Many Social Choice Rules

Similar documents
answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Economics 470 Some Notes on Simple Alternatives to Majority Rule

Fairness Criteria. Majority Criterion: If a candidate receives a majority of the first place votes, that candidate should win the election.

Today s plan: Section : Plurality with Elimination Method and a second Fairness Criterion: The Monotocity Criterion.

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Elections with Only 2 Alternatives

Social Choice: The Impossible Dream. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

Fairness Criteria. Review: Election Methods

MATH 1340 Mathematics & Politics

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2017

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued

Measuring Fairness. Paul Koester () MA 111, Voting Theory September 7, / 25

The Manipulability of Voting Systems. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

9.3 Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates

Voting Methods

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/36

Social welfare functions

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

Voting Criteria: Majority Criterion Condorcet Criterion Monotonicity Criterion Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives Criterion

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/31

Voting Criteria April

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued. Voting II 1/27

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

Comparison of Voting Systems

12.2 Defects in Voting Methods

Rationality of Voting and Voting Systems: Lecture II

Voting. Hannu Nurmi. Game Theory and Models of Voting. Public Choice Research Centre and Department of Political Science University of Turku

Homework 7 Answers PS 30 November 2013

1 Voting In praise of democracy?

Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Kenneth Arrow. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Strategically vulnerable

The Mathematics of Voting. The Mathematics of Voting

The Impossibilities of Voting

In deciding upon a winner, there is always one main goal: to reflect the preferences of the people in the most fair way possible.

Math Circle Voting Methods Practice. March 31, 2013

Algorithms, Games, and Networks February 7, Lecture 8

Math for Liberal Studies

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems

Lecture 11. Voting. Outline

Public Choice. Slide 1

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1

The Mathematics of Voting

Mathematical Thinking. Chapter 9 Voting Systems

Exercises For DATA AND DECISIONS. Part I Voting

Math for Liberal Arts MAT 110: Chapter 12 Notes

Chapter 2 Descriptions of the Voting Methods to Be Analyzed

Name Date I. Consider the preference schedule in an election with 5 candidates.

Main idea: Voting systems matter.

Introduction: The Mathematics of Voting

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

Chapter 1 Practice Test Questions

Write all responses on separate paper. Use complete sentences, charts and diagrams, as appropriate.

Minimax Is the Best Electoral System After All

In deciding upon a winner, there is always one main goal: to reflect the preferences of the people in the most fair way possible.

The search for a perfect voting system. MATH 105: Contemporary Mathematics. University of Louisville. October 31, 2017

Desirable properties of social choice procedures. We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures:

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream

Social Choice & Mechanism Design

SOCIAL CHOICES (Voting Methods) THE PROBLEM. Social Choice and Voting. Terminologies

Simple methods for single winner elections

Voting and preference aggregation

Introduction to the Theory of Voting

Voting and preference aggregation

CS 886: Multiagent Systems. Fall 2016 Kate Larson

CSC304 Lecture 14. Begin Computational Social Choice: Voting 1: Introduction, Axioms, Rules. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

Lecture 16: Voting systems

Approaches to Voting Systems

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

that changes needed to be made when electing their Presidential nominee. Iowa, at the time had a

In Elections, Irrelevant Alternatives Provide Relevant Data

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE

Math116Chap1VotingPart2.notebook January 12, Part II. Other Methods of Voting and Other "Fairness Criteria"

Make the Math Club Great Again! The Mathematics of Democratic Voting

VOTING SYSTEMS AND ARROW S THEOREM

The Mathematics of Voting

How Should Members of Parliament (and Presidents) Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study

Josh Engwer (TTU) Voting Methods 15 July / 49

What is the Best Election Method?

How should we count the votes?

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 16 Nov 2018

Fair Division in Theory and Practice

: It is mathematically impossible for a democratic voting method to satisfy all of the fairness criteria was proven in 1949.

Four Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods for Single-Winner Elections

Grade 6 Math Circles Winter February 27/28 The Mathematics of Voting - Solutions

Kybernetika. Robert Bystrický Different approaches to weighted voting systems based on preferential positions

Introduction to Theory of Voting. Chapter 2 of Computational Social Choice by William Zwicker

Random tie-breaking in STV

Intro to Contemporary Math

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

Grade 7/8 Math Circles Winter March 6/7/8 The Mathematics of Voting

Constructing voting paradoxes with logic and symmetry

Statistical Evaluation of Voting Rules

Transcription:

Many Social Choice Rules 1 Introduction So far, I have mentioned several of the most commonly used social choice rules : pairwise majority rule, plurality, plurality with a single run off, the Borda count. Each of these rules has some weaknesses and/or quirks : pairwise majority rule does not always work (i.e. there may not be an alternative which is a Condorcet winner), plurality neglects alternatives which are popular, but not ranked first by many voters, the Borda count creates incentives for strategic voting. Soon (in the third section of the course), I will discuss a general feature of all social choice rules : each of them has at least one weakness. Arrow s Impossibility Theorem (and related results which followed it) shows that we will never be able to find a foolproof social choice rule. Here, I list some of the different social choice rules which have been proposed by various mathematicians, political scientists and cranks most of which are actually used by some organizations. 2 Approval Voting Each voter can vote for as many, or as few alternatives as she wishes. Unlike the Borda count, there is no ranking of alternatives, and no point system. Instead, each voter is asked : of the m alternatives, which are acceptable to you? The voter then lists the alternatives which are acceptable to her. If she wants, she can put just one of the alternatives (presumably her favourite) on the list. In fact, if she wants, she can submit an empty list, indicating she disapproves of all the alternatives. But she could list 2 or 3 or 7 of the alternatives (presumably the 2 or 3 or 7 which are above some threshold level of acceptability). Or all m alternatives, if she wants. Then we add up the number of votes which each alternative received, and we choose the alternative which has the most votes. That is, the alternative which the most voters find acceptable is the one chosen. 3 Baldwin s Social