Intro Prefs & Voting Electoral comp. Voter Turnout Agency GIP SIP Rent seeking Partisans. 4. Voter Turnout

Similar documents
Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting Mechanisms: An Experimental Study

Extended Abstract: The Swing Voter s Curse in Social Networks

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

External Validation of Voter Turnout Models by Concealed Parameter Recovery 1

Voter Participation with Collusive Parties. David K. Levine and Andrea Mattozzi

Third Party Voting: Vote One s Heart or One s Mind?

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Economic potentials of the refugee immigration in the long run

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE PERFORMANCE OF THE PIVOTAL-VOTER MODEL IN SMALL-SCALE ELECTIONS: EVIDENCE FROM TEXAS LIQUOR REFERENDA

ON IGNORANT VOTERS AND BUSY POLITICIANS

Candidate Citizen Models

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting An Experimental Study

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits

At least since Downs s (1957) seminal work An Economic Theory of Democracy,

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

The Swing Voter's Curse *

Compulsory versus Voluntary Voting An Experimental Study

Voting and Electoral Competition

Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute for Economic Research

The Performance of Pivotal-Voter Models in Small-Scale Elections: Evidence from Texas Liquor Referenda

Travel destination Iceland Denmark, United Kingdom, Germany and France

Information Acquisition and Voting Mechanisms: Theory and Evidence

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing

CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997)

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

Obtaining evidence from Germany for use in a US civil or commercial trial

Collective Decision with Costly Information: Theory and Experiments

The welfare effects of public opinion polls

Experimental Evidence on Voting Rationality and Decision Framing

Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership

University of Toronto Department of Economics. Influential Opinion Leaders

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks

Wisdom of the Crowd? Information Aggregation and Electoral Incentives

Introduction to Political Economy Problem Set 3

Jury Voting without Objective Probability

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation

Local security in Germany

Corruption in Committees: An Experimental Study of Information Aggregation through Voting 1

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 11 and 12. Information, Beliefs and Politics

Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention

The Citizen Candidate Model: An Experimental Analysis

Coalition Governments and Political Rents

The Provision of Public Goods Under Alternative. Electoral Incentives

University of Toronto Department of Economics. Party formation in single-issue politics [revised]

The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting 1

Electoral Engineering: One Man, One Vote Bid

A Dead Heat and the Electoral College

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

Corruption and Political Competition

14.11: Experiments in Political Science

A positive correlation between turnout and plurality does not refute the rational voter model

Get Out the (Costly) Vote: Institutional Design for Greater Participation. Current Version: May 10, 2015

Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1

Electoral Engineering: One Man, One Vote Bid

Immigration and Conflict in Democracies

Testing Political Economy Models of Reform in the Laboratory

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout

A MODEL OF POLITICAL COMPETITION WITH CITIZEN-CANDIDATES. Martin J. Osborne and Al Slivinski. Abstract

Get Out the (Costly) Vote: Institutional Design for Greater Participation. Current Version: November 26, 2008

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

Illegal Migration and Policy Enforcement

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas?

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association

The Dark Side of the Vote: Biased Voters, Social Information, and Information Aggregation Through Majority Voting

Union Organizing Decisions in a Deteriorating Environment: The Composition of Representation Elections and the Decline in Turnout

Should Straw Polls be Banned?

Strategic Sequential Voting

Median voter theorem - continuous choice

POLITICAL EQUILIBRIUM SOCIAL SECURITY WITH MIGRATION

political budget cycles

Capture and Governance at Local and National Levels

4.1 Efficient Electoral Competition

Electing the President. Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling

The Swing Voter s Curse in Social Networks

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout

MIDTERM EXAM 1: Political Economy Winter 2017

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF ALTERNATIVE CAMPAIGN FINANCE SYSTEMS: DONATIONS, ELECTIONS AND POLICY CHOICES

Get Out the (Costly) Vote: Institutional Design for Greater Participation

Identity and Diversity: Unity in diversity as an European vision

The Political Economy of Trade Policy

3 Electoral Competition

THE EFFECT OF OFFER-OF-SETTLEMENT RULES ON THE TERMS OF SETTLEMENT

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 8 and 9: Political Agency

"Efficient and Durable Decision Rules with Incomplete Information", by Bengt Holmström and Roger B. Myerson

