Bi Zhaohui Kobe University, Japan. Abstract

Similar documents
Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy

Political Economy of Growth: Understanding Political Dynamics

Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. Cloth $35.

University of Southampton Research Repository eprints Soton

THREATS TO SUE AND COST DIVISIBILITY UNDER ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION. Alon Klement. Discussion Paper No /2000

Price volatility and the political economy of resource-rich nations

2 Political-Economic Equilibrium Direct Democracy

The Mandate of Heaven:

and Latin America in this regard is quite stark. Most Northern European countries extended the franchise during the late 19th and early 20th centuries

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

Political Change, Stability and Democracy

ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS

Contents. Acknowledgments

Econ 554: Political Economy, Institutions and Business: Solution to Final Exam

Political Selection and Persistence of Bad Governments

Illegal Migration and Policy Enforcement

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

A Theory of Independent Courts in Illiberal Democracies

Natural resources, aid, and democratization: A best-case scenario

How Dictators Forestall Democratization Using International Trade Policy 1

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 11 and 12. Information, Beliefs and Politics

Darmstadt Discussion Papers in Economics

A Political Economy Theory of Populism and Discrimination

Game theory and applications: Lecture 12

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

THE POLITICS OF PUBLIC PROVISION OF EDUCATION 1. Gilat Levy

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

3 Electoral Competition

Regime Change and Critical Junctures

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy

An Overview Across the New Political Economy Literature. Abstract

Rhetoric in Legislative Bargaining with Asymmetric Information 1

Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States. Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

Democratization and the Rule of Law

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

INEFFICIENT PUBLIC PROVISION IN A REPEATED ELECTIONS MODEL

Seminar in Political Economy: Institutional Change

Comparative Democratization

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES. No CONSENSUAL AND CONFLICTUAL DEMOCRATIZATION, RULE OF LAW, AND DEVELOPMENT

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

Part IIB Paper Outlines

IMPERFECT INFORMATION (SIGNALING GAMES AND APPLICATIONS)

Wisdom of the Crowd? Information Aggregation and Electoral Incentives

IDEOLOGICAL POLARISATION, COALITION GOVERNMENTS AND DELAYS IN STABILISATION. Chiara DALLE NOGARE *

4.1 Efficient Electoral Competition

A Theory of Competitive Authoritarian Elections

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability

University of Southern California Law School

The Real Swing Voter s Curse

Formal Models of Nondemocratic Politics

Candidate Citizen Models

Gerrymandering Decentralization: Political Selection of Grants Financed Local Jurisdictions Stuti Khemani Development Research Group The World Bank

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

Refinements of Nash equilibria. Jorge M. Streb. Universidade de Brasilia 7 June 2016

Optimal Voting Rules for International Organizations, with an. Application to the UN

DEMOCRACY AND DEVELOPMENT DR. RACHEL GISSELQUIST RESEARCH FELLOW, UNU-WIDER

Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Voter Turnout Agency. Political Economics. Ludwig-Maximilians University Munich. Summer term / 62

A Theory of Minimalist Democracy

Democracy and economic growth: a perspective of cooperation

Participatory Democracy

by Jim Dolmas and Gregory W. Huffman

CURRICULUM VITAE DARON ACEMOGLU

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES DEMOCRACY, REDISTRIBUTION AND INEQUALITY. Daron Acemoglu Suresh Naidu Pascual Restrepo James A. Robinson

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9: Political Agency

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION

Why are the transition paths in China and Eastern Europe different?

