rivals. II. THE DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE AND THE STRAINS OF COMMITMENT Rawls s theory of justice is built around a thought experiment. We are asked to imagine that parties in an original position are to choose the principles that will govern the fundamental terms of social cooperation. 1 In light of the finality of the decision they are to make, Rawls stipulates that the parties must choose principles they will be able to willingly affirm no matter what their place in the distribution of social and natural

3 endowments. Put the other way around, the parties must reject principles that could give rise to obligations they could not discharge without rancor or resentment, that is to say, principles that would create excessive strains of commitment. 2 One of Rawls s main arguments against Utilitarianism is that those citizens whose interests are sacrificed in order to maximize the net balance of benefits would find it difficult to willingly embrace policies that served this objective. For example, while a majority of citizens might prefer that certain religions be suppressed, the parties in the original position would not adopt a principle of selective suppression because any one of them might turn out to be a member of an unpopular religious sect and could not willingly acquiesce in the suppression of their deeply-held beliefs. In a similar fashion, the parties would insist upon equality of opportunity in employment because, even if discrimination in employment turned out to be economically efficient, citizens who were discriminated against could not willingly accept their unequal treatment even if it meant greater incomes for the majority of citizens. In light of these and other considerations, Rawls argues that an equal right to the basic liberties and fair equality of opportunity must be (in this order) the fundamental principles of a just state. In thinking through the principles that should guide the economic organization of a just state, Rawls again rejects Utilitarianism because the application of its greatest good for the greatest number criterion could leave some citizens impoverished if their adverse condition were the by-product of economic arrangements that produced greater benefits for the vast majority of citizens. Instead, Rawls contends that the parties would select the Difference Principle, which sanctions inequalities of wealth and income only insofar as they work to the long-run advantage of the least well off. According to Rawls, the Difference Principle would produce much

4 weaker strains of commitment than Utilitarianism because the terms of social cooperation sanctioned by this principle are consistent with the psychology of reciprocity, which Rawls regards as a powerful motive deeply rooted in human nature. 3 More specifically, the main argument Rawls develops in favor of the Difference Principle runs as follows. The parties in the original position, who do not know their place in the distribution of social and natural advantages, and who represent citizens as free and equal, begin their deliberations about the basic terms of social cooperation by assuming that the benefits of social cooperation are to be equally distributed. Starting from this baseline, the parties then consider the gains that could be achieved for everyone if unequal shares were offered as an incentive for especially productive effort, innovation, risk taking, and the like. The parties continue to reason in this vein, examining the consequences of marginal increases in inequality until they reach a point where further increases in inequality no longer work to everyone s advantage. Inequality in excess of this threshold will only raise the income of more productive citizens at the expense of less productive citizens. Since the parties must be able to meet their public responsibilities no matter what their place in the distribution of social and natural advantages, they focus their attention on the income of the least well off, and therefore select the degree of inequality that maximizes the income of this group. This line of reasoning is depicted in figure one, which displays the income of a representative citizen among the least advantaged group (on the horizontal axis) in relation to the degree of income inequality in the political community (on the vertical axis). (In all that follows, I shall always be referring to either the representative citizen, or to the average income, of some group). According to Rawls s account, we are to envision the parties beginning at the origin, where income shares are equal, and then

5 gradually moving up the income-inequality curve in the direction of the arrows until they reach the point at which the income of the least well off reaches its maximum, where we find the Difference Principle. Figure 1 Income Inequality and the Income of the Least Well Off High Degree of Inequality DP ineq Difference Principle Low Equal shares DP inc Low Income of the Least Well Off High In figure one, the points, DP ineq and DP inc, designate, respectively, the degree of inequality and the income of the least well off, under the Difference Principle. Any further increase in inequality above DP ineq reduces the income of the least well off. Since Rawls assumes that everyone gains in the move from equal shares to the degree of inequality marked by the Difference Principle, and that the income of the least advantaged declines with any further increase in inequality, this version of Rawls s argument for the Difference Principle has been called the Pareto interpretation. 4

