Comment: untoward neutral principles: market failure, implicit contract, and economic adjustment injuries

Similar documents
Management prerogatives, plant closings, and the NLRA: A response

Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation

Federal Labor Laws. Paul K. Rainsberger, Director University of Missouri Labor Education Program Revised, April 2004

PROBLEMS OF CREDIBLE STRATEGIC CONDITIONALITY IN DETERRENCE by Roger B. Myerson July 26, 2018

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

Robust Political Economy. Classical Liberalism and the Future of Public Policy

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

CRITIQUE OF CAPLAN S THE MYTH OF THE RATIONAL VOTER

Occasional Paper No 34 - August 1998

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

Letting Go of The Normal in Pursuit of an Ever- Elusive Real: A Proposal for Innovation in International Law and Economics Theory and Scholarship

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

EXAMINATION OF GOVERNANCE FOR COLLECTIVE INVESTMENT SCHEMES

THE FEDERAL RULES AND THE QUALITY OF SETTLEMENTS: A COMMENT ON ROSENBERG'S, THE FEDERAL RULES OF CIVIL PROCEDURE IN ACTION

INTRODUCTION EB434 ENTERPRISE + GOVERNANCE

Two Faces of Liberalism

Democracy As Equality

Some Current Controversies in Critical Legal Studies

Comments: Individual Versus Collective Responsibility

Limits on Scientific Expression and the Scope of First Amendment Analysis

THE FOLLOWING PUBLICATION DOES NOT IDENTIFY THE REQUESTER OF THE ADVISORY OPINION, WHICH IS NON PUBLIC DATA under Minn. Stat. 10A.02, subd.

Party Autonomy A New Paradigm without a Foundation? Ralf Michaels, Duke University School of Law

Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance by Douglass C. North Cambridge University Press, 1990

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

Market, State, and Community

FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell. Thesis: Policy Analysis Should Be Based Exclusively on Welfare Economics

ITUC OBSERVATIONS TO THE ILO COMMITTEE OF EXPERTS ON CONVENTION 87 AND THE RIGHT TO STRIKE

Advancing the Disarmament Debate: Common Ground and Open Questions

The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Time. By Karl Polayni. Boston: Beacon Press, 2001 [1944], 317 pp. $24.00.

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Corporate Governance Guidelines Altria Group, Inc. as of October 25, 2017

INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC LAW: THE POLITICAL THEATRE DIMENSION

Journals in the Discipline: A Report on a New Survey of American Political Scientists

COMMENT TO THE RULE 23 SUBCOMMITTEE OF THE CIVIL RULES ADVISORY COMMITTEE ON BEHALF OF PUBLIC CITIZEN LITIGATION GROUP.

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

The Culture of Modern Tort Law

TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER

Revising NATO s nuclear deterrence posture: prospects for change

The State, the Market, And Development. Joseph E. Stiglitz World Institute for Development Economics Research September 2015

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Ducking Dred Scott: A Response to Alexander and Schauer.

SOME PROBLEMS IN THE USE OF LANGUAGE IN ECONOMICS Warren J. Samuels

Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules

UNDERSTANDING AND WORKING WITH POWER. Effective Advising in Statebuilding and Peacebuilding Contexts How 2015, Geneva- Interpeace

Corporate Ethics and Governance in the Health Care Marketplace: An Introduction. Annette E. Clark 1

POSTGRADUTAE PROGRAM: BUSINESS ETHICS AND SOCIAL ACCOUNTING, SOME GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS TO INTEGRATE THE PAPERS AND THE SLIDES OF THE COURSE

Property Law in the West

Book Review by Marcelo Vieta

Summary. The Politics of Innovation in Public Transport Issues, Settings and Displacements

Preserving the Integrity of Police. Officers Notes

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison

Loretta J. Capeheart Northeastern Illinois University

Independent review of the Financial Reporting Council s enforcement procedures sanctions

Arbitration of Distribution and Franchise Disputes

The Way Forward: Pathways toward Transformative Change

Problems with Group Decision Making

THE PROPOSED NEW BRUNSWICK JUDGMENT ENFORCEMENT ACT QUESTIONS AND COMMENTS

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

This book has a simple and straightforward message. The

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

The Inter-Subjectivity of Objective Justice: A Theory and Praxis for Constructing LatCrit Coalitions

Damages Actions for Breach of the EC Antitrust Rules

preserving individual freedom is government s primary responsibility, even if it prevents government from achieving some other noble goal?