ECONS 491 STRATEGY AND GAME THEORY 1 SIGNALING IN THE LABOR MARKET

YOUTH, REVOLUTION, AND REPRESSION

Equilibrium Checks and Balances

Corruption and Political Competition

Princeton University Spring 2015 T. Romer. Politics 584/Economics 576 Foundations of Political Economy. Reading List

The Economic Origins of Democracy Reconsidered. John R. Freeman. University of Minnesota. Dennis P. Quinn. Georgetown University

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES LEFT, RIGHT, LEFT: INCOME, LEARNING AND POLITICAL DYNAMICS. John Morrow Michael Carter

POLITICAL SELECTION AND PERSISTENCE OF BAD GOVERNMENTS DARON ACEMOGLU GEORGY EGOROV KONSTANTIN SONIN

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

An Economic Theory of Leadership Turnover

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits

Bonn Econ Discussion Papers

Introduction. The Politician and the Judge: Accountability in Government

WORKING PAPER SERIES

Divide and Rule: An Origin of Polarization and Ethnic Conflict *

Department of Economics

To Segregate or to Integrate: Education Politics and Democracy

An example of public goods

Decentralization and Electoral Accountability: Incentives, Separation, and Voter Welfare

Working Paper No On the Role of Democracy in the Ethnicity Growth Relationship: Theory and Evidence

Technical Appendix for Selecting Among Acquitted Defendants Andrew F. Daughety and Jennifer F. Reinganum April 2015

Incentives for separation and incentives for public good provision

Partisan Competition, Growth and the Franchise

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE REAL SWING VOTER'S CURSE. James A. Robinson Ragnar Torvik. Working Paper

Electoral Economics in New Democracies: Affecting Attitudes About Democracy

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 12: Political Compromise

Oligarchic Versus Democratic Societies

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks

Transcription:

Income inequality, redistribution and democratization Bi Zhaohui Kobe University, Japan Abstract We consider that in a society, there are conflicts of income redistribution between the rich (class) and the poor (one), and the extent of income inequality creates conflict between these two groups in the society, bringing to a revolution aimed for more redistribution. In our model, we assume that there are two types of poor: weak and strong. The difference between the weak type and the strong type is that the later can win through a revolution, but the former can not. However, this is the private information of the poor and is not observed by the rich. When income inequality increases, with this asymmetry of information, the weak type of the poor is more likely to attempt a revolution. As a result, larger inequality results in higher probability of democratization. I am grateful for valuable comments from Associate Editor Richard McLean. And I would like to thank Taro Kumagai (Matsuyama University), Kaoru Ishiguro (Kobe University) and seminar participants for helpful comments. This paper has also been presented at the 2007 Spring meeting of Japanese Economic Association at Osaka Gakuin University and especially I am very grateful for the valuable comments and suggestions from Makoto Okamura (Hiroshima University). Citation: Zhaohui, Bi, (2007) "Income inequality, redistribution and democratization." Economics Bulletin, Vol. 4, No. 35 pp. 1-10 Submitted: August 10, 2007. Accepted: September 22, 2007. URL: http://economicsbulletin.vanderbilt.edu/2007/volume4/eb-07d70012a.pdf

1 Introduction The reasons some societies switch from nondemocracy to democracy are numerous. For example, the introduction of universal suffrage; certain ideological preferences over regimes (Diamond 1999); the importance of economic crises in triggering democratizations processes (Haggard and Kaufman 1995) and so on. In this paper, we discuss the transitions from dictatorship to democracy when the income inequality of societies becomes high. Acemoglu and Robinson (2006) present the first systematic formal analysis framework of redistributive conflict, in which the poor can pose a revolutionary threat aiming for more redistribution and the rich choose between concessions and oppression. They conclude that under complete information (the types of the poor and the rich; the cost of revolution), there is an inverted U-shaped relationship between inter-group inequality and democratization. The model explored in the present paper is based on Acemoglu and Robinson (2006). However, in this paper, we assume that the types of the poor (weak and strong) and the revolution cost are private information of the poor, that is, are not observed by the rich. In this framework, the rich will make concessions (i.e., promises) to avoid a revolution initiated by the poor. However, because the rich hold political power and, therefore, have the right to determine the level of taxes and transfers in the future, the promise of concessions may not be sufficiently credible. Therefore, if the poor have great certainty to believe that the rich would keep the promises, the poor will not initiate a revolution; if the poor anticipate that the nondemocratic regime will renege on its promises, they may initiate a revolution with strong probability. In fact, we will show that with asymmetry of information, an increase in inter-group equality may cause the weak type of the poor also initiate a revolution. As a result, there will be a great possibility for the transition from non-democracy to democracy. The paper is organized as follows. In section 2, we present the fundamentals of the model; in section 3, we analyze the game of incomplete information; in section 1