External Validation of Voter Turnout Models by Concealed Parameter Recovery 1

A psychologically-based model of voter turnout

Ming Li Concordia University Dipjyoti Majumdar Concordia University

Congressional Gridlock: The Effects of the Master Lever

Should We Tax or Cap Political Contributions? A Lobbying Model With Policy Favors and Access

Supplementary Materials for Strategic Abstention in Proportional Representation Systems (Evidence from Multiple Countries)

On Optimal Voting Rules under Homogeneous Preferences

Social Polarization and Political Selection in Representative Democracies

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

Approval Voting and Scoring Rules with Common Values

Experimental Computational Philosophy: shedding new lights on (old) philosophical debates

Expert Mining and Required Disclosure: Appendices

Transcription:

4. Voter Turnout

Paradox of Voting So far we have assumed that all individuals will participate in the election and vote for their most preferred option irrespective of: the probability of being pivotal and the cost associated with voting. This appears, however, rather peculiar from a cost-benefit perspective.

Paradox of Voting Following the hypothesis of utility-maximizing individuals, a rational voter i will participate in election e if with p e i B e i > C e i (3.1) p e i : probability that voter i s vote is pivotal B e i : benefit from implementing voter i s favorite policy C e i : cost of voting If we assume that pi e is small, a rational voter will most likely abstain form voting.

Paradox of Voting Wahlbeteiligung nach Bundesländern In Prozent der Wahlberechtigten, Deutschland 86 84 82 80 78 76 Prozent Bayern Baden-Württemberg Niedersachsen Schleswig-Holstein Nordrhein-Westfalen Hessen Rheinland-Pfalz Saarland Hamburg Deutschland Gesamt Bremen Berlin 74 72 Thüringen Brandenburg Sachsen 70 68 Mecklenburg-Vorpom. Sachsen-Anhalt 0 1990 1994 1998 2002 Quelle: Bundeswahlleiter Stand: 08.2005 Jahr 2005 Bundeszentrale für politische Bildung Figure 4.1 Figure 15: Voter turnout in Germany by state

Paradox of Voting Wahlbeteiligung nach Altersgruppen 1953 2002 In Prozent der Wahlberechtigten bei Bundestagswahlen, Deutschland Prozent 95 92 89 86 83 80 77 74 71 68 65 Gesamt 60 70 50 60 45 50 40 45 35 40 70 und älter 30 35 25 30 unter 21 21 25 62 0 1953* 1957* 1961 1965 1969 1972 1976 1980 1983 1987 1990 2002 Jahr** Quelle: Bundeswahlleiter * 1957: ohne Saarland; 1953: ohne Rheinland-Pfalz, Bayern, Saarland 2005 Bundeszentrale Stand: 08.2005 ** 1994 und 1998: keine Angaben wegen Aussetzung der Wahlstatistik für politische Bildung Figure 4.2 Figure 16: Voter turnout in Germany by age

Paradox of Voting The voter turnout in many elections is in contrast to this prediction, however, significant. Downs (1957) names this contradiction the Paradox of Voting.

Paradox of Voting Ways to solve the paradox Introduce a direct consumption benefit of voting D e i Compliance with the civic duty to vote yields direct benefit The explanatory power of the exogenously imposed benefit is, however, rather limited (no testable prediction) The puzzle why people vote remains. Remark: Expressive Voting: Voting itself yields an direct consumption benefit (D e i ). Instrumental Voting: Voting as an instrument to implement the most preferred policy.

Paradox of Voting In the sequel, we discuss three different groups of models which try to explain why people vote. 1 Pivotal Voter Models: give a micro-foundation of the probability of being pivotal. 2 Ethical Voter Models: endogenize the direct benefit component D e i. 3 Uncertain Voter Models: endogenize the cost of voting C e i.

Pivotal Voter Model Idea: Probability of being pivotal may still be significant and thus the turnout may be positive. In particular, the model predicts that turnout is higher: the smaller the electorate, and the more close the election outcome is. The subsequently presented formal reasoning is based on the review article by Merlo (2005). The complete model and derivation of the respective equations can be found in the article.

Pivotal Voter Model Assumptions and model ingredients: A1 Two policy platforms A and B which divide the electorate in two groups, favoring either A or B. A2 Each individual knows his/her most preferred option, but can only infer that any other individual will favor A over B (or vice versa) with probability 0.5. A3 The size of the electorate is N which is finite (an infinite number of voters would reduce p e i to 0). A4 The utility when the most preferred option wins is 1, while it is -1 when the other option wins. A5 The cost of voting Ci e is independently and uniformly distributed on the interval [0,1].