6 III. Utilitarianism and the Strains of Commitment Although the income of the least advantaged declines as inequality increases beyond the threshold marked by the Difference Principle, Rawls assumes that the income of more favored citizens (not shown in figure one) continues to rise as the degree of inequality increases. To illustrate this relationship, figure two displays the average income of the least well off group (LWO) and the average income of all other citizens, the non-least well off (NLWO), under varying degrees of inequality. For purposes of comparison, I ve shown two principles of distribution, the Difference Principle and Utilitarianism. Figure 2 Income of the Least Well Off (LWO) and All Others (NLWO) under Alternative Principles High LWO NLWO Utilitarianism Degree of Inequality Difference Principle Low Equal shares Low L U L D A D A U Income High In figure two, the income of the least well off (LWO) and the average income of all other citizens (NLWO) are both represented on the horizontal axis. The points, L U and L D, designate the income of the least well off (LWO) under Utilitarianism and the

7 Difference Principle, respectively. Similarly, the points A U and A D designate the average income of all other citizens (NLWO) under Utilitarianism and the Difference Principle, respectively. Note that in moving up the income inequality curve from the Difference Principle to Utilitarianism, the income of the least well off declines from L D to L U, whereas the average income of the remaining population rises from A D to A U, an amount that exceeds the lost income of the LWO by a considerable amount. There are many reasons why this is likely to be the case, but the one most relevant to our concerns is that the gains made possible by incentives exceeding those sanctioned by the Difference Principle would increase the income of many citizens while decreasing the income of only a few, a trade off sanctioned by the Utilitarian objective of maximizing the greatest good for the greatest number. 5 Looking at figure two, some students may ask why the parties in the original position would choose the Difference Principle rather than Utilitarianism in light of the fact that, given certain additional, but plausible, premises, Utilitarianism promises greater expected income (and even greater expected utility) than the Difference Principle. 6 One of Rawls s arguments against this conclusion is that Utilitarianism and, more specifically, the aim of maximizing expected (i.e., probability-weighted) utility, is not an appropriate decision rule in the circumstances of the original position. In the first place, Rawls emphasizes that the parties do not have sufficient information to attach probabilities to possible outcomes; hence they cannot estimate expected values. 7 Looking back at figure two, and bearing in mind Rawls s assumption that the parties in the original position don t know their place in the distribution of natural and social endowments, we can interpret this requirement by stipulating that the parties don t know whether they are on the LWO or the NLWO curve, i.e., whether they belong to the least well off group or not.

8 Secondly, Rawls insists that the parties, who are conceived as moral persons, have very little interest in income above some minimal standard, so that the marginal value of income diminishes rapidly once this threshold is reached. 8 In addition to the foregoing arguments, Rawls also makes a case for the superiority of the Difference Principle over Utilitarianism by introducing considerations that revolve around the strains of commitment. Since the parties choosing principles of justice know they cannot enter into agreements that may have consequences they cannot accept, they must consider the strains of commitment, weighing with care whether they will be able to stick by their commitment in all circumstances. 9 Although the parties have only a general knowledge of human psychology to go on, Rawls insists that this information is enough to tell which conception of justice involves the greater stress. 10 To begin with, Rawls argues that this knowledge is sufficient to reject Utilitarianism because the principle of utility may require that the interests of some citizens be sacrificed in order to advance the interests of others. Consequently, a social system organized around the principle of utility will not be stable unless those who must make sacrifices strongly identify with interests broader than their own. 11 Although Rawls allows that sympathy and benevolence can be called upon to prompt sacrifices from time to time, he contends that these motives are not strong enough to prompt willing sacrifices from the same groups on an ongoing basis. By contrast, Rawls argues that the Difference Principle would not give rise to such intense strains of commitment. His argument rests on the following three claims: 1) any degree of inequality greater than that sanctioned by the Difference Principle would allow the more favored to gain at the expense of the least favored, thereby coming into conflict with the psychology of reciprocity, which Rawls regards as a deep and, most

9 likely, permanent, part of human nature; 2) since the least favored do as well as possible under the Difference Principle, they have no reason for complaint; and 3) since those more favored by nature do even better than the least favored, they, too, have no reason for complaint. These ideas are illustrated in figure three, which displays the strains of commitment among the least well off (LWO) and among all other citizens (NLWO). Although figure three resembles figure two, it s important to recognize that the intensity of the strains of commitment (SOC) replaces income on the horizontal axis, so the SOC become weaker as we move rightward along this axis (whereas, in figure two, income increases as we move rightward along the horizontal axis.) Figure 3 Strains of Commitment under Alternative Principles High LWO NLWO Utilitarianism Degree of Inequality Difference Principle Low Equal shares L U L D A D A U High Strains of Commitment Low

