Brief Remarks on the Unilateral Use of Force

Similar documents
State sovereignty and the protection of fundamental human rights: an international law perspective. by Alain Pellet

418 ALAIN PELLET. Alain Pellet

Should All References to International Crimes Disappear from the ILC Draft Articles on State Responsibility?

Andrew Clapham* Abstract. ... The Role of the Individual in International Law

WEBSTER UNIVERSITY. The future of the RESPONSIBILITY TO PROTECT. Genève, 9th December Keynote address by Cornelio Sommaruga

Chapter VI Identification of customary international law

Natalia Ochoa-Ruiz and Esther Salamanca-Aguado

ITUC OBSERVATIONS TO THE ILO COMMITTEE OF EXPERTS ON CONVENTION 87 AND THE RIGHT TO STRIKE

Book Review: War Law Understanding International Law and Armed Conflict, by Michael Byers

TOPIC EIGHT: USE OF FORCE. The use of force is of particular concern to the international community.

Countermeasures of General Interest

From Unity to Polarization: International Law and the Use of Force against Iraq

The General Assembly resolution requesting the Kosovo opinion and the ultra vires issue

Intervention vs. Sovereignty: Kosovo Conflict

Enver Hasani REVIEWING THE INTERNATIONAL ADMINISTRATION OF KOSOVO. Introduction

UNITING FOR PEACE : DOES IT STILL SERVE ANY USEFUL PURPOSE?

Preemptive Strikes: A New Security Policy Reality

Russia and the United Kingdom in the Changing World

Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court *

STATUTE OF THE INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL TRIBUNAL

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

International law and third-party countermeasures in the age of global instant communication. Carlo Focarelli

Speech on the 41th Munich Conference on Security Policy 02/12/2005

DISSENTING OPINION OF JUDGE KOROMA

SETTLEMENT OF DISPUTES CLAUSES. [Agenda item 15] Note by the Secretariat

PANEL II: GLOBAL ATTITUDES ON THE ROLE OF THE

REPORTS AND DOCUMENTS. Introduction : : : : : : :

Between Codification and ][>rogressive Development of the Law: Sorne Reflections from the ILC

Foreword: Human Rights and Non-Governmental Organizations on the Eve of the Next Century

International Humanitarian intervention in Kosovo

29. Security Council action regarding the terrorist attacks in Buenos Aires and London

DECLARATION OF JUDGE SKOTNIKOV

STATE RESPONSIBILITY MR. SANTIAGO VILLALPANDO. Santiago, Chile 24 April 19 May 2017

Introductory remarks at the Seminar on the Links between the Court and the other Principal Organs of the United Nations.

IV. CZECH PRACTICE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

LEGAL STANDARDS FOR INTERVENTION IN INTERNAL CONFLICTS

I. INTRODUCTION II. EVALUATING THE DIRECT CONNECTION REQUIREMENT IN RESPECT OF THE FIRST AND SECOND COUNTER-CLAIMS

Part Four GENERAL PROVISIONS

Responsibility to Protect Engaging Civil Society A Project of the World Federalist Movement s Program on Preventing Conflicts -Protecting Civilians

Examiners report 2010

Counter-measures as Interim Measures

Humanity as the A and Ω of Sovereignty: A Rejoinder to Emily Kidd White, Catherine E. Sweetser, Emma Dunlop and Amrita Kapur

Political Will and Multilateral Cooperation in International Justice

Recognition and secessionist in the complex environment of world politics

The advisory function of the International Court of Justice. 5 November Mr. Chairman, distinguished delegates, Ladies and Gentlemen,

No. 2010/25 22 July Accordance with international law of the unilateral declaration of independence in respect of Kosovo.

X Conference of Forte de Copacabana International Security A European South American Dialogue

A Vision of U.S. Security in the 21st Century Address by former Secretary of Defence Robert S. McNamara. ECAAR Japan Symposium, 28 August, 1995

For a Universal Declaration of Democracy

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Third Committee (A/65/456/Add.2 (Part II))]

Volume II. ARTICLE 13(1)(a)

Vladimir Ortakovski. University St. Kliment Ohridski, Skopje, Macedonia. Use of Force According to United Nations Charter

SECRET. 2. As I have previously advised, there are generally three possible bases for the use of force:

European Parliament recommendation to the Council of 18 April 2013 on the UN principle of the Responsibility to Protect ( R2P ) (2012/2143(INI))

THE NON-ALIGNED MOVEMENT

Resolved: United Nations peacekeepers should have the power to engage in offensive operations.