Pivotal Voter Model Refereing to eq. (3.1) we can define a cut-off level C. All individuals with a cost below this level will participate in the election while the remaining individuals will abstain. To characterize individual voting behavior, we proceed as follows: 1 We determine the probability that s individuals indeed find it optimal to vote. 2 Then we derive the conditional probability that i is pivotal given that s individuals vote. 3 Combining the first two items, we compute the unconditional probability that individual i will be pivotal. 4 Finally, we characterize the induced cut-off level C.

Ad 1: The probability that s individuals vote Each individual will vote, if his/her individual cost of voting are below the threshold C. So, the ex-ante probability that with which any individual votes is given by ϑ = PrC e i C (3.2) Since we assume that voting costs are independently and identically distributed according to a uniform distribution on the support [0;1], we know that ϑ = PrC e i C = C (3.2 )

Ad 1: The probability that s individuals vote Therefore, the probability that s individuals vote is given by: ( ) N 1 pi e (s) = (C ) s (1 C ) N 1 s. (3.3) s The citizen s decision to vote or not to vote follows a binomial distribution as the decision is discrete with two realizations. Moreover, the cost draws are independent and the "success" probability (that citizen vote) is constant and equal to C.

Binomial Distribution The binomial distribution is the discrete probability distribution of the number of successes in a sequence of n independent yes/no experiments, each of which yields success with probability p. Example: Assume 5% of a very large population to be green-eyed. You pick 100 people randomly. The number of green-eyed people you pick is a random variable K which follows a binomial distribution with n = 100 and p = 0.05. The probability of getting exactly K successes in n trials is: ( ) n p(k) = (p) k (1 p) n ks. k

Ad 2: The conditional probability of i being pivotal Voter i is only pivotal, if (s)he is able to alter the outcome of the election. This is the case if the preferred alternative of i is behind by one vote the pivotal voter can induce a tie both alternatives have gained the same number of votes the pivotal voter can induce his/her preferred alternative to win. In either case the citizens i s vote increases the expected utility by 1. if s 1 and s is odd, citizens i is pivotal if s 1 2 citizen vote for the preferred alternative.

So, we have: two discrete events: alternative A or B s independent draws each of which yields "success" with probability 0.5 the event that out of s voters s 1 2 will support option A follows a binomial distribution and the conditional probability that voter i is pivotal, given that s citizens vote, states: π e i (s) = ( ) s s 1 (0.5) s 1 2 (0.5) s s 1 2. (3.4) 2

Ad 3: The probability of i being pivotal If two events are independent, their joint probability is the product of the prior probabilities of each event occurring by itself: P(A B) = P(A) P(B). Thus, the unconditional probability of being pivotal is: pi e (s) = ( ) N 1 s = 0 N 1 (C ) s (1 C ) N 1 s πi e (s). (3.5) s p e i is lower the higher the cut-off level C. Intuition: A rise in C increases the probability that many voters are around; an event which is unfavorable for the prospect that voter i is pivotal.

The induced cut-off level The last issue which needs to be checked is whether there exists a C [0, 1], which induces individuals to vote if C e i < C. For an individual with cost realization C it must hold that p e i B e i C = 0 p e i C = 0 since the benefit of being pivotal is B e i = 1. As we know, that p e i = 1 if C = 0 and p e i = 0 if C = 1, we know by the intermediate value theorem that there exists a value C which is interior to [0,1].

Empirical Relevance: Pivotal Voter Model The theory can in principle explain a positive turnout (when C > 0), but the questions is whether the predicted value conforms with values observed in the data. Coate et al. (2004) take the model to a test: They use data on local referenda in the state of Texas. In doing so, they divide the data set in referenda held in large and small jurisdictions and estimate voting turnout for the sub-sample of small jurisdictions (for which the model is most suited). The result is that turnout can be quite well predicted. However, the model yields an upward bias in the predicted closeness of the election outcome.

Empirical Relevance: Pivotal Voter Model Figure 17: Average Turnout as Percentage of Eligible Voters

Empirical Relevance: Pivotal Voter Model Figure 18: Distribution over Closeness Voter Turnout in Germany by Age

Ethical Voter Model Idea: Elections typically divide the electorate in two groups (supporters and opposers) which triggers a kind of contest between the two groups. Members of both groups may thus base their voting decision on what they consider best for promoting the success of their group; i.e. they want to do their part to help their group win. They are inclined to follow a voting rule that, provided everybody adheres to it, maximizes the chance that the group wins. Group solidarity may be due to a common ethnic identity or people feel similarly strongly about the political issues involved (e.g. abortion policy).

