Louisiana Law Review. Gary L. McDowell

Similar documents
REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia

American Constitutional Interpretation GLSP PAC 319 Wesleyan University Ext Syllabus. I Introduction

POLITICS AND THE CONSTITUTION IN THE HISTORY OF THE UNITED STATES, by William W. Crosskey. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, vols. $20.00.

The Influences of Legal Realism in Plessy, Brown and Parents Involved

Book Review: The American Judicial Tradition: Profiles of Leading American Judges, by G. Edward White

The Louisiana State Constitution: A Reference Guide, by Lee Hargrave. New York: Greenwood Press, Pp $55.

Book Review: American Constitutionalism: from Theory to Politics. by Stephen M. Griffin.

Foreword: Symposium on Federal Judicial Power

Federalists and anti-federalists The power of subtleties

Constitutional Law and Politics Comprehensive Exam and Reading List (Effective Fall, 2011)

Raoul Berger, Government by the Judiciary: The Transformation of the Fourteenth Amendment

The Doctrine of Judicial Review and Natural Law

US Government Module 2 Study Guide

NEW YORK COUNTY LAWYERS ASSOCIATION

PURPOSES AND RESPONSIBILITIES OF COURTS. INTRODUCTION: What This Core Competency Is and Why It Is Important

Location: This class will take place at George Washington University, District House (2121 H Street NW, Room 117).

Dedication: Chief Judge Charles Clark

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

STATE HEARING QUESTIONS

GEORGE MASON UNIVERSITY GOVT 420: American Political Thought Summer 2013

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

MIDDLE SCHOOL NATIONAL HEARING QUESTIONS ACADEMIC YEAR

Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review

How Do You Judge A Judge?

Constitutional Interpretation: Just Politics or Fidelity to the Past?

PH 3022 SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY UK LEVEL 5 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3

March 22, Examination of Goodwin Liu, Nominee to the United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit

WORKER'S COMPENSATION LAW AND PRACTICE Second Edition. By Wex S. Malone and H. Alston Johnson, III. West Publishing Co Pp. xvi and 654.

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Principles of the Entitlement State Remarks for the Hillsdale College Free Market Forum Atlanta - October, Ronald J.

From the veil of ignorance to the overlapping consensus: John Rawls as a theorist of communication

Book Review: How Does the Constitution Secure Rights? Edited by Robert A. Goldwin and William Schambra.

The Rule of Law, Core Texts and Liberal Education Rodney K. Smith, Trustee-American Academy for Liberal Education*

STATE HEARING QUESTIONS

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

Full file at

The Constitutional Foundations of Intellectual Property

IS STARE DECISIS A CONSTRAINT OR A CLOAK?

Big Idea 2 Objectives Explain the extent to which states are limited by the due process clause from infringing upon individual rights.

A Reply to Professor William Binchy on Constitutionality, the Rule of Law and Socio-Economic Development

Medellin's Clear Statement Rule: A Solution for International Delegations

Woodrow Wilson on Socialism and Democracy

Strategic Insights: Getting Comfortable with Conflicting Ideas

Of Inkblots and Originalism: Historical Ambiguity and the Case of the Ninth Amendment

IS IT TIME TO REWRITE THE CONSTITUTION? FIDELITY TO OUR IMPERFECT CONSTITUTION

Rethinking Administrative Deference

Separation of Powers: History and Theory

NATIONAL HEARING QUESTIONS ACADEMIC YEAR

McDONALD v. CITY OF CHICAGO 130 Sup. Ct (2010)

Section 1 What ideas gave birth to the world s first democratic nation?

Foundations of Government

CONSTITUTION DAY GUIDE

Louisiana Law Review. Robert A. Pascal. Volume 14 Number 3 April Repository Citation

5. Which of the following documents created a compromise that led to the formation of a bicameral legislature

Introduction The Politics of Original Intention

The Interpretation/Construction Distinction in Constitutional Law: Annual Meeting of the AALS Section on Constitutional Law: Introduction

Wednesday, February 29 th

The Progressivism of America s Founding

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

United States Constitutional Law: Theory, Practice, and Interpretation

Cambridge University Press Victory in War: Foundations of Modern Strategy William C. Martel Frontmatter More information

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Enlighten Me. Influential Enlightenment Ideas. Benchmarks

Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy

Law, Community, and Moral Reasoning: Foreword

Louisiana Law Review. Saul Litvinoff. Volume 34 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

NEO-CONSERVATISM IN THE USA FROM LEO STRAUSS TO IRVING KRISTOL

Unit 3: Building the New Nation FRQ Outlines. Prompt:Analyze the reasons for the Anti-Federalists opposition to ratifying the Constitution.

