Wealth. Munich Personal RePEc Archive. Ferdinando Meacci. University of Padova

Similar documents
University of Manitoba Department of Economics. ECON 4050 HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT I Fall Term

INTERNATIONAL TRADE & ECONOMICS LAW: THEORIES OF INTERNATIONAL TRADE AND ECONOMICS

Keynes as an Interpreter of Classical Economics

ECON 5060/6060 History of Economic Doctrines

Social Capital as Patterns of Connections. A Review of Bankston s Immigrant Networks and Social Capital

PAPER No. : Basic Microeconomics MODULE No. : 1, Introduction of Microeconomics

Classical Political Economy. Week 2 University i of Wollongong

Syllabus. History of Economic Doctrines. Economics Fall Semester Hours Class: MW 3:00-4:30. Instructor: John Watkins

Classical Political Economy. Part II. J. B. Say & T. Malthus

Ricardo the Logician versus Tooke the Empiricist : on their different vital contributions to classical economics. Matthew Smith

Late pre-classical economics (ca ) Mercantilism (16th 18th centuries) Physiocracy (ca ca. 1789)

Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, 1776

Chapter 2 Comparative Advantage

R. Jones, An Essay on the Distribution of Wealth and on the Sources of Taxation, John Pullen. No January 2001

A Shrinking Universe How Corporate Power Shapes Inequality

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS. Economics 3214

From The Wealth of Nations

Ricardo: real or supposed vices? A Comment on Kakarot-Handtke s paper Paolo Trabucchi, Roma Tre University, Economics Department

Economics 555 Potential Exam Questions

David Ricardo on natural and market prices

How Cantillon and Hume Propose the Same. Theory of First-Round Effects

Fall 2013 AP/ECON 4059 A History of Economic Thought I

Course Title. Professor. Contact Information

A CRITIQUE OF JOHN LOCKE AND THE VALUE OF MONEY OISÍN GILMORE. Senior Sophister

ECON 5060/6060 History of Economic Doctrines

The Two Conflicting Approaches to the Concept of Capital within Economic Thought

Economic history What was mercantilism?

David Ricardo ( )

Classical Political Economy. Part I. Adam Smith

LECTURE 5: CLASSICAL POLITICAL ECONOMY. Dr. Aidan Regan Website: Twitter: #CapitalUCD

1. At the completion of this course, students are expected to: 2. Define and explain the doctrine of Physiocracy and Mercantilism

Classical Political Economy. Part III. D. Ricardo

THE CREEDY COLLECTION OF IMPORTANT ECONOMICS BOOKS

Why do Countries Trade? Part II

Individualism. Marquette University. John B. Davis Marquette University,

RICARDO ON AGRICULTURAL IMPROVEMENTS: A NOTE

The Cambridge Contribution to the Revival of Classical Political Economy Abstract

Smith s and Ricardo s common logic of trade

Adam Smith s Discovery of Trade Gravity

1. Free trade refers to a situation where a government does not attempt to influence through quotas

Comparative advantage and the labor theory of value

The new economics of the brain drain

Essay #1: Smith & Malthus. to question the legacy of aristocratic, religious, and hierarchical institutions. The

Critiques on Mining and Local Corruption in Africa

John Stuart Mill ( )

Comparative Advantage : The Advantage of the Comparatively Powerful? J. Bradford DeLong Last edited:

Economic Thought of J B Say and J S Mill Episode 10

The textbook we will use is History of Economic Theory and Method by Ekelund R.B. and Hebert F.R. (EH) We will draw on a number of other readings.

Comments on Schnapper and Banting & Kymlicka

CLASSICAL THEORIES OF MONEY, OUTPUT AND INFLATION

Democracy and Justice

N I CH O LAS BAR BO N : AN T I CI P AT I N G T H E CLASSI CS

Schumpeter s Review of Frank A.