Two aspects of figure three deserve emphasis. First, notice that the strains of commitment are greater for the least well off (LWO) than for the more favored (NLWO) at every point north of the origin, that is, under all distributions except the baseline of equal shares. This is because the strains of commitment decrease as a citizen s absolute income increases, and the least well off (LWO), by definition, always have less income than others. Second, it s important to stress that the strains of commitment among the least well off (LWO) increase at any point above that marked by the Difference Principle for two reasons, first because their income decreases when inequality exceeds this threshold, and second because the more favored gain at their expense, which, by coming into conflict with the psychology of reciprocity, gives rise to resentment and perhaps even a diminution of self-respect. Since Rawls s strains of commitment argument is directed mainly against Utilitarianism, it may be fruitful to ask how a Utilitarian might respond to this argument. One natural reply would be to deny the relevance of the strains of commitment as an independent consideration in the design of society s most fundamental institutions. For an unabashed Utilitarian, the strains of commitment command attention only insofar as this stress involves a cost, or disutility, which must be included in calculating the net benefits of the alternatives under consideration. Having insisted on this point, the Utilitarian may go on to argue that Rawls has underestimated the strength of our capacity for sympathy, that is, our willingness to incur costs so that others may enjoy greater benefits, a capacity which, it may be added, could be further strengthened by education and other means. 12 According to this understanding, the difference between the strains of commitment among the least well off under the Difference Principle, on the one hand, and under Utilitarianism, on the other, could be less than Rawls imagines. Specifically,

11 the strains of commitment curve for the least well off (LWO) in figure three would be less backward-bending where it exceeds the threshold level of inequality marked by the Difference Principle. Although this response, assuming its premises are granted, weakens the force of Rawls s strains of commitment argument in favor of the Difference Principle, it s worth mentioning that the income distribution consistent with Utilitarianism, insofar as the Utilitarian takes Rawls s notion of the strains of commitment seriously (at least as a cost that must be taken into account), would perhaps be more egalitarian than would be the case in the absence of this consideration. We can take a further step along this path if we abandon the strict Utilitarian doctrine and accept Rawls s notion that the strains of commitment must not be excessive for any group. In this case, the parties in the original position may find the notion of Utilitarianism with a Social Minimum (as proposed by Jeremy Waldron) an appealing alternative to the Difference Principle. 13 For the addition of a social minimum to an otherwise straightforward Utilitarianism would go a considerable distance toward addressing Rawls s claim that Utilitarianism would create excessive strains of commitment among the least well off. In figure three above, Utilitarianism with a Social Minimum could be represented by a horizontal line lying between the lines representing Utilitarianism and the Difference Principle, allowing greater inequality than the Difference Principle, but less than unrestricted Utilitarianism, while generating greater average income than the Difference Principle and a higher minimum than Utilitarianism. Nevertheless, the Rawlsian may insist, any degree of inequality greater than that sanctioned by the Difference Principle would come into conflict with the psychology of reciprocity and on this ground alone would produce unacceptable strains of commitment

12 among the least well off. We shall consider this argument more closely below, but first let s turn to an entirely different view about the strains of commitment and their bearing upon the hypothetical choice to be made in the original position. IV. Libertarianism and the Strains of Commitment Rawls s most famous libertarian critic, Robert Nozick, argues that under the Difference Principle the strains of commitment experienced by the most well off would, in fact, be greater than the strains experienced by the least well off because the income of the most well off under the Difference Principle is much less than it would be under a variety of alternative principles, but most especially Laissez Faire. 14 According to Nozick, the proper baseline for comparison is not equal shares, but rather whatever distribution would result from the free exchange of justly acquired goods. Looking at figure four below for reference, the proponents of Laissez Faire would argue that (within Rawls s strains-ofcommitment framework), the correct starting point for measuring gains and losses is whatever degree of inequality would result from just acquisition and free exchange under the policy of Laissez Faire. 15 And beginning from this starting point, it is obvious that the most favored lose at the expense of the least favored as we move down the inequality-income curve from Laissez Faire to the Difference Principle. In the libertarian view, therefore, the Difference Principle, by imposing heavy losses upon the most favored, would create more powerful strains of commitment among this group than among the least well off. We will examine this claim in more detail later, but first let s give diagrammatic expression to the moral psychology at work in the libertarian argument. Figure four displays the strains of commitment for the least well off (LWO) and the most well off (MWO) groups under Laissez Faire and under the Difference Principle.