4, we investigate the influence of the magnitude of inter-group income inequality on the probability of the rich creating a democracy; and section 5 concludes. 2 The Model We assume that there are two types of poor actors, W (weak) and S(strong). The distinction between the two types is that when the type of the poor is W, the revolution will fail and when the type is S, the revolution will succeed. However, this is private information of the poor and is not observed by the rich. If the poor do not initiate a revolution, the rich will perform a redistribution. And if the poor initiate a revolution, the rich make a decision between oppression (denoted O) and full democratization (denoted D). 2.1 General Setting of the Model We assume that in the population (normalized to unity) there exist two classes of individuals: the rich and the poor. A fraction 1 δ > 1/2 of the agents is poor (superscripted p), with identical income y p. The remaining fraction δ is rich (superscripted r) from an oligarchy, with identical income y r. The mean income is, ȳ = δy r + (1 δ)y p, and, y p < ȳ < y r. The type of the poor is W (weak) with probability a and S (strong) with probability 1 a. Our focus is on the distributional conflict, so here, we define income inequality, θ, as the share of total income accruing to the rich; In other words, we have: y p = (1 θ)ȳ 1 δ, yr = θȳ δ. (1) Notice that an increase in θ represents an increase in inequality and from (1), we obtain θ > δ. The timing of events is as follows: The rich perform a redistributive policy to avoid revolution. Nature chooses the type of the poor (t = W, S), but this type is not observed by the rich. 2

The poor move next and choose one of two actions: non-revolution (NR) or revolution (R). If the poor choose NR, the rich will perform the promised tax rate. If the poor choose R, then the rich decide whether to realize democratization (D) or initiate oppression (O). If the poor choose R, the rich update their beliefs about the type of the poor. We denote the posterior beliefs of the rich that the weak type of the poor is p and the strong one is 1 p, and the rich democratize with probability q and oppress with 1 q. Figure 1 (Appendix 1) presents the game tree. We consider that if the poor attempt a revolution, the payoff of the rich depends on the type of the poor. If the type of the poor is W, the revolution will fail; if the type is S, repression fails and democratization will be realized. Now we consider the situation that the rich perform a redistribution. government(the rich) has a balanced budget that levies a proportional tax on income and performs a lump-sum transfer to all individuals equally. We assume that levying a redistributive tax rate τ increases the costs of taxation C(τ) where C ( ) > 0, C ( ) > 0, C (0) = 0 and C (1) = 1. Therefore, the payoffs of the poor and the rich are as follows: 1 where i = {p, r}. 2 (1 τ)y i + (τ C(τ)) ȳ if k = NR, y i (k) = (1 τ p )y i + (τ p C(τ p )) ȳ if k = D. The We know that under non-democracy, the tax rate, τ, is performed by the rich which is smaller than the equilibrium tax rate under democracy, i.e., most preferred by the poor, τ p, (by Median Voter Theorem). Actually, by the F.O.C, we (2) 1 See Persson and Tabellini 2000, pp. 19-21. 2 We can find equilibrium tax rate, τ p, by maximizing the post-tax income of a poor agent. The F.O.C gives y p + (1 C (τ p ))ȳ = 0. By (1), we can obtain (θ δ)/(1 δ) = C (τ p ). 3