Classics of Political Economy POLS 1415 Spring 2013

Political Science The Political Theory of Capitalism Fall 2015

Organized by. In collaboration with. Posh Raj Pandey South Asia Watch on Trade, Economics & Environment (SAWTEE)

From Adam Smith to Mr Keynes: A Short History of Economic FFEC020H4ACB

Book Prospectus. The Political in Political Economy: from Thomas Hobbes to John Rawls

Malthus Ricardo Debate

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

An Attempt to Reshape Capitalism s Image

THEORIES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY: FROM SMITH TO SACHS MORSE ACADEMIC PLAN TEXTS AND IDEAS. 53 Washington Square South

WHAT S VALUE GOT TO DO WITH THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY? THE MULTIPLE MEANINGS OF VALUE THEORY IN MARX.

I. Rocco s Critique of Liberalism, Democracy and Socialism

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

Dr Kalecki on Mr Keynes

Planning versus Free Choice in Scientific Research

Classical Political Economy

Unit Outline* ECON3310. History of Economic Ideas. Semester 1, 2011 Campus: Crawley. Unit Coordinator Professor Michael McLure

PORTRAITS OF FRANCE FRENCH ECONOMICS (PT. I) Yann GIRAUD IEP SGEL

Why did economic systems begin to shift during the Industrial Revolution?

A History of Economic Theory

Adam Smith: Inspiration and Issues 1

Trade theory and regional integration

Book review: Capital in the Twenty-First Century/Le capital au XXI e siècle

AS-2606 B.COM. FIRST SEMESTER EXAMINATION, 2013 ELEMENTS OF ECONOMICS MODEL ANSWER

INTERNATIONAL LAW COMMISSION Sixty-eighth session Geneva, 2 May 10 June and 4 July 12 August 2016 Check against delivery

Law & Economics Lecture 1: Basic Notions & Concepts

The Rise of New Institutional Economics and Assessment its Contributions to the Post Washington Consensus

Sociology 3410: Early Sociological Theory

Marxian Economics. Capital : overview of the main topics and theses

Mises on the Nation and the State

Credit and the value of money, AMERICAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION, PUBLICATIONS, SERIES III, Vol. VI, 19-5.

The Ricardo Puzzle Francisco L. Lopes *

World Trade and World Money: A Neoricardian Outlook on Global Economy

MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

How, If At All, Has Adam Smith s Intentions to

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

A Comparison of the Theories of Joseph Alois Schumpeter and John. Maynard Keynes. Aubrey Poon

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

Marxism, the Millennium and Beyond

The Not-So-Destructive Scourge of Illegal Immigration

A Political Economy to Examine Brexit

Convictions Opposed to Certain Popular Opinions: The 1903 Anti- Protectionism Letter Supported by 16 British Economists

Misunderstanding Classical Economics? A Reply to Blaug. Pierangelo Garegnani

COURSE INFORMATION ECON 3008 History of Economic Thought 3 2 (January-May 2014) 3 ECON 1001and ECON 1002

I. Capital in the Neoclassical Theory. Some Notes *

Contract to pay dollars is a contract to pay coined silver

CAMBRIDGE MONETARY THOUGHT

Book Review: Collective Bargaining Law in Canada, by A. W. R. Carrothers

Transcription:

MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Wealth Ferdinando Meacci University of Padova 1998 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/14713/ MPRA Paper No. 14713, posted 19. April 2009 04:32 UTC