SOCIALIST REPUBLIC OF VlEINAM MISSION TO THE UNITED NATIONS 866 UNITED NATIONS PLAZA

I. WORKSHOP 1 - DEFINITION OF VICTIMS, ROLE OF VICTIMS DURING REFERRAL AND ADMISSIBILITY PROCEEDINGS5

Protection of Persons in the Event of Disasters

The 1954 Hague Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict and the notion of military necessity by Jan Hladík

RESERVATION TO TREATIES A. BACKGROUND

Self-Judging Self-Defense

The Yugoslav Crisis and Russian Policy: A Field for Cooperation or Confrontation? 1

Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. [on the report of the Sixth Committee (A/56/589 and Corr.1)]

CONSTANZE SCHULTE, COMPLIANCE WITH DECISIONS OF THE INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE (OXFORD: OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS, 2004) Par Sébastien Jodoin*

VI. READING ASSIGNMENTS International Law (Laws ) Fall 2008

Germany and the Middle East

Advancing the Disarmament Debate: Common Ground and Open Questions

National Model United Nations New York

Peter Katzenstein, ed. The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics

Threat or Use of Weapons of Mass Destruction and the Right to Life: Follow-up Submissions

Democracy, Prudence, Intervention

Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969

Association of the Bar of the City of New York Human Rights Committee

The Opinions of the Badinter Arbitration Committee A Second Breath for the Self-Determination of Peoples

SEPARATE OPINION OF JUDGE SETTE-CAMARA

Note établie par le Bureau Permanent * * *

VIENNA CONVENTION ON THE LAW OF TREATIES

The Kosovo Opinion and General International Law: How Far-reaching and Controversial is the ICJ s Reasoning?

2000 words. Your topic: Analytical & Research Skills Coursework. Your topic's description: Assessment for the Law in Global Context Module

The International Community facing Libyan and Syrian crisis: two different standards of evaluation

CHANGING NORMS OF UNILATERAL INTERVENTIONISM

AFFIRMATION OF THE PRINCIPLES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

The University of Edinburgh. From the SelectedWorks of Ray Barquero. Ray Barquero, Mr., University of Edinburgh. Fall October, 2012

Introduction THE INTERNATIONAL TRIBUNAL FOR THE FORMER YUGOSLAVIA: A CASE STUDY IN SECURITY COUNCIL ACTION

Fiji Comments on the Discussion Paper on implementation of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court

The Protection of the Civilian Population and NATO Bombing on Yugoslavia: Comments on a Report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY

Unit 7 Station 2: Conflict, Human Rights Issues, and Peace Efforts. Name: Per:

New York, 28 October 2010

CASE CONCERNING MILITARY AND PARAMILITARY ACTIVITIES IN AND AGAINST NICARAGUA. (Nicaragua v. United States of America) ICJ Decision of 27 June 1986

ANDREAS ZIMMERMANN & RAINER HOFMANN, ED., UNITY AND DIVERSITY IN INTERNATIONAL LAW (BERLIN: DUNCKER & HUMBLOT, 2006) By Mario Prost

State-by-State Positions on the Responsibility to Protect

APPLYING THE HUMANITARIAN INTERNATIONAL LAW IN DESTRUCTURED INTERNAL CONFLICTS

HUMAN RIGHTS AND THE NEW WORLD ORDER

What is humanitarian accountability?

The United Nations and Peacekeeping in Cambodia, Former Yugoslavia and Somalia, Chen Kertcher

INTERNATIONAL PROGRESS ORGANIZATION

ALIGARH MUSLIM UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF POLITICAL SCIENCE. A SYLLABUS FOR M. Phil/Ph.D. COMMON ADMISSION TEST

ARTICLE 51. Table of Contents

The International Criminal Court: Trigger Mechanisms for ICC Jurisdiction

Transcription:

BIlL 2000 Brief Remarks on the Unilateral Use of Force Alain Pellet* Abstract There can be no doubt that the NATO action in Kosovo can (and must) be seen as legitimate, while, on the other hand, the jamming of the Security Council by China and Russia cannot. The actual lawfulness of the initiative, however, is more debatable, even though arguments based both on the UN Charter and on the law of state responsibility can be made in its favour and indeed become persuasive when seen together with, and in Iight cf, Resolution 1244 (1999) of the Security Council. Nevertheless, it is essential thal new 'community' mechanisms be found in the future in order to avoid being restricted to a choice between the 'Zorro' principle (as applied in Kosovo) and the Munich policy. A revivaj' of Resolution 'Dean Acheson' (1950) and a deepening of the notion oj'state crime' ami its consequences provide, among others, possibilities for limiting the need for legitimate but legaijy dubious unilateral uses of force. The task of a commentator may be both easy and difficult: easy since one may simply hand out good and bad marks and have the final word on the subject; difficult since, if the main authors have examined the issues thoroughly and intelligently, there may remain little to be said. It is definitely a case of the latter in taking up the task of commenting upon the articles by Ruth Wedgwood and Vera Gowlland-Debbas. Both authors have covered the issues in great depth and, what i8 more, l find myselflargely in agreement with them. These authors have focused on a single debate seen at different angles - a debate that can be summarized in two short questions: when is unilateral action lawful? and - when such an action is unlawful, can it be legitimate? To this last question, the answer is, indisputably: 'Yes, of course, it might be, and it sometimes is, legitimate, to disregard the law.' This holds true in l,he domestic sphere as weil as in interuational society and, in the long term, there can be no doubt: Antigone always triumphs over Creon. This issue has been recently dealt with by both Bruno Simma and Antonio Cassese * Professor. University of Paris X-Nanterre: Member. International Law Commission. BJLL (2000), Vol. 11 No. 2, 385-392

386 BJIL 11 (2000), 385-392 in their very stimulating articles about the Kosovo crisis published in this Journal. 1 While they do not agree on important points, both writers try to reconcile the ethical and the legal perspectives, but they do so differently, Briefly, Slmma seems to consider that NATO's intervention was not 'that much' illegal and that the 'thin red line' was not 'really' crossed, while Cassese says, approximately: 'lndeed the intervention was illegal - but this is not the important issue and, in any case, it constitutes an important precedent.' There should be no difficulty with this approach. Law is not an aim per se and even if it is to be hoped that (social) moral standards and legal rules will usually coincide, the latter can be forgotten (ifthey shock the human conscience), However, for a lawyer this is not fully satisfactory, Such reasoning compel:> one to oppose the ethical perspective on the one hand and the legal approach on the other. The question can therefore be posed from another angle: in situations like Kosovo, or Rwanda, or East Timor, is the choice exclusively between the 'Munich principle' (and this would be the result ofthe 'legalistic' approach) and the 'Zorro principle' (that is, an unlawful but legitimate intervention)? In this respect, it is worth recalling a very 'Franco-French' debate that has raged among French internationallawyers for about 12 years on the so-called 'droit' or 'devoir d'ingérence' (the right or dut y to intervene), When it was launched in the late 1980s by Bernard Kouchner and Mario Bettati 2 it engendered both irony and scepticism, 1 In very broad terms, the ide a is that, in the case of a humanitarian catastrophe, whatever its cause (civil war, famine, natural disaster), external actors have a right or/and a dut y to intervene, lnitially, however, this doctrine was mainly aimed at justifying an intervention by humanitarian NGOs, not by foreign states,4 It does not, therefore, really solve the problem when states (and the use of armed force) are involved: if such a thing as the devoir d'ingérence does exist, it would legitimate in law 'Zorro's interventions' by NGOs, but leaves open the question of the legality of third states' interventions, In any case, it begs the question: Does such a devoir d'ingérence exist, legally speaking? Simma, 'NATO, the UN and the Use ofporce: Legal Aspects', 10 EJIL (1999) 1-22: Cassesc, 'Ex injuria ius oritur: Are We Moving towards International Legitimization ofporcible Hnmanitarian Countermeasures in the World Community?', 10 8J1L (1999) 23-30: for a third approach, see Pellet, '''La guerre du Kosovo" - Le fait rattrapé par le droit', Forum international (1999) 160-165, On this debate, sec e,g, M, Bettati and B. Kouchner (eds), Le devoir d'ingérence (1987); 0, Corten and p, Klein, Droit d'ingérence ou obliqalion de réaction? (1992); Alain Pellet led,), Droit d'ingérence ou devoir d'assistance humanitaire? Problèmes politiques et sociaux, nos, 758-759, 1-22 December 1995, Doc, Française; or M, Bettati. Le droil d'ingérence - Mutation de l'ordre international (1996), 1 must say that 1 was among those who were, at the time, at least sceptical. 1 still doubt that the words werc approprialely chosen: nearly as a malter of definition, 'intervention' is negalive!y considered in the international sphere and the 1Crs radical condemnalion in 1949 (see judgment of 9 April 1949 in the Corji, Channel case, lcj Reports (J 949) 35) slill holds true today, Howe17cr, the very ide a that lies at the origin of the concepl is worth consideration, lt has now bcen expanded by ils proponcllts, Thus, for example, Dr Kouchner dcfines the UN action in Kosovo as an illustration of the devoir d'ingérence,