Authority versus Persuasion

Chapter 8: Power in Global Politics and the Causes of War

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. Issued by the Center for Civil Society and Democracy, 2018 Website:

Rawls and Feminism. Hannah Hanshaw. Philosophy. Faculty Advisor: Dr. Jacob Held

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017)

POLICY SEA: CONCEPTUAL MODEL AND OPERATIONAL GUIDANCE FOR APPLYING STRATEGIC ENVIRONMENTAL ASSESSMENT IN SECTOR REFORM EXECUTIVE SUMMARY

Comments on Burawoy on Public Sociology

George Mason University School of Recreation, Health & Tourism Court Reports SLOWE v. PIKE CREEK COURT CLUB, INC. (Del. Sup. Ct.

FLORIDA BAR ETHICS OPINION OPINION 02-4 April 2, Advisory ethics opinions are not binding.

Foundations of the Economic Approach to Law. Edited by AVERY WIENER KATZ

Community and consent: Issues from and for deliberative democratic theory

David R. Johnson and David G. Post, Law and Borders The Rise of Law in Cyberspace 45 Stan. L. Rev (1996)

Dr. John J. Hamre President and CEO Center for Strategic and International Studies Washington, D. C.

An Essay in Bobology 1. W.MAX CORDEN University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia

The deeper struggle over country ownership. Thomas Carothers

Qualities of Effective Leadership and Its impact on Good Governance

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

BOOK REVIEW: WHY LA W MA TTERS BY ALON HAREL

Mark Scheme (Results) Summer Pearson Edexcel GCE in Government & Politics (6GP03) Paper 3B: UK Political Ideologies

Running Head: POLICY MAKING PROCESS. The Policy Making Process: A Critical Review Mary B. Pennock PAPA 6214 Final Paper

Ask an Expert: Dr. Jim Walsh on the North Korean Nuclear Threat

Book Review James Q. Whitman, Harsh Justice: Criminal Punishment and the Widening Divide between America and Europe (2005)

Grassroots Policy Project

General Rulebook (GEN)

A Tribute to Ron Delisle

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION (PUAD)

PRIVATIZATION AND INSTITUTIONAL CHOICE

<91- J,-/--, CLAUSEWITZ,,NUCLEAR WAR AND DETERRENCE. Alan W. Barr. Military Thought and National Security Strategy. National War College 1991

EXECUTIVE SUMMARY 1. Ireland s Five-Part Crisis, Five Years On: Deepening Reform and Institutional Innovation. Executive Summary

Strengthening the Foundation for World Peace - A Case for Democratizing the United Nations

Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal

Compassion and Compulsion

Pearson Edexcel GCE in Government & Politics (6GP03/3B)

Transcription:

NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository School of Law Faculty Publications Northeastern University School of Law 1-1-1993 Comment: untoward neutral principles: market failure, implicit contract, and economic adjustment injuries Karl E. Klare Follow this and additional works at: http://lsr.nellco.org/nusl_faculty Recommended Citation Klare, Karl E., "Comment: untoward neutral principles: market failure, implicit contract, and economic adjustment injuries" (1993). School of Law Faculty Publications. 182. http://lsr.nellco.org/nusl_faculty/182 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Northeastern University School of Law at NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in School of Law Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact tracy.thompson@nellco.org.