WEALTH by FERDINANDO MEACCI Università di Padova Wealth in itself -says Cantillon (1755, Ch.I)- is nothing but the Maintenance, Conveniences, and Superfluities of life. This definition, which is conspicuously quoted in two equally approving footnotes to a famous passage by Smith both in Cannan s and in Campbell and Skinner s editions of the Wealth of Nations (1776, Bk.I, Ch.V, n.1), is crucial in a number of senses. One is that, according to this definition, wealth in itself is made up of goods and not of money. The other is that the goods of which wealth consists are final rather than instrumental goods. Still another is that wealth is a flow of final goods rather than a stock of instrumental goods. Since, however, the meaning of this term has changed over time and since it is wealth that is said to be produced, distributed and consumed in the titles and contents of most treatises of political economy from, say, Turgot (1766) to J.S.Mill (1871), it is worthwhile to go deeper into Cantillon s definition for this paves the way for the notion of wealth that prevailed in classical political economy since Adam Smith. GOODS VS. MONEY All know, says J.S.Mill (1871, Vol. I, p.3), that the questions how a nation is made wealthy, and how it is made free, or virtuous, or eminent in literature, in the fine arts, in arms, or in polity, are totally distinct enquiries. But, he continues, some theorists and practical politicians have been equally and at one period universally infected by a mischievous confusion of ideas on the question concerning what is to be considered as wealth. The fault of these theorists (the Mercantilists) was to confuse, he argues, wealth with money. Not that this confusion was the result of a conceited terminology for, as Smith himself pointed out, that wealth consists in money, or in gold and silver, is a popular notion to the extent that the great affair, we always find, is to get money (Smith, 1776, Bk. IV, Ch.I). The fact is that the

Mercantilists identification of wealth with money, and of money with precious metals, was instrumental to, or associated with, their central belief that, the world amount of these metals being given at a given moment, the only way for a nation to become richer was to make another nation poorer. Thus Mill s argument highlights what Schumpeter calls a standard topic in the historiography of economics (1954, p. 361). This topic is due to Adam Smith. For it was Smith who first provided a systematic examination of the negative consequences of the Mercantilists initial confusion (1776, Bk. IV) as well as a positive theory of how the necessaries, conveniences and amusements of human life available in a nation can grow along with those of other nations. In this connection Schumpeter s argument that Smith s criticism of the Mercantile system is unintelligent on the grounds that even in the age of Mercantilism wealth was at times regarded as goods rather than as money is untenable. For Schumpeter seems to ignore, beyond the textual evidence he provides, the analytical foundations of Mercantilism (which is based on the principle that one nation s gain must be another nation s loss) and, with a stronger reason, the countervailing foundations of Smith s system of thought which is rather based on the notion that one nation s gain is compatible with, and may indeed be strengthened by, another nation s gain if only the principles of capital and competition were known and practiced in all nations. INDIVIDUAL VS. NATIONAL WEALTH The proposition that one nation s gain must be another nation s loss is the consequence of a still deeper confusion. This concerns the nature and causes of the wealth of an individual as distinct from the nature and causes of the wealth of the whole society (Smith, 1776; Lauderdale, 1804; and others). While saying that Mercantilists felt it was nice for a nation as well as for individuals to have money - and said so without thinking any more about it, Schumpeter (1954, p. 344) implicitly denies his own critique of Smith s criticism of the Mercantile system. For Smith knew very well that the great affair is to get money and devoted to this affair much more

thought than all Mercantilists put together in, to begin with, Book II of the Wealth of Nations. Here money is considered in the light of the theory of capital while capital is studied in the light of the distinction between the stock which a man possesses and the general stock of any country or society. In the wealth of mankind, says in this connection J. S. Mill (1871, p. 8), nothing is included which does not of itself answer some purpose of utility or pleasure. To an individual anything is wealth which, though useless in itself, enables him to claim from others a part of their stock of things useful or pleasant. The great affair of mankind, therefore, is to get (to produce) the goods rather than the money by which they are circulated from one individual to another. That the notion of wealth is strictly connected with the idea of production is as unclear in Cantillon s definition as it is clear in Smith s implicit use of it. For, to begin with, Smith s opening statement of the Wealth of Nations that the annual labour of every nation is the fund which originally supplies it with all the necessaries and conveniences of life which it annually consumes cannot apply to those necessaries and conveniences which are given by nature (and which are actually included in Cantillon s definition). This question was cleared up by Say (1843) through his distinction between richesses naturelles and richesses sociales: while the former comprise only the goods given by nature, the latter refer to the goods available only on condition that some labour be spent on their production. The idea of property (and therefore of exchange value) is associated with the latter, not with the former, form of wealth. Say s practical conclusion comes therefore to coincide with Smith s starting point: the subject of political economy is not wealth in itself but only that large and growing part of it which requires to be produced by labour. Thus wealth is most properly defined as all useful or agreeable things except those which can be obtained, in the quantity desired, without labour or sacrifice (J.S.Mill, 1871, p.10; see also McCulloch, 1864; Senior, 1836; Torrens, 1821; and others). The only qualification worth adding to this definition is that the necessaries, conveniences and amusements which result from the application of labour, and which therefore constitute wealth as the subject of political economy, need not consist, unlike what is