Brie! Remarks on the Unilateral' Use of Force 387 Indeed, as shown by Wedgwood and Gowlland-Debbas, the Kosovo crisis is probably the most appropriate case to choose for discussing the problem in concrete terms. However, the relevance of this example should to sorne extent be qualified. As aptly noted by Ruth Wedgwood in a l'ecent article, 'A NATO decision de serves greater deference than purely unilateral action'. 5 This is persuasive: NATO's intervention in Serbia is an illustration of 'regional or collective unilateralism', not of purely 'state unilateralism'; it implies at least sorne checks and balances, both in the decisionmaking andin action (even though this argumentis disliked bythe United States). The Kosovo case would nevertheless have been clearer if Yugoslavia had been part of the Alliance, and one hypothesis where unilateralism could be acceptable is intervention inside a regional alliance; in this respect' African unilateralisms', referred to in sorne of the papers in this Symposium, are often different in nature from the Kosovo case. This being said, my own views on Kosovo are not far from those of Wedgwood and Gowlland-Debbas. My first reaction was to follow Antonio Cassese's rather 'schizophrenic' approach and to see NATO's intervention as legitimate, but unlawful, but since then Resolution 1244 (1999) has reconciled lawfulness with llegitimacy, at least bearing in mind the general pattern of arguments that could have been made since the very beginning ofnato's strikes. When taken in isolation, none ofthem seems to me probative; taken together in light of Resolution 1244, they make, l think, a good legal case. Right from the beginning, two tracks could have been explored by international lawyers (and they have been): the law of international responsibility on the one hand, that of the UN legal framework on the other. Professor Gowlland-Debbas has particularly stressed the first aspect. but she has linked it very closely with the 'UN track'. However, even though she accepts that they do not entirely merge, she suggests that these two chapters ofinternationallaw come so close to each other that they almost become as one. That is doubtful. Both bodies oflegal rnles work in a similar way in many respects. But this does not mean that the Charter mechanisms are part of the general law of international responsibility or that both regimes are entirely intermingled - and for a conclusive reason: their purposes are clearly distinct. As made clear in Articles 1 and 3 of the ILC Draft Articles on State Responsibility, responsibility is the global mechanism - which exists in alliegai systems - that deals with the consequences of a wrongful act. For its part, the Charter is not concerned with the enforcement of legal mies, but with the maintenance of peace. Of course, it can happen - it is to be hoped more often than nat - that both aims coincide. However, the coincidence is purely fortuitous. l cannot agree with Vera Gowlland-Debbas when she suggests that a decision of the Secu:rity Council under Chapter VII can be seen as a circumstance precluding wrongfulness under the generall mies of the law of responsibility. If compliance with a Chapter VII decision precludes wrongfulness, it is because of Article 103 of the Charter and has nothing to do with the law of state responsibility as such. At best the Charter could be seen as a 'NATO's Campaign in Yugoslavia', 93 fljil (1999) 833.