Karl E. Klare* COMMENT: UNTOWARD NEUTRAL PRINCIPLES - MARKET FAILURE, IMPLICIT CONTRACT, AND ECONOMIC ADJUSTMENT INJURIES I Introduction Superb papers by Ronald Daniels' and Katherine Stone' discuss the appropriate social and legal response to generic problems of injury to non-shareholder constituencies, particularly workers, occasioned by adjustments in corporate structure or strategy. Both authors insist that significant adjustment injuries such as employee displacement can be triggered by a wide range of changes in firms' competitive strategies and investment decisions, not just takeovers and other change-of-control events on which the literature has focused. The authors suggest an array of well-conceived proposals for law reform, with which I largely agree. This brief note probes the authors' conceptual framework rather than their specific conclusions and policy prescriptions. Several difficulties limit the scope and effectiveness of their approaches. The authors adopt the model that conceives the firm as a nexus of contractual relations between its various constituencies (the NCR model). In Stone's analysis, management induces employees to make a long-term investment of human capital in the firm by internal promotion schemes and implicit promises of deferred compensation and job security. The problem she discloses is that management often has strong incentives to renege, and the law affords employees entirely inadequate instruments with which to enforce the implicit contract and prevent end-game betrayal. For Stone, the adjustment injuries problem is primarily a question of expropriation, and her solution is to enable employees to make and enforce more effective contractual guarantees against such misbehaviour. Stone accepts the contracting model of the firm only provisionally, treating it as a medium in which to advance her democratic and egalitarian commitments. She advances other approaches to law reform, including the idea of revising the background legal rules of the economic game so as to redistribute power from employers to workers. * Northeastern University School of Law I Ronald Daniels 'Stakeholders and Takeovers: Can Contractarianism Be Compassionate?' this issue 2 Katherine Van Wezel Stone 'Policing Employment Contracts Within the Nexus-of- Contracts Firm' this issue (1993), 43 UNIVERsrrY OF TORONTO LAW JOuI'AL 393

394 UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LAW JOURNAL Daniels is much more committed to the NCR model. But where Stone sees opportunistic wealth diversion in violation of implicit contract, Daniels emphasizes the absence of contractual protections. Employees and some other stakeholders systematically underprotect themselves from adjustment harms due to a pervasive problem of market failure. Employees possess imperfect information about the likelihood and risks that unpredictable market forces (notably the globalization of competition) will devalue stakeholders' firm-specific capital. His solution is to correct for contracting failure by positing and enacting the outcome that would have been bargained for in the presence of perfect information. Because the problem stems from mistake rather than misconduct, arguably society should shoulder some of the assistance burden. II Preliminary points 1. EXTERNALITIES In practice, NCR discussions of adjustment injuries pay insufficient attention to significant externalities and third-party effects emanating from the corporate contractual nexus. Capital mobility can generate severe third-party dislocation costs for which firms bear no liability (increases in domestic violence, alcohol abuse, and suicide; community decline; and loss of the social and political contributions of labour unions). Because they externalize these costs onto the community, firms are likely to overvalue alternative uses of capital and therefore to overproduce disinvestment. This supplies an additional argument for legal reform and specifically for firm liability for adjustment injuries.' 2. INDUSTRIAL RELATIONS The NCR model is sociologically unsophisticated; it has no organizational theory. Specifically, NCR discussions of economic adjustment often ignore the findings of industrial relations theory. The tendency is to regard noncontractual stakeholder protections as an inhibiting tax on wealth generation, but this view disregards considerable evidence that job security protections can enhance productivity (by creating an industrial relations climate more conducive to technological innovation), and that junking our senior, experienced workforce robs the economy of productive capability. In this respect, the implicit contract model is superior to the market failure analysis because it offers a theory of why heightened protections can lead to joint gains. In general, we should complement the 3 See generally Joseph Singer 'The Reliance Interest in Property' (1987) 49 Stan. LR 611.