Ethical Voter Model To formally illustrate the reasoning, we present a simple model based on Merlo (2005). The assumptions are the same as for the pivotal voter model except of: A2 The fraction of the population which supports option A is µ which is uniformly distributed on [0,1]. A3 There is a continuum of individuals. The size of the population is normalized at unity. The assumption excludes the possibility that individuals are pivotal (no instrumental voting).

Ethical Voter Model The cut-off levels for group A and B are denoted by CA and CB. They are chosen such as to maximize the overall expected utility of the group members. For a given fraction of individuals in favor of A, group A wins, if the number of supporters with a cost below CA (being equal to CA times the fraction of supporters µ) exceeds the corresponding value for the other group; µca > (1 µ)c B µ > C B /(C A + C B ). (3.6)

Ethical Voter Model The assumed cost of voting for any group A member is C A 0 CdC = 0.5(C A )2. (3.6) For a given µ, the conditional expected overall cost of voting is 0.5µ(CA )2 and the unconditional expected overall cost reads: 1 0.5µ(CA )2 dµ. (3.7) 0 In contrast, the conditional group benefit is dependent on the outcome of the election. For group A, it is µ(1) in case of victory and µ( 1) otherwise.

Ethical Voter Model Taking expectations over µ, the overall expected benefit for group A becomes: 0 C B C A +C B Thus, the overall expected payoff is: 0 C B C A +C B 1 µdµ + µdµ. (3.8) C B C A +C B 1 µdµ + µdµ C B C A +C B 1 0 0.5(C A )2 µdµ =

Empirical Relevance: Ethical Voter Model = 0 C B C A +C B 1 µ[ 1 0.5(CA )2 ]dµ + µ[1 0.5(C C B A )2 ]dµ C A +C B Differentiating the term for group A with respect to C A and solving the two FOCs for the values yields: CA = C B 0.71(Merlo, 2005). Here turnout is positive and might be significant. Note, the cost realizations are independent of the assignment to either group.

Empirical Relevance: Ethical Voter Model The theory relies on the assumption that each individual follows the voting rule which maximizes group welfare. The theory thus disregards free-riding behavior! Besides evaluating the plausibility of the model, another more important evaluation of the theory is to analyze the extent to which the theory can explain turnout observed in the data. Coate and Conlin (2004) use the same data set as for evaluating the pivotal voter model in Coate et al. (2004). As shown in figure 4.5, they find a significant share of voter turnout to be explained by the model. However, there is a tendency to over-predict turnout with low actual turnout rates and vice versa.

Empirical Relevance: Pivotal Voter Model Figure 19: Actual versus Predicted Turnout

Uncertain Voter Model Idea: The uncertain voter model assumes that the cost of voting is zero (Ci e = 0), but that individuals have different information about the nature of the optimal option. The lack of perfect information may lead them to make mistakes which are costly from each voter s perspective. It is in this way that voting becomes costly. To shed some light on the economics of voter participation, we start with a simple example.

Uncertain Voter Model Example 1: Assume there are two options, A and B, on the table and three individuals. In state A of the world all individuals prefer A to B. The state A occurs with probability µ = 0.9. In state B of the world all voters prefer B to A. The benefit is 1 when the most preferred option wins and -1 otherwise. One individual is perfectly informed about the true state of the world; A fact, which is known by the two other, uninformed individuals. In this situation the (perfect Bayesian-Nash) equilibrium involves that the informed individual will always vote, while the uninformed individuals will abstain.

Uncertain Voter Model Given that the uninformed individuals will abstain, it is optimal for informed individual to vote and to induce his/her most preferred outcome (assume that if nobody votes, either option is implemented with probability 0.5). Given that the informed individual votes, an uninformed individual cannot induce a higher utility by voting. When voting for A, (s)he wouldn t change the outcome in state A, but would induce a tie in state B and, thereby, produce the "wrong" outcome with probability 0.5. Equivalently, when voting for B, (s)he wouldn t change the outcome in state B, but would induce a tie in state A (costly!). Thus, abstention by uninformed individuals and voting by the informed individual is an equilibrium.