388 EJIL 11 (2000), 38 S~392 'self-contained responsibility régime', 6 although sorne arguments in favour of NATO' s intervention in Serbia can certainly be based on the law of state responsibility, There can be little doubt that ethnie cleansing was being committed in Kosovo before March 1999 and the Bosnian precedent showed how far it could have gone (there were no less than 200,000 deaths in Bosnia and Herzegovina). Nor can there be any real doubt that ethnie cleansing amounts to genocide, an indisputable 'crime' in the meaning of Article 19 of the ILC Draft Articles,7 and, even more, a 'crime against the peace and security of mankind'. H One of the consequences of such a crime is that au members of the international community may, and probably must, react to su ch an internationally wrongful act. 9 But - and this is an important 'but' - there is at least a limit to this right or dut y of reaction: the prohibition of the use of force, except when in accordance with the UN Charter, and it seems dubious that astate could react to a crime by breaching another peremptory norm of general internationallaw. lo The other body of legal rules which could have been invoked as being relevant by NATO in Kosovo is the UN Charter norms. Here again arguments can be made - and they have been made, in different forms. both by Ruth Wedgwood and by Vera Gowlland-Debbas: First, it must be borne in mind that the Security Council had determined. in Resolutions 1160. 1199,1203 (1998) and 1239 (1999), ail under Chapter VII of the Charter, that the situation in Kosovo constituted a threat to the peace. However, and, here again, this is a big 'but', a threat to the peace is different from an armed attack. While, in this llast hypothesis, members of the UN may resort to collective or individual self-defence until the Security Couneil takes 'such action as it deems necessary in order to maintain or restore international peace and security' (Article 51), the only legal consequence of a finding that a situation constitutes a threat to the peace is that the Council itselfis entitled to authorize or to decide recourse to armed force. The Security Council's findings under Article III On self-contained régimes, see e.g. Simma, 'Self-Contained Régirr.es', NYBIL (1995) 111~136; Riphagen's 3rd Report on State Responsibility, A/CNA/366. ILe Yearbook (1982), Vol. II, Part 1. paras 72-73 and Arangio-Ruiz's 3rd Report, A/CN.4/440, ILC Yearbook (1991), Vol. II, PartI. paras 84-88. The most unfortunate paragraph 3 of Article 19 cites among the four categories of crimes that il lists serions breaches of international obligations 'of essenlial importance for safeguarding the hnman being, such as those prohibiting slavery, genocide and apartheid' (sec ILC, Repart on the Work of ils 48th Session (1996), GA Official Records. Supplement No. 10. A/51110, at 131). Sec Article 17 of the ILC Draft Code of Crimes against the Peace and Security ol'mankind, ibid., at 85-86. See the very poody conceived Articles 40, para. 3. and 51-53 of the ILC draft on State Responsibility, ibid" at 141 and 146. The recenlly (Jnne 1999) and provisionally adopted Article 29 bis ofthe ILC draft does not change the picture. Il provides that '[t]he wrongfulness 01' an aet of astate 'ls precluded if the aet is requircd in the circumstances by a peremptory norm of general inlernationallaw'. Il would have a role to play if, and only if, the 'dutyto intervcne' in 1he case of genocidc would have a peremptory character; and il would be ditlîcult to go that far.