know that τ p is a function of (θ, δ). Next, we define the payoffs of the rich and the poor when the rich choose oppression depending on the type of the poor: Definition 1. y r φµȳ if j = W, y r (O j) = 0 if j = S, (3) where µ is the destroyed fraction of the mean income of post-revolution, i.e. the revolution cost (0 < µ < 1), and φ is a parameter in (0, 1). 3 This means that if the rich choose oppression, their payoffs depend on the type of the poor. If the type of the poor is W, the oppression will succeed with a small loss of income; and if their type is S, the oppression will fail and the payoff of the rich is 0. Definition 2. y p (O j) = y p µȳ if j = W, 1 µ 1 δ ȳ if j = S. (4) This definition means that if revolution falls, it will cost the poor µȳ and if revolution succeeds, they get a payoff of 1 µ ȳ. (we assume µ > δ). 1 δ Next, we define the condition for the strong type of the poor to attempt a revolution since the revolution will surely succeed. Definition 3. We define a revolution constraint : if y p (O S) > y p, the poor may attempt a revolution, i.e., θ > µ. (5) Therefore a greater inequality (i.e., higher θ) makes the revolution constraint more likely to bind. Since non-revolution and non-democratization are the best outcomes for the rich, therefore they will try to prevent a revolution by a redistributive policy if at all possible. Whether they can do this depends on the value 3 In practice, any value, which is smaller than y r (D), will be reasonable. For simplicity, we assume that y r (O S) = 0. 4

they can promise to the citizens. Clearly, the most favorable tax rate they can offer to the poor is τ p. However, this is not as good as offering τ p for certain. That is to say, if the redistributive tax rate satifies y p (NR) y p (O S), then such a concession would prevent a revolution attempt. 4 By (1), (2) and (4), we get µ θ [τ p (θ δ) (1 δ)c(τ p )]. (6) If inequality is limited (i.e., θ is relatively low) or there is a high probability that the promise made by the rich will be upheld, then living under nondemocracy is not too bad for the poor, (6) will hold and even the strong type of poor will not revolt too. To analyze the model, we determine a critical value of the revolution cost µ such that (6) holds as an equality: µ = θ [τ p (θ δ) (1 δ)c(τ p )]. Then, when µ > µ, (6) will hold. We can then know that if the rich perform a tax rate τ τ p (i.e., by promising) such that y p (NR) = y p (O S), they can prevent a revolution attempt successfully. Therefore, τ satisfies µ = θ [τ(θ δ) (1 δ)c(τ)]. (7) However, because the cost of revolution is not observed by the rich, the redistributive tax τ can not always prevent a revolution attempt. And with the asymmetry of information, the poor of weak type may also attempt a revolution. Therefore if a revolution arises, what will the rich choose democratization or oppression? We will present a solution to this question in the following analysis of the game. 3 Analysis of the Game Since the type of the poor and the revolution cost are not observed by the rich, the poor of weak type may take advantage of the asymmetry of information to attempt a revolution. There exists the following perfect Bayesian equilibria: 4 In this framework, we assume that the purpose of the poor is only to aim for more redistribution and they have no ideological preferences over regimes. 5

Proposition 1. If (5) does not bind, both types of the poor choose NR and the rich choose O, with beliefs p [ p, 1]; the rich redistribute with τ = 0. And even if the rich redistribute with any τ (0, τ p ), the equilibrium does not change. If (5) binds but µ µ, the rich redistribute with τ which satisfies (7); both types of the poor choose NR and the rich choose O, with beliefs p [ p, 1]. And if τ does not satisfy (7), the strong type of the poor choose R, the weak type of the poor choose NR and the rich choose O, with beliefs p [ p, 1] off the equilibrium path. This proposition means that if the revolution constraint does not bind, a revolution would not be attempted by any type of the poor, so the rich do not perform any redistribution; and even if the revolution constraint binds, the rich can also prevent the revolution by redistribution. However, when the revolution constraint binds and the cost of revolution is small, there will be the following two equilibria: Proposition 2. When (5) binds and µ < µ, A semi-pooling equilibrium: the strong type of the poor always choose R and the weak type of the poor choose R with probability r and NR with probability 1 r, where r = p(1 a) ; the rich democratize a(1 p) with probability q and oppress with probability 1 q with beliefs p. If the rich choose D, then both types of the poor choose R and the equilibrium redistributive tax rate (ERTR) is τ p ; and if the rith choose O, then the weak type of the poor choose NR. A pooling equilibrium: both types of the poor will initiate R and the rich will choose D, with beliefs p = a [0, p]; the ERTR is τ p. And if τ < τ p, the strong type of the poor choose R, the weak type of the poor choose NR, the rich choose O, with beliefs p = a [0, p] off the equilibrium path. 6