Uncertain Voter Model Conclusion of Example 1 The finding that all uninformed voters "delegate" the voting decision to the informed voter presupposes that the voters preferences are aligned. Delegation does not incur a cost on the uninformed voters. Voting incentives might be different if there are voters around which would vote, but not for the option the uninformed citizens prefer. To see this more clearly, we modify the example as follows.

Uncertain Voter Model Example 2: There is a fourth voter who has a partisan preference, i.e. (s)he will get a positive benefit from option A in both states of the world and no benefit from option B. In this situation it becomes optimal that one uninformed individual votes for option B, while the other abstains. Both the partisan and the informed individual will vote as well. Why? The informed individual will induce a tie in both states of the world when abstaining, while guaranteeing the "correct" outcome with probability 1 when voting. When the uninformed voter opts for B, (s)he will not change the election outcome in state B, but will induce a victory of B in state B.

Uncertain Voter Model Differently, when the uninformed non-voter opts for A, then (s)he will not change the outcome in state A, but will induce a tie relative to a victory for option B in state B (costly!!). Similarly, when opting for B, (s)he will induce a tie in state A (rather than a victory for option A) and no change in state B (also costly). The partisan individual can move the outcome in his/her most preferred direction in state A and is not influential in state B.

Uncertain Voter Model Conclusion of Example 2 The last example shows that uninformed, independent (i.e. non-partisan) individuals may vote and, if yes, they do so to neutralize the partisan bias. They may vote for option B, although it is less likely to be the "correct" voting decision (µ = 0.9). The result extends to more general models; i.e. the higher the fraction of partisan voters favoring option A, the higher the fraction of independent individuals who vote, and the more inclined are independent voters to opt for alternative B.

Uncertain Voter Model What is the prediction for voter turnout? The pivotal and ethical voter model predict a higher turnout when the race becomes more close. Such a prediction may not arise in the current model. It may be just in the situation when (independent and uninformed) voters are pivotal that they will abstain. They rationally anticipate that they may decide the election in the "wrong" direction. The phenomenon is named Swing voter s curse (in analogy to the winner s curse in auctions) - see Feddersen and Pesendorfer (2004): The latter says that if bidders get independent signals about the value of the item which is auctioned off (with the possibility that the signal is wrong as it gives a too high value), the winner may be worse off (relative to not winning).

Empirical Relevance: Uncertain Voter Model The model emphasizes the role of information for the decision to vote. This can rarely be observed in field data (unless there is a natural experiment where one group of voters is randomly chosen and gets more information about the alternatives under consideration). A different strategy is to resort to experimental analysis where the information level of voters and the number of partisan voters can be more accurately controlled.

Empirical Relevance: Uncertain Voter Model In fact, Battaglini et al. (2005) conduct a laboratory experiment. Therein, each lab session lasts 30 periods. After 10 periods the number of partisan voters, m, is changed and announced to the participants - see Figure 4.6 for a description of the different sessions, where p is the probability that state a occurs.

Empirical Relevance: Uncertain Voter Model Figure 4.7 gives a summary of how the uninformed voters respond to the adjustment in the number of partisan voters. In line with the theory, less individuals abstain and more vote for option b (not preferred by the partisan), the higher the number of partisans.

Figure 22: Experimental Outcome 2 Empirical Relevance: Uncertain Voter Model The "time-profile" of the voting decisions of uninformed individuals is depicted in figure 4.8 where the solid line gives the theoretical prediction w.r.t. the probability of voting for a and b. Following the change in m, the probability to vote for b is "correctly" adjusted, while the probability to vote for a remains at a low level.

References Battaglini, M, R. Morton, and T. Palfrey (2005), The Swing Voter s Curse in the Laboratory, CEPR Discussion Paper No. 5458. Borgers, T. (2004), Costly Voting, American Economic Review, 94, 57-66. Coate, S. and M. Conlin (2004), A Group Rule-Utilitarian Approach to Voter Turnout: Theory and Evidence, American Economic Review, 94, 1476-1504. Coate, S, M. Conlin and A. Moro (2004), The Performance of the Pivotal-Voter Model in Small-Scale Elections: Evidence from Texas Liquor Referenda, mimeo. Downs, A. (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York: Harper Collins. Feddersen, T. and W. Pesendorfer (1996), The Swing Voter s Curse, American Economic Review, 86, 404-424. Merlo, A. (2005), Whither Political Economy? Theories, Facts and Issues, PIER Working Paper No. 05-033.