Brie! Remarks on the UnilaterallJse of Force 389 39 of the Charter can certainly not be equated with the decision to take action under Article 42. 11 Secondly. similarly, little can be inferred from the negative vote of 3 to 12 on the Indian (and others') proposai condemning NATO's action. It cannot be accepted that a non-decision is equivalent to a decision and certainly not to a 'legitimizing' decision. Otherwise, a veto by any of the so-called 'big five' would legally transform any unlawful act into a legal one and this cannot be so. The legal conclusion is, and must be, that there was a case for NATO's action; but, at least if taken in isolation, the legal arguments in favour of it were not persuasive enough to make it a winning case. Simma' s 'thin red line' existed when NATO decided its action in Serbia and still existed when it put it into operation. However, and, on this point, l entirely agree with Ruth Wedgwood, Resolution 1244 (1999) dramatically changed the picture. Indeed, it does not formally declaœ that NATO's intervention was lawful - and, in any case, this is not the Security Council's dut y - and both China and Russia maintained that they did not accept its legality. However, it clearly endorses the consequences of this intervention and it cannot be seriously maintained that the principal organ of the United Nations vested with the 'primary responsibility for the maintenance of international peace and security' (which includes the determination of the existence of an act of aggression - Article 39) would have given its blessing to such an act if only because one effect of a crime (and an act of aggression 12 too is a crime 1,) can legally pro duce no consequence nor can its consequences be recognized under any circumstances. As the, very 'shy', Article 53(a) of the ILC Draft Articles on State Responsibility puts it: 'An international crime committed by astate entails an obligation for every other State: (a) not to recognize as lawful the situation created by the crime...'.14 In other words, there certainly were doubts as to the legality of NATO's action before 10 June 1999. However. when put together. the arguments in favour of its lawfulness become persuasive - and particularly so in light of Resolution 1244. At the end of the day legality meets legitimacy. This does not mean that the picture is satisfactory. The ex post frarcto legalization of NATO' s intervention in Serbia is unfortunate and introduces in the internationallegal order a part of uncertainty which is deeply repugnant to the very function of law in any society 1 sand it is impossible to assume that it will not happelll again in similar situations in the future. But, here, as Casse se notes, in the future, the Kosovo case will constitute a very powerful precedent. 1\ In this respect. perhaps Professor Wedgwood goes tao far in aggregating both kinds ofresolution: under Article 39 the Council defines a situation: under Articles 41 and 42. it decides rneasures. 12 TfNATO's action were not lawlli!. J do not see how it could be legally qualified bul as an act of aggression (which is what it is called in Milosevic's Yugoslavia). Il See Article 19, para. 3(a), of the ILC draft, slipra note 7, at 131. 14 Il/id..,li 14fi. This is not only a consequence of the 'Stimson doctrine' as Ruth Wedgwood alleges. 15 However, il must be noted in passing that all domestic systems arc acquainled wilh thc 'disreputable' use of 'rcgularization statules' which caver up previous unlawful administrative behaviours.

-_.--.----------_. 390 BJlL 11 (2000), 385-392 This rather unfortunate situation could have been avoided by reviving the resolution 'United for Peace'.- and in this respect 1 must dissociate myselffrom Vera Gowlland-Debbas, Resolution 377(V) was precisely adopted in view of situations where the Security Council is not in a position to assume its primary (but not exclusive) responsibility conferred upon it by Article 24 of the UN Charter, And it has, during the last 50 years, been used in sufficiently varied situations as to cover its possible original 'constitulcional' wealmess,16 However, Resolution Dean Acheson has not been used - a sign of the arrogance of the big powers as well as of the disappearance of the Third World from the international scene. There is no doubt that the latter was ill at ease with an action which it probably approved from a political point of view, 17 but was not de siro us of giving its blessing to a 'threatening' precedent and chose a low profile, thus missing an opportunity to regild the prestige of the not unjustly discredited General Assembly, For their part, the United States and its allies were certainly willing to avoid interference from the 'plebeian' Assembly in their 'leadership' - another name for (illegitimate) hegemony, It is crystal clear that the United States' claimed and self-appointed 'leadership' drives it to not infrequent intolerable unilateral aets (the Helms-Burton or D'Amato Acts) or actions (Granada, Nicaragua, Panama",),lH But they are in good company and it cannot be denied that other big (or semi-big) states are far from irreproachable in this respect, including the European Communities, or India, or China, or even France which is described in Ruth Wedgwood's paper as the 'fifth gendarme' (and which would probably like to be the second!), There is, however, a difference. There is but one superpower - and 1 suggest that this imposes upon it a special burden and a special dut y of self-restraint. lt may not always act accordingly, and this might explain why, seen from Europe, US good conscience is more olten than not resented as ideological, economic, poiitical and ev en military arrogance since, when used outside any multilateral machinery, unilateralism is the means for such arrogance, Power does not confer 'leadership', but special responsibility, This being said, the main point must not be lost from sight: whatever the respective responsibilities of the Western Group, and primarily, of the United States, and, to a much lesser extent of the Third W orld, the main states deserving blame in the circumstances are those, namely China and Russia, which impeded the Security Council from deciding on measures equal to the situation created by Yugoslavia in 16 For a reliable review of cases (before 1980) where recourse was made to the Dean Achcson Resolution, sec J.F. Guilhaudis, 'Consid(~rations sur la pratique de l'union pour le maintien de la paix', AFD.I (1981) 382-398. See also P. Daillier and A. Pellet, DroilintemationaljJublic (Nguyen Quoe Dinh), 6th ed.. (1999) 815-816 and 957. 17 For once, it seems difficult to ascribe undisclosable or shameful desigm; to the Western powers: they have (to their cost) reacted to crimes against a Moslem and a poor population; wilh no ail and no 'Monicagate' lh in sighl. This unl(mnded messianie approach is reflccted and (hopefully) caricalured in Allan Gerson's paper in the pre via us issue of this journal.