THE ADEQUACY OF STAKEHOLDER CONTRACTUAL PROTECTION 395 NCR approach with a theory of the firm as a bureaucratic institution in need of democratization. 3. REPUTATIONAL LOSS Some NCR theorists argue that the risk of reputational loss deters opportunistic breach of contracts with non-shareholder constituencies, obviating the need for heightened legal protections. Stone questions, but Daniels sees merit in this view, with qualifications. The reputational loss argument for legal abstention is incoherent. Harm to a firm's reputation (and deterrent impact on others) arises only in the case of conduct widely judged to be inappropriate and therefore worthy of censure. If, in the prevailing view, an uncompensated mass layoff is not understood to be a wrong but 'a curse of fate' or 'just bad luck,' then downsizing firms risk no injury to reputation. Legal values and practices significantly affect the prevailing cultural messages. When the law and the culture are fatalistic about worker dislocation, employees adapt to preferences that undervalue job security because they internalize the view that they cannot realistically expect to have it. Conversely, there is a greater risk of reputational damage when the law teaches that junking employees is wrong. Thus, the risk of reputational loss can only function as a deterrent when the background legal rules and the dominant cultural understandings stigmatize unilateral action causing adjustment injuries. 4. ATYPICAL WORKERS The implicit contract theory is undermined by the problem of labour market segmentation. The theory is most persuasive regarding the primary labour market, where long-term employment is the norm. But a crucial development of recent years has been the dramatic expansion of secondary or contingent labour markets, in which employers negate expectations of continuity, job security, and deferred compensation. Many employers see maintenance of low-commitment (and frequently low-wage) relationships as a viable profit-seeking strategy. Sometimes employees will prefer low-commitment or part-time work, but often lowcommitment employment is accepted reluctantly and only because the job-seeker lacks the bargaining power to do better. The destructive consequence for the economy as a whole of the proliferation of contingent employment is the long-run degradation of human capital. Often the case is exactly as Stone describes. An employer has implicitly (or even expressly) promised job security and deferred compensation, 4 See generally Hugh Collins 'Market Power, Bureaucratic Power, and the Contract of Employment' (1986) 15 Industrial LJ 1.

396 UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LAW JOURNAL and the feeling of betrayal among dismissed workers is authentic and appropriate. But it must be acknowledged that this is not always so. Particularly (though not exclusively) in the secondary labour market, there may be no promise of job security. Employees, even unionized employees, often fail to bargain for job security and adjustment protections, not because they do not value these things or because they lack pertinent information, but because they simply do not have enough market strength to achieve protections. As to such employees, the case for enhanced protections cannot be made solely in contractual reliance terms. An efficiency case can be made for adjustment protections (discouraging involuntary low-wage/low-commitment employment upgrades societal productivity), but in the end, an argument from the standpoint of distributive equity is required. iii Critique: Neutral principles? The NCR model does not and cannot fulfil the hope of some proponents, notably Daniels, to avoid controversial normativejudgments. Accordingly, discussion of adjustment harms should openly debate questions of distributional equity towards affected constituencies and the question of democratization of the firm regarded as a political institution. Professor Daniels is admirably candid about his agenda to get beyond the 'highly contestable normative and empirical claims'" characteristic of the 'paralysing- terms" of political debate between individualists and communitarians. He seeks a way to keep law and politics separate, while justifying 'humane and compassionate assistance to deserving victims of economic transitions, without forgoing the wealth-creating benefits that these transitions confer on society at large.' 7 He hopes that a sophisticated efficiency analysis of the contractual ties binding various social constituencies will provide a neutral, apolitical rhetoric in which to justify a dynamic but socially softened capitalism. The normative glue of the theory is supplied by 'capacious, fair-minded interpretations of widely shared contractarian values.' 8 Stone shares none of Daniels's beyondideology agenda. Indeed, her goal is 'to contest the normative message contained in the contractual theory of the firm.' 9 But Daniels perceptively notes that a great appeal of implicit contract theory for progressives is 5 Supra note 1, text following note 26 6 Ibid., text following note 93 7 Ibid. 8 Ibid. 9 Supra note 2, text following note 11