Towards a Theory of State Constitutional Jurisprudence

The Language of Law and the Foundations of American Constitutionalism

Unit 3- Hammering Out a Federal Republic

2018 Visiting Day. Law School 101 Room 1E, 1 st Floor Gambrell Hall. Robert A. Schapiro Asa Griggs Candler Professor of Law

Test Bank to accompany Constitutional Law, Third Edition (Hall/Feldmeier)

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

An Introduction to Documents of Freedom

An Independent Judiciary

Book Review: Government Discrimination: Equal Protection Law and Litigation

Theory Comprehensive January 2015

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

ORIGINALIST IDEOLOGY AND THE RULE OF LAW. Ian Bartrum *

Why do you think the Framers organized the new country as a republic, when most countries in the world (in 1783) were ruled by a king or queen?

2 approaches to curb mischiefs

Arkansas Social Studies Curriculum Framework United States Government

GREGORY S. WEINER Department of Political Science Assumption College 500 Salisbury Street Worcester, MA (703)

Competing Accounts of Interpretation and Practical Reasoning in the Debate over Originalism

We the People: The Citizen and the Constitution

1 st United States Constitution. A. loose alliance of states. B. Congress lawmaking body. C. 9 states had to vote to pass laws

3: A New Plan of Government. Essential Question: How Do Governments Change?

Some Thoughts on Political Structure as Constitutional Law

The Scope of Congressional Powers. Congressional Power. Strict Versus Liberal Construction

Global Ethics: An Introduction Written by Kimberly Hutchings Cambridge: Polity, 2010 (ISBN: ) 244pp.

AP American Government

The State of the Union under a failed Constitution. June 14, 1997

Philosophy 221/Political Science 221 Philosophical Foundations of the American Revolution

Faculty Advisor (former) to Black Law Student Association (BLSA) and National Lawyers Guild.

Vocabulary for Evolution of Government

STATE HEARING QUESTIONS

The House of Representatives shall be composed of Members chosen every second Year by the People of the several States.

Walter Berns s Constitution

The Articles of Confederation

Transcription:

Louisiana Law Review Volume 45 Number 3 The 1984 Revision of the Louisiana Civil Code's Articles on Obligations - A Student Symposium January 1985 The Moral Wish as Father to the Consitutional Thought - Constitutional Fate: Theory of the Constitution. New York: Oxford University Press, 1982. Pp. 285. $22.95 (Cloth), By Philip Bobbitt. $7.95 (paper). Gary L. McDowell Repository Citation Gary L. McDowell, The Moral Wish as Father to the Consitutional Thought - Constitutional Fate: Theory of the Constitution. New York: Oxford University Press, 1982. Pp. 285. $22.95 (Cloth), By Philip Bobbitt. $7.95 (paper)., 45 La. L. Rev. (1985) Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/lalrev/vol45/iss3/11 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at LSU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Louisiana Law Review by an authorized editor of LSU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact kayla.reed@law.lsu.edu.