BriefRemarks on tlle Unilateml Use of Force 391 Kosovo. Whatever the legality of NATO's intervention, their opposition to any credible answer to Milosevic's cynical enterprise was indeed illegitimate. In an article published in 1988 in the American Journal of International Law, Ruth Wedgwood wrote that '[ u ]nilateralism sits uncomfortably in a muitilateral world'.19 This might be an over-optimistic view since it implies that the world has become truly multilateral, which, in turn, presupposes that the change from the Westphalian inter-states society to a communities-oriented international law has already taken place. Indeed, the world has changed.. The League of Nations Covenant, then the UN Charter, have introduced a dose of multilateralism into international relations. It remains that 'community' mechanisms have never worked well- and for sever al reasons: sometimes, the danger remained outside the world organization (this was the case during the inter-war period); or the balance of powers was not properly calibrated, either because it was bilateral and 'too equal' (or seen as being so), as was the case during the Cold War, or because it is too unequal, as it is now. This explains the permanence of a private justice in the international sphere,20 which can find a lawful expression in 'legitimate countermeasures', or in an unacceptable unilateralism, as saon as it cornes to the use of force without authorization from a responsible international organ, that is, primarily, the Security Council and, in the last resort, the General Assembly of the United Nations. This form ofunilateralism must be firmly rejected, whether the US, China or France (or others) like it or not. The paradox here is that community values have made progress at the conceptual and, to a lesser extent, at the normative levels but, at the same time, this development encourages resort to unilateral measures. Suffice it to mention the notion of state crimes 21 which is, no doubt, a progression in the direction of community values since it shows that at least sorne forms ofunilateralism are simply Intolerable in the modern world. But, simultaneously, this induces a 'counter (or neo-)unilateralism' since individual states, or groups of states, arrogate to themselves a unilateral right of reaction to the lack of accompanying institution al progress. It is the dut y of our generation (and the next ones) to strengthen and deepen these conceptual advances 22 and to see to it that they go hand in hand with parallel effective institutional mechanisms. If crimes are prevented, conceptually speaking, it will become indispensable to find sorne international machinery in order to neutralize the 19 'The Enforcement of Security Counci! Resolution 687: The Threat of Force against Iraq's Weapons of Mass Destruction', 92 AJIL (1998) 726 - emphasis added. 20 See D. Alland, Justice privée et ordre juridique international (1994). 21 The quickly devcloping 'international criminallaw' is another example. ~~ In this respect. il is to be hoped that the International Law Commission will Dot yield to the increasing pressures from sorne big states (not ail Western) which try (0 'kill' the very notion of 'state crime' - see Pelle!, 'Can a State Commit a Crime? Definitely, Yes!', ID EJlL (1999)42~,-434 and 'Vive le crime! Remarques sur les degrés de l'illicite en droit international' in ILC, International Law ai tlze Dawn of tlze Twenty~First Cmtury - Views from the I.L.C.. (1997) 287-315.

--------- -------------- 392 BILL 11 (2000), 385-392 unilateralist temptations of the big powers 21 exactly as the mechanism for dispute settlement has accompanied the definition of new rules of the game in trade relations 24 and has constituted a great achievement of 'communitarianism' versus 'unilateralism'. The same kind of evolution is desperately needed in the even more fundamental field of the maintenance and restoration of peace, in order to avoid in the future the very unsatisfying alternative between the 'Zorro' and 'Munich' principles, 2l The previous Special Rapporteur of the ILC on State Responsibility, Prol'essor Arangio-Ruiz, made some very innovative proposais in this respect (see in particular his seventh repor!, A/CN.4/469 and Add.l and 2, ILC Yearbook (1995). Vol. lit, Part 1), lml they were clearly unrealistic and, in any case, snch a construction is out of the mandate and reach of the Commission. '" The present writer docs Ilot share the undcrlying values inspiring these llew rules; the fact is, howcver, that they reflect a common multilateral approach by most of the members of the international society which has established correlative enforcement procedures.