13 Figure 4 Strains of Commitment in the Moral Psychology of Libertarian Theorists High Laissez Faire LWO MWO Degree of Inequality Difference Principle Low Equal shares L L M D L D M L Low Strains of Commitment High In the libertarian version of the strains of commitment depicted in figure four, the group that experiences the greatest stress depends on which principle of distribution is adopted. Under Laissez Faire, the least well off (LWO) experience the greatest strains, marked by L L, because their income is significantly less than it would be under the Difference Principle, that is, at L D. Contrariwise, under the Difference Principle, the most well off (MWO) face the greatest strains because their income, at M D, is significantly less than it would be under Laissez Faire, that is, at M L. It s worth underscoring the crucial significance of the baseline against which gains and losses are measured. For Rawls, the appropriate baseline for free and equal citizens is equal income shares, whereas for Nozick, it is whatever distribution arises from the combination of just appropriation and free exchange. 16 V. The Psychology of Reciprocity

14 Let s take a closer look at Rawls s conception of reciprocity, as it plays an important role in his argument for the Difference Principle. In figures three and four, the strains of commitment among the least well off gradually decrease as their income rises, and then gradually increase as the degree of inequality exceeds the threshold sanctioned by the Difference Principle, and their income falls. But Rawls s characterization of the psychology of reciprocity, in combination with his view that the more favored gain at the expense of the least favored when inequality exceeds the threshold prescribed by the Difference Principle, suggests that there is a discontinuous break in the strains of commitment among the least well off at the point where inequality exceeds this threshold. This notion is illustrated in figure five, which displays the strains of commitment among the least well off (LWO) under Laissez Faire and the Difference Principle. Figure 5 Strains of Commitment among the Least Well Off Under Rawls s Moral Psychology High Laissez Faire Degree of Inequality Difference Principle Exploitation Cooperation Low Equal L L L D Shares High Strains of Commitment Low

15 In figure five, the strains of commitment among the least well off gradually diminish as the degree of inequality increases up to the threshold marked by the Difference Principle, that is, L D. Beyond this threshold, which marks the endpoint of mutually advantageous cooperation, there is a sharp, discontinuous increase in the strains of commitment among the least well off because any increase in inequality beyond this point means that, in Rawls s conception, one segment of the community gains at the expense of another. And this state of affairs, in turn, comes into conflict with the psychology of reciprocity, thereby creating powerful strains of commitment among a group that not only has less income than any other group, but, from Rawls s perspective, makes sacrifices that benefit those who are already more favored. Notice that the curve representing the strains of commitment among the least well off (LWO) is convex above the Difference Principle, which means that the strains of commitment rise even faster in this region, as if additional inequality beyond the Difference Principle rubs salt into the wounds of the least well off. Under the Difference Principle, by contrast, everyone benefits from the resulting scheme of cooperation, (so that the discontinuous segment of the psychology of reciprocity-driven strains of commitment does not come into play). Since, in Rawls s words, everyone s good is affirmed, all acquire inclinations to uphold this scheme. 17 This argument is not entirely satisfying. We may agree with Rawls that the psychology of reciprocity is a deep part of our nature, and that we tend to develop loyalties to people and institutions that advance our good. But Rawls gives us no reason to think that in judging whether a particular relationship or social arrangement advances our good, we naturally assume a baseline of equal shares against which we measure our gains and losses. One can easily envision relationships of reciprocity in which the

16 benefits accruing to each participant are not measured in relation to any recognizably egalitarian baseline. For example, consider a voluntary association where, in Rawls s words, the members view one another as equals, as friends and associates, joined together in a system of cooperation known to be for the advantage of all and governed by a common conception of justice. 18 Although association members may fulfill their responsibilities because they enjoy advantages as members of the association, there is no reason to believe these benefits are measured, even informally, against some kind of equal shares baseline, rather than against, say, the advantages a person might enjoy as a member of a different association, or simply by spending more time with one s family. 19 More generally, we can say that among competing conceptions of justice that specify different baselines for the purpose of assessing gains and losses, appeals to reciprocity are question-begging because they presuppose precisely what is at issue, that is, the baseline against which costs and benefits are to be measured. In Rawls s argument, everyone can be said to benefit from the adoption of the Difference Principle, provided 1) we start from the equal shares baseline, 2) move up the income-inequality curve by small increments, and 3) never cross the inequality threshold marked by the Difference Principle. For Nozick, on the other hand, the Difference Principle is not a principle of reciprocity because it transfers income from the more productive to the less productive, thereby leaving the first group worse off when measured against a baseline in which privately owned assets have been justly acquired. Laissez faire, on this view, gives reign to reciprocity because exchanges are voluntary and therefore typically work to the advantage of contracting parties. This debate is not really about which institutional arrangement is consistent with our propensity to reciprocate, but about the appropriate baseline from which to assess gains and losses. 20 The real work in Rawls s argument for