BOOK REVIEW THE MORAL WISH AS FATHER TO THE CONSTITUTIONAL THOUGHT Constitutional Fate: Theory of the Constitution. New York: Oxford University Press, 1982. Pp. 285. $22.95 (Cloth), By Philip Bobbitt. $7.95 (paper). Reviewed by Gary L. McDowell* Like the old gray mare, constitutional theory just ain't what she used to be. There was a time-not so long ago, really-when constitutional theory was primarily concerned with analysis of the text of the Constitution.' No longer is this an article of faith. Prompted by the Warren Court's willingness to extend constitutional protection to rights neither explicitly found in the Constitution itself nor granted by prior constitutional jurisprudence, a new generation of lawyers, judges, and law professors has dedicated itself to taking rights seriously. It seems beyond doubt that the true legacy of the Warren Court will prove to be not so much its decisions in specific cases as the jurisprudential attitudes it spawned and nurtured. 2 Since the heyday of Warren Court activism, there has been a growing army of theorists whose efforts to bolster the intellectual integrity of Warren Court liberalism have all but cast the rest of the constitutional landscape in their moral shadows.' Believing, as Ronald Dworkin has put it, that there can be no progress until there has been a fusion of moral philosophy with constitutional law, contemporary theorists have unrelentingly pursued in the pages of the leading law reviews and under Copyright 1985, by LOUISIANA LAW REVIEW. * Director, Office of the Bicentennial of the Constitution, National Endowment for the Humanities. Assistant Professor of Political Science, Newcomb College, Tulane University. B.A., 1972 University of South Florida; M.A., 1974, Memphis State University; A.M., 1978, University of Chicago; Ph.D., 1979, University of Virginia. 1. See, e.g., Graves v. New York ex rel. O'Keefe, 306 U.S. 466, 491-92 (1939) (Frankfurter, J., concurring) ("[T]he ultimate touchstone of constitutionality is the Constitution itself and not what we have said about it."); 3 C. Warren, The Supreme Court in United States History 470 (1922) ("However the court may interpret the provisions of the Constitution, it is still the Constitution which is the law, not the decisions of the court."). 2. Wright, Professor Bickel, the Scholarly Tradition, and the Supreme Court, 84 Harv. L. Rev. 769, 804 (1971). 3. See, e.g., A. Miller, Toward Increased Judicial Activism (1982); M. Perry, The Constitution, the Courts, and Human Rights (1982); L. Tribe, American Constitutional Law (1978).

LOUISIANA LA W REVIEW [Vol. 45 the imprints of the most respected publishing houses what Alexander M. Bickel described as America's quest for moral self-government. 4 As a result, those with an interest in constitutional jurisprudence have been forced to chop their way through a "jungle of moral philosophy theories."' In the old days, constitutional theory was understood to move between the poles of "strict construction" and "loose construction," between what used to be called a Jeffersonian view of the Constitution and a Hamiltonian view. But all has changed. Now constitutional theory is understood to move between something called "noninterpretive" judicial review and "interpretive" judicial review. In the old school the question was how to read the Constitution; in the new, the question is whether to read the Constitution. As a result, contemporary constitutional theory has little to do with the explication of the constitutional text or its intention. Today constitutional theory is generally comprised of innovative constructions of moral theories that are then superimposed on the Constitution-if, indeed, the document is considered at all. Few writers display this modern proclivity as candidly as Philip Bobbitt. To those who endeavor to take the Constitution-both its text and its original intention-seriously, this is indeed a book, as one commentator has described it, that one "instantly dislikes." '6 This is not to say that this is a book totally devoid of merit. It is of value for two reasons. First, Professor Bobbitt's typology of constitutional theories is helpful in sorting through a collection of writings that might otherwise strike one as imponderable if not simply impenetrable. The second value of Constitutional Fate is more substantive. This book shows just how far awry good intentions can go, and the danger to the Constitution that is the result of such murky moralizing and ideological meandering. Constitutional Fate sketches for the reader the current contours of constitutional theory. Beginning with what he calls the Historical Argument, or the intentions of the Framers, Professor Bobbitt leads his reader through the various other arguments that describe the ways people think about the Constitution. Through his analysis the author moves from the concrete to the more abstract. The Historical Argument, he concludes, is ultimately "more effective as rhetoric than as decision procedure. ' 7 The Textual Argument-the present sense of the language of the document-holds out greater opportunities; it is a theoretical device that "provides a valve through which contemporary values can be intermingled with the Constitution." ' Moving still further along', one 4. A. Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch (1962). 5. R. Berger, Death Penalties: The Supreme Court's Obstacle Course 181 n.1 (1982). 6. Agresto, Book Review, Benchmark 55 (Mar.-Apr. 1984). 7. P. Bobbitt, Constitutional Fate: Theory of the Constitution 24 (1982). 8. Id. at 36.