assumed in Malthus s definition (Malthus, 1827, p. 234), of material objects. For the element of utility (or desirability), which is essential to all articles of wealth (Senior, 1836; Say, 1843), belongs also to services (whether provided by durable goods or by labour itself). FINAL VS. INSTRUMENTAL GOODS Whether wealth is considered in itself or as the result of human exertions (i.e., in Smith s words, as the annual produce of the land and labour of the society ) it is generally unclear whether this term refers a) to final goods or to final plus instrumental goods, or b) to any of these two sets of goods at an instant or in a period of time. These questions will be dealt with, respectively, in the current and following sections. It should be noted, to begin with, that, in spite of the many passages where Smith argues that money makes no part like all other instruments of trade of the revenue of the society to which it belongs, he states in an isolated passage of Bk.I, Ch.XI of the Wealth of Nations that land [an instrument of production] constitutes by far the greatest, the most important, and the most durable part of the wealth of every extensive country. Since, however, the term revenue is repeatedly used by Smith as synonymous with wealth (with the result that land cannot be said to be part of the wealth of any country for the same reason why it cannot be said to be part of its revenue), his statement on land cannot be but a misleading synthesis of two alternative sentences. These sentences may be put as follows: a) the greatest, the most important, and the most durable part of the source of wealth of every extensive country ; and b) the greatest, the most important, and the most durable part of the wealth of individuals in every extensive country. If Smith s statement on land were split into, or interpreted according to, these two sentences its initial ambiguity would disappear. For one thing is the wealth of society; another the wealth of an individual. While in the case of an individual (which corresponds to sentence b above) wealth may well consist of (the possession of) land as much as of money and other instruments of trade, in the case of the wealth

of society (which corresponds to sentence a) wealth rather appears as the necessaries, conveniences and amusements of human life (final goods) available in a period of time. These necessaries etc. are said elsewhere to be the sole end and purpose both of the fixed and the circulating capitals (Smith, 1776, Bk.II, Ch.I, p.) and may be said, therefore and with a stronger reason, to be the sole end and purpose of land itself (as an instrument of production). This implies that all instruments (of trade or production) can be regarded as wealth only in the ellyptic sense of being sources of wealth or, to put it in terms that will become fashionable later on, only in so far as they are indirect or intermediate or inchoate wealth (Taussig, 1896); or, to put it in even more different terms, only in so far as they are wealth to come. That the wealth of the whole society is made up of final goods and that Smith is not inconsistent when he considers it as synonymous with national revenue is highlighted by the fact (noted by Max, Capital, Volume 2, Ch.19) that the term revenue, coming from the past participle revenu of the French verb revenir, denotes in itself something that returns. Unlike the term wealth, therefore, the term revenue is strictly connected with the idea of the reproduction of the necessaries, conveniences and amusements of human life (whether this does or does not require the production of intermediate wealth), namely with the notion that the necessaries etc. which are available in a country this year (and thus constitute the wealth of this year) are the direct or indirect outcome of the necessaries etc. (wages fund) which were exchanged for, and consumed by, the labour employed in past years. In this connection it may be added that the idea of revenue need not coincide with the very idea of income. For, if revenue denotes what returns, income more simply denotes what comes in. It may indeed be indifferent, from the point of view of an individual, whether the goods he receives this year are returning to him as a revenue, or simply coming to him as an income. And, since this may be even more indifferent to the taxman, it may well be that the notion of (individual) income was developed in political economy when the theory and practice of taxation (of income) became more