THE ADEQUACY OF STAKEHOLDER CONTRACTUAL PROTECTION 397 that it accomplishes the feat of justifying communitarian policies by reference to autonomy-based contractarian premises.' 0 Expanding the point, NCR theory apparently enables progressives to use efficiency talk or, as in Stone's case, contractual reliance arguments, to advance an egalitarian and empowerment program. In pursuit of his objectives, Daniels skilfully deploys a theoretical manoeuvre launched by Guido Calabresi years ago in his work on accident law. Calabresi, too, sought a neutral rhetoric that would consistently generate pro-compensation tort results. He achieved this by linking the prestige of neoclassical welfare economics to the old enterprise liability tradition. The latter had advanced the frankly redistributive and therefore always politically suspect principle of using the price system to 'socialize' accident costs. To this contestable normative premise Calabresi added an efficiency argument. Unless enterprises are liable for accident costs they generate, externalities will distort proper market functioning and unsafety will be overproduced. Ronald Coase advised us that free bargaining automatically eliminates the allocation problem, but Calabresi quickly responded that this is true only in the absence of significant transaction and information costs and other forms of market failure. These debates produced a generation of legal scholars who have treated 'tort law as a high transaction cost exception to a contract paradigm.. But even within its own terms the market failure approach to liability rules has not succeeded in banishing controversial judgments implicating political controversy. All the key working concepts - 'enterprise,' 'transaction cost,' 'externality,' and so on - have been shown to be too indeterminate to permit value-neutral elaboration of the theory. That is true here as well. Daniels perceptively surfaces a key ambiguity in the implicit contract theory. Even in the primary sector where employees often justifiably rely on implicit promises of job security and deferred compensation, the implicit contract does not always and obviously include a continuity guarantee even when intervening events have rendered continuance of the relationship economically irrational. And in many, particularly secondary-sector, settings, it is not always clear whether there was an assurance of continuity at all. Inevitably, value judgments and moral sensibilities will ground interpretations regarding the existence and content of implicit promises of job security. But this same observation 10 Supra note 1, text following note 8 11 Morton Horwitz 'Law and Economics: Science or Politics?' (1980) 8 Hofstra LR 905, 908. This paragraph is drawn from the Horwitz article and Duncan Kennedy 'Cost- Benefit Analysis of Entitlement Problems: A Critique' (1981) 33 Stan. LR 387.

398 UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LAW JOURNAL applies to Daniels's own hypothetical contract approach. Without reference to controversial background normative assumptions and intuitions, one cannot determine what protections would have been negotiated by employees in the presence of perfect information (and 'equal bargaining power,' he throws in intriguingly at one point)." Although Daniels attempts to 'discipline' the inquiry, he virtually concedes the indeterminate and ultimately value-laden character of the hypothetical contract exercise. Daniels's hypothetical contract, like Stone's implicit contract, combines a recognition of authentic needs and expectations of the parties, a fundamental sense of fairness and justice, and a certain amount of wishful thinking. In the end, he invokes the classic fall-back rubric of legal argument, 'widely shared values,' to sustain the neutrality of the enterprise. In reference to a question as politically charged as adjustment entitlements, this is unconvincing. I emphasize again that I share many of Daniels's moral intuitions and policy goals. My hesitation is about whether we can justify humane and compassionate assistance to victims of economic dislocation without getting into matters of normative and political controversy. I strongly believe that adjustment assistance is conducive to societal well-being and specifically to long-run economic productivity because it protects and enhances human capital. But at the end of the day, the most compelling argument for adjustment assistance is not that it is efficient or that it has been or hypothetically would be bargained for or relied upon. The strongest argument invokes claims of equity, namely that it isjust that we all share in the misfortunes occasioned to innocent victims by economic growth policies from which we all benefit, and that a particular burden to assist rightfully falls upon those who profit directly from social policies that enhance capital mobility. IV Conclusion: Equity and empowerment The Daniels and Stone papers demonstrate that the NCR model is not riveted to a particular social or political outlook, and that its frame of reference can be invoked to ground a progressive social curbing of capitalism. This is a considerable achievement. Contrary to many liberal and leftist sceptics, I share the Daniels/Stone view that rational-choice theory and transaction-cost economics are politically open-ended, not intrinsically apologetic or legitimationist discourses. Socially concerned scholars should draw upon the insights of and pursue projects within the medium of these theories. I attempt to do so in my own work. 12 Supra note 1, text following note 86