1985] BOOK REVIEW finds the Structural Argument, a belief that certain results are implicit in the institutional relationships created by the Constitution. This is a still looser way of thinking about constitutional law in that the conclusions one can reach do not depend upon the confining and peculiar facts of a particular case; rather, they "arise from general assertations about power and social choice." 9 Even farther away from the morally shackling provisions of the literal Constitution, one can take solace in the Prudential Argument, the understanding that constitutional doctrines are best advanced by practical wisdom; cases are rightly decided by consideration not so much of the constitutional text as by reference to "the political and economic circumstances 0 surrounding the decision."' Finally, one bumps up against the Doctrinal Argument. The principal premise of this line of reasoning is "the notion that the judicial function with respect to the Constitution is essentially a common law function."" While Bobbitt finds each of the approaches helpful in thinking about the Constitution and constitutional law (a distinction not terribly important in his jurisprudential efforts), they are, taken both separately and collectively, deficient. What is missing is precisely what Bobbitt purports to supply: a line of constitutional reasoning that will "help 1 justify particularly difficult and otherwise troublesome 2 decisions.' What that means, at bottom, is a more amorphous constitutional argument that can be used on demand to justify decisions with which the commentator agrees but for which there is no clear support-be it historical, structural, textual, doctrinal, or prudential. What is needed is what Professor Bobbitt offers in his own name: The Ethical Argument. The Ethical Argument the author has in mind is an argument advancing a particular view of constitutional meaning that is an attempt to free constitutional law from the cold, dead hand of the past. His quest is for a constitutional theory whereby "the present... [can] control the past."' 3 The crux of the Ethical Argument is that it seeks to advance, not sterile institutions or stale intentions or precedents, but nothing less than the "ethos of the American polity.' ' 4 The mechanics of the Ethical Argument are neither too complex, nor too new. 5 In making an ethical argument, Bobbitt argues, the text is often used "not for its own force, but rather as evidence of a more general principle from which a nontextual argument was derived.' ' 1 6 For 9. Id. at 74. 10. Id. at 61. 11.* Id. at 44. 12. Id. at 93. 13. Id. at 239. 14. Id. at 94. 15. See Fiss, Foreword-The Supreme Court 1978 Term: The Forms of Justice, 93 Harv. L. Rev. 1 (1979); Chayes, The Role of the Judge in Public Law Litigation, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1281 (1976). 16. P. Bobbitt, supra note 7, at 142.

834 LOUISIANA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 45 example, "the textual provision of the Eighth Amendment which forbids cruel and unusual punishment is evidence of a more general constitutional ethos, one principle of which is that government must not physically degrade the persons for whose benefit it is created. 1' 7 This is more than a mere leap of logic; it is a case of the moral wish being father to the constitutional thought." The ultimate object Bobbitt seeks to achieve by tapping this great American ethos is to transform constitutional law from mere litigation into a moral source for the development and articulation of a national constitutional conscience. At the most profound level, this is nothing more than an argument for the political resuscitation of the often maligned doctrine of substantive due process: not the old substantive due process rooted in a theory of property rights, but a new substantive due process rooted in what has come to be seen as a polar opposite of property rights-human rights.1 9 This new substantive due process is ''necessary" given the "necessarily partial list of rights which is the Bill of Rights." 20 As Bobbitt puts it, "substantive due process is ethical argument by another name. That is, the attempt to require of states a process that yields fair legislation is in part a reflection of the constitutional ethos of limited government." 2 ' Thus by Bobbitt's standards the Constitution is more than a constitution. It is, he argues, "our Mona Lisa, our Eiffel Tower, our Marseillaie." 22 And in this spirit, our Bill of Rights is much more than a catalog of restrictions on government. "The particular Bill of Rights we have," Bobbitt suggests, "serves, and seems chosen to serve, as more than a text for exegesis. It acts to give us a constitutional motif, a cadence of our rights, so that once heard, we can supply the rest on our own." 23 Not only is the Bill of Rights the theoretical heart of the Constitution; the Bill of Rights exists less in its letter than in the spirit evoked by whatever moral mood happens to move a majority of justices. This is not a constitution designed to be a popular constitution of limited powers; this is an unlimited constitution with a moral vengeance. In the end Bobbitt's enterprise is highly undemocratic. The judiciary is often morally obligated to push the constitutional ethos in the face of "the largely inchoate notions of the people generally." ' 24 The point 17. Id. at 143. 18. See R. Berger, supra note 5, at 194. 19. See generally B. Siegan, Economic Liberties and the Constitution (1980). 20. P. Bobbitt, supra note 7, at 147. 21. Id. at 168. 22. Id. at 185. 23. Id. at 177. 24. Id. at 211.