(See Appendix 2). First note that revolution is a dominant strategy for the strong type of the poor. Then the nature of equilibrium hinges on whether the weak type of the poor chooses revolution or not. There is always a semi-pooling equilibrium in which the weak type of the poor is indifferent between choosing revolution and nonrevolution and the rich are indifferent between democratization and oppression. However, in the semi-pooling equilibrium, the weak type of the poor attempt a revolution with probability r and hence this behavior would raise the probability of democratization. More important for this paper is the pooling equilibrium. With asymmetric information, when the poor stage a revolution the rich have to democratize. The reason is that if the type of the poor is strong, the oppression fails and the payoff of the rich would be 0. This is the worst outcome for the rich, in consequence democratization would be realized with a greater possibility. 4 Concluding Remarks and Futher Research We have provided a framework in which an income inequality increase gives the opportunity to the poor, due to asymmetric information, of initiating a revolution and particularly, if the cost of oppression becomes higher (i.e., criticism from the international society), there would be a greater possibility for the rich to democratize. And another important point is that once democracy is created, the problem of how to consolidate it is left. In particular, the threaten from a coup undertaken by the rich. We will investigate this in a future work. 7

Appendix 1 Poor NR 1 r Rich set tax rate (y p (NR), y r (NR)) W a R r Rich p D q 1 q (y p (D), y r (D)) τ O (y p (O W ), y r (O W )) Rich N D q (y p (D), y r (D)) S 1 a R 1 p Rich O 1 q (y p (O S), y r (O S)) Poor NR Rich set tax rate (y p (NR), y r (NR)) Figure 1: The Game Tree 8

Appendix 2 We define the posterior beliefs of the rich, p, that if p = p, then the rich would be indifferent between D and O. Since their expected payoff from D is py r (D) + (1 p)y r (D), and their expected payoff from O is py r (O W ) + (1 p)y r (O S), the critical level of their posterior is defined as p = yr (D) y r (O W ) (0, 1). (8) If p < p, the rich will democratize. In contrast, if p > p, the rich will initiate oppression. We also define q as the probability of democratization by the rich following a revolution that will make the weak type of the poor indifferent between choosing R and NR. This is given by qy p (D) + (1 q)y p (O W ) = y p (NR), where the left side is the payoff from revolution and the right side is the payoff from NR. It is defined by q = yp (NR) y p (O W ) y p (D) y p (O W ) (0, 1). (9) When the rich choose D with probability q > q, the weak type would initiate a revolution with probability 1. In contrast, if q < q, R would not arise. If the type of the poor is S, the poor will always choose a revolution. In a word, when q > q, any type of the poor will initiate a revolution and the probability of the poor s type being W is given by p equals to a by Bayes rule. In contrast, if q < q, the weak type chooses NR and the strong one initiates a revolution. It means p = 0 but it is contradictory to p = p. When q = q, the strong type initiates a revolution and the weak one plays a local strategy. Here, we define the probability that the weak type initiates a revolution as r. From Bayes s rule, r = p(1 a) a(1 p). (10) 9

References 1. Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James A. (2000) Repression or Democratization? European Economic Review 44, 683-693. 2. Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James A. (2001) A Theory of Political Transitions American Economic Review 91, 938-63. 3. Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James A. (2006) Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy, New York: Cambridge University Press. 4. Diamond, Larry J. (1999) Developing Democracy: Towards Consolidation, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. 5. Francois, Bourguignon and Thierry, Verdier (2000) Oligarchy, democracy, inequality and growth Journal of Development Economics 62, 285-313. 6. Haggard, Stephan, and Robert R. Kaufman (1995) The Political Economy of Democratic Transitions, Princeton: Princeton University Press. 7. Josef Falkinger (1999) Social instability and redistribution of income European Journal of Political Economy 15, 35-51. 8. Przeworski, Adam (2005) Democracy as an equilibrium Public Choice 123: 253-273. 10