THE ADEQUACY OF STAKEHOLDER CONTRACTUAL PROTECTION 399 But the endeavour is not without risks. To provide insight regarding and support for humane reform, the gaps and silences in the NCR model must be corrected. Like all bargaining-focused approaches to social choice, the NCR model is limited by a tendency to privilege the existing distribution of wealth, income, and power, that is, the existing social subordination of working people. The NCR model is a classic instance of a theory designed to represent socially constructed power relationships as the product of 'consent,' with a consequent tendency (a mission for some theorists, though not these authors) to efface power from the analysis.' One way the NCR model in practice suppresses questions of equity and power is to obscure and deflect attention from the role of law in setting the background rules of the game of economic conflict.' Because law has this role, it is partially responsible for determining the relative bargaining power of economic actors and therefore the sorts of contracts they are likely to conclude about things like adjustment injuries. That is, the law is implicated in and at least partially responsible for determining the substantive content of the contracts that make up the firm as nexus. The NCR discourse takes for granted the existence and justice of many background rules that enhance the power of capital vis-a-vis that of other constituencies. For example, NCR discourse is complacent about the legal assumptions that the employer may discharge at will (absent contrary contractual protections), and that capital disinvestment that destroys communities is not a compensable tort. That is, NCR discourse assumes as a starting point of legal analysis that the owners of capital may externalize the costs of adjustment injuries onto affected constituencies. Nothing in the nature of things requires a society to operate on these assumptions. These rules of law represent politically chosen and mandated subsidies to capital formation. Perhaps these subsidies are wise, but that case needs to be made. By hypothesis, it cannot be made solely in efficiency terms. Thus, ultimately the adjustment injury inquiry must come back to and candidly address questions of distributional equity and 13 Alan Hyde argues that a central motivation for some NCR theorists was to eliminate the question of power from the analysis of the corporation, specifically any power of the firm over others. See Alan Hyde 'In Defense of Employee Ownership' (1991) 67 Chi.-Kent LR 159, 180 n66. If the corporation is a bundle of freely chosen contracts, 'it' cannot have power over anyone. This pre-empts the argument that corporations are quasi-governmental entities suitable for statutory or constitutional regulation. Hyde insists, however, that although some influential NCR theorists may have had apologetic ambitions, this is not an intrinsic feature of the theory. He urges that socially concerned scholars remain open to dialogue with the school. Ibid. 14 See generally Duncan Kennedy 'The Stakes of Law, or Hale and Foucaultl' (1991) 15 Legal Studies Forum 327.

400 UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LAW JOURNAL power, and this in turn requires us to examine the fairness of the background legal rules that set the terms of conflict and negotiation between the various constituents of the firm. The clear superiority of Stone's approach is that she constantly reminds us of this point. Have we achieved a just, socially defensible allocation of the costs and benefits of economic flexibility and capital mobility? Are the substantial subsidies to capital formation that are such a prominent feature of Canadian and us law really justified by their contribution to economic development, seen in the light of the often tragic human and social consequences of uncompensated and unassisted dislocation? Theoretical economics cannot provide answers to these questions. The answers depend on highly contextualized, empirical inquiries and at least partly on controversial normative judgments. The view of the firm as constituted by inter-constituency bargaining can yield insights, so long as we are careful to appreciate that the bargaining takes place on a field of legally set background rules that affect the parties' relative power. But we should also enlarge our vision of the firm to see it as a political and social institution with its own organizational and industrial relations dynamics. This enlarged conception of the firm appropriately opens the door to debate about questions of equity and democratic empowerment.