17 the Difference Principle is being done by the equal shares baseline, the assumption of rationality, and the considerations Rawls brings to bear in their defense, and not by the psychology of reciprocity, which, in Rawls s account, is part of our natural constitution, but which, we have argued, does not necessarily embody an egalitarian baseline. This point helps us to appreciate Rawls s remark that it is hard to imagine any conception other than the Difference Principle that would satisfy the reciprocity condition. Yes, of course, provided we start from a baseline of equal shares. 21 VI. CONCLUSION A diagrammatic presentation of Rawls s arguments concerning the strains of commitment serves two purposes. In the first place, it is an alternative way of illustrating some of the basic premises and arguments of Rawls s conception of justice as fairness. In fact, some interesting nuances in Rawls s theory can be brought out simply by focusing upon the shape of the curves displayed above. Secondly, these diagrams may be especially helpful to students who are unfamiliar with philosophical discourse, but comfortable with the graphical representation of concepts. Although the deepest questions about the nature of justice do not revolve around diagrams, these figures may, hopefully, facilitate discussion about the first principles of political philosophy.

18 Endnotes 1 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, chapter III. Also see Rawls, Justice as Fairness: a Restatement, pp. 14-24. 2 See A Theory of Justice, pp. 176-183 3 See ibid., pp. 102 ff. 4 The claim that everyone benefits from inequality up to the point marked by the Difference Principle requires a further premise, which Rawls calls the chain connection. Rawls also refers to it as a Kantian justification of the Difference Principle because no person uses another as a mean, that is to say, no one gains at the expense of someone else. A Theory of Justice, pp. 81-83, 251-257. 5 Strictly speaking, income must be translated into utility before balancing gains and losses. In addition, the diminishing utility of income imposes an egalitarian constraint on distributional alternatives. 6 Such assumptions would include the premise that the probability of being among the least favored is low in comparison with the probability of not belonging to this group. 7 Moreover, Rawls argues, there are strong reasons against even the default position wherein all outcomes are assumed to be equally likely. 8 To be sure, this premise does not fit comfortably with the theory of incentives that supports the operation of the Difference Principle. 9 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 176. 10 Ibid. 11 Ibid., pp. 177-178. 12 Cf. G. E. Cohen, If You re an Egalitarian, How Come You re So Rich? Chapters 8-10. 13 See Jeremy Waldron, John Rawls and the Social Minimum, in Waldron, Liberal Rights, 1981-1991. 14 See Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia. 15 It may be noted that the appropriate starting point, laissez faire, is also the correct ending point from the libertarian vantage point. 16 It s harder to say what Utilitarianism s comparable baseline would be, for while Utilitarians claim to treat everyone s interests equally, I cannot find a line of reasoning that leads from here to an equal shares baseline, nor to an equal utility baseline, nor, finally, to anything resembling the libertarian baseline.

19 17 A Theory of Justice, p. 177. 18 Ibid., p. 472. 19 To avoid misunderstanding, I should emphasize that the issue in this instance is not whether equal shares is the morally appropriate baseline, but rather whether this baseline, and the gains and losses measured in relation to it, constitute the reference point in terms of which the psychology of reciprocity is activated or not. 20 To summarize, appeals to the psychology of reciprocity only carry weight if the competing principles under consideration specify the same baseline for measuring gains and losses. What is left of Rawls s strains-of-commitment argument in favor the Difference Principle if it turns out that the natural psychology of reciprocity cannot be plausibly harnessed to Rawls s equal shares baseline? Rawls could still argue that the strains of commitment decrease as a citizen s absolute income increases and therefore the Difference Principle, which maximizes the income of the least well off, necessarily minimizes the strains of commitment in comparison with any alternative principle. Although this fallback position is straightforward, it does not carry the same force as Rawls s original argument, which includes the additional strain that would arise if, under greater inequality than that sanctioned by the DP, the more well off gain at the expense of the least well off. 21 Rawls, Justice as Fairness: a Restatement, p. 124. References Cohen, G. E. If You re an Egalitarian, How Come You re So Rich? (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001). Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1977). Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971). Rawls, John. Justice as Fairness: a Restatement (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001). Waldron, Jeremy. Liberal Rights, Collected Essays 1981-1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.