fashionable than the old classical, and more general, doctrine of reproduction (of wealth). From the point of view of society, however, the story is quite different -and has remained so even after classical economics went out of fashion. For, unless it consists only of richesses naturelles, the wealth of society must be annually reproduced before being subdivided between, and consumed by, its individual members as wages, profits and rents. STOCKS VS. FLOWS Whether the goods constituting wealth are considered at an instant or in a period of time is a question that can in turn be settled in the light of the distinction between the wealth of an individual and the wealth of the whole society (Pasinetti, 1977). The repeated use of the term annual in the passages where Smith deals with these concepts indicates by itself that the goods referred to by his expression wealth or revenue are to be considered in a period of time. On the other hand, since the wealth of an individual may well consist (as shown above) of (the possession of) goods that exist at an instant of time, the wealth that is said to be annual cannot be but the wealth (revenue) of society. And since the general aim of Smith and many other classics was to study the nature and causes of the wealth of nations, it follows with a stronger reason that the focus of their analysis was (the increase of) the flow of final goods available in a period (and made possible by using up the intermediate goods inherited from a previous period) rather than the stock, however formed, of instrumental goods (let alone the value of this stock) owned by individuals at an instant of time (assets). It is no chance, therefore, that when a subsequent generation of economists focused their attention on the wealth of individuals it was the notion of wealth as a stock of goods owned, in any form and for whatever reasons, at an instant of time that was brought to the forefront of economic analysis. The author who perfected this change of attitude was Irving Fisher (1906). The meaning of the term wealth was accordingly reformulated, first, in the sense that wealth was defined as material

objects owned by human beings and, secondly, in the sense that the income of an individual was said to consist of the services (a flow) provided by (or expected from) the wealth (a stock) owned by this individual at an instant of time (1906, Ch. XIII). Hence Fisher s new concept of capital (which is defined in this new context as a stock of wealth existing at an instant of time and, therefore, as everything but the wages fund of the classics) and his development of the concept of capital value (Meacci, 1989). This concept, which was not unknown to Smith (1776, Bk.V, Ch.II, Pt.II, Arts.I & II, App.), is defined in detail by Fisher as the net present value (calculated according to the principles of discounting) of the future income stream (or cash flows) expected from the stock of wealth owned by an individual in any form at an instant of time. References CANTILLON, R. (1755), Essai sur la nature du commerce en général, New York: Kelley FISHER, I. (1906), The Nature of Capital and Income, New York: Macmillan LAUDERDALE, J. M. (1804), An Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Public Wealth, Edinburgh: Constable MALTHUS, T.R. (1827), Definitions in Political Economy, New York: Kelley (1986) MCCULLOCH, J.R. (1864), The Principles of Political Economy, New York: Kelley (1965) MEACCI, F. (1989). Irving Fisher and the Classics on the Notion of Capital: Upheaval and Continuity in Economic Thought, History of Political Economy, 21:3, pp.409-24 MILL, J.S. (1871), Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy, Toronto: Toronto University Press (1965) PASINETTI L. (1977), Lectures on the Theory of Production, London: Macmillan RICARDO, D. (1821), Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, in P. Sraffa (ed.), The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1951-73 SAY, J.B. (1843), Cours complet d économie politique pratique, Rome: Edizioni Bizzarri (1968) SCHUMPETER, J.A. (1954), History of Economic Analysis, London: Routledge

SENIOR, N.W. (1836), An Outline of the Science of Political Economy, New York: Kelley (1965) SMITH, A. (1776), An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, Oxford: Clarendon Press (1976) TAUSSIG, F.W. (1896), Wages and Capital, London School of Economics Reprints, London: 1932 TORRENS, R. (1821), An Essay on the Production of Wealth, New York: Kelley TURGOT, A.R.J. (1766), Réflexions sur la formation et la distribution des richesses, New York: Kelley