19851 BOOK REVIEW of judicial power is not to define constitutional lines and limits but to give "concrete expression to the unarticulated values of a diverse nation." '2 Not that these values are in any way permanent; the constitutional ethos itself changes. 26 There are two problems with this logic that instantly float to the surface of such an argument. First, it is not clear, as Bobbitt seems to believe with Owen Fiss and others, that judges are possessed of a "special substantive rationality" that enables them to discover unarticulated values. They are, after all, only lawyers who usually find their way to the bench, not by moral or intellectual virtue, but by their political attachments and ideological inclinations. Secondand this is the deeper problem-it is not clear that the form of popular government which our Constitution creates and empowers can logically be understood to rest on unarticulated values that are discerned and applied by officers of that government. The first presumption of the legitimacy of popular government is that it has something to do with popular opinion. That is not to say that popular opinion can never be wrong or never be tyrannical; at least since James Madison penned the tenth 'essay of The Federalist we have known better. But it is to say that there is a great distance between a court that says what government cannot do on the basis of the terms of a written constitution and a court that says what government should do to give moral vent to unarticulated values. The judges, no less than any other officials or even the people, were not expected to be "the philosophical race of kings wished for by Plato." 27 At its deepest level Constitutional Fate is a rhetorically shimmering attempt to argue for the notion of a "living" constitution. It is an argument that holds that a written constitution of limited powers and clearly drawn rights can only be given proper effect by ignoring it. It is an argument, not for a constitution of fixed principle deemed by its creators as fundamental and designed with the hope that it would last, if not forever, then surely for ages and only alterable by the "most solemn and authorative" act of amendment, 28 but for a "participatory Constitution ' 29 whose meaning is understood to rest on nothing firmer than time, circumstances, and the shrewd insights of a judge bent on doing justice for the people in spite of themselves. 25. Id. 26. Id. at 221. 27. The Federalist No. 49, at 340 (J. Madison) (J. Cooke ed. 1961). 28. McDowell, On Meddling with the Constitution, 5 J. Contemp. Stud. 3, 4 (Fall 1982). 29. P. Bobbitt, supra note 7, at 235.

LOUISIANA LA W REVIEW [Vol. 45 This approach of taking rights seriously-an approach of "considerable passion and conviction" 30 -serves in the end only to take the Constitution frivolously. 3 To view rights as a matter of judicial beneficence rather than as the result of limited government is to ignore what most threatens rights. Bobbitt and others of his jurisprudential persuasion like Laurence Tribe and Michael Perry too easily dismiss the hardearned wisdom of the founding generation, certainly a generation that knew something about rights. To them rights would not be secure if they depended simply on public officials-any public officials, judges included-for their protection. Nor did they think rights could only be secured by a bill of rights. 3 2 The Founders were deeper than that; their theories reflected a far more profound appreciation of human nature than do those of our contemporary theorists. 33 To the Founders, the Bill of Rights was not much more than a "fitting close to the parenthesis around the Constitution that the preamble opens." 3 a4 The substance of their constitutional design lay in "a design of government with powers to act and a structure arranged to make it act wisely and responsibly. It is in that design, not in its preamble or its epilogue, that the security of American civil and political liberty lies." 35 '3 6 "In our theories," Professor Bobbitt concludes, "shall be our fates. With constitutional theories such as Professor Bobbitt's, there is greater cause for concern than for comfort. 30. Id. at 94. 31. See Berns, Judicial Review and the Rights and Laws of Nature, 1982 Sup. Ct. Rev. 49. 32. See The Federalist No. 84 (A. Hamilton) (J. Cooke ed. 1961). 33. See, e.g., Diamond, The Federalist, in History of Political Philosophy 631 (L. Strauss & J. Cropsey 2d ed. 1972). 34. Storing, The Constitution and the Bill of Rights, in Taking the Constitution Seriously: Essays on the Constitution and Constitutional Law 266, 280 (G. McDowell ed. 1981). 35. Id. 36. P. Bobbitt, supra note 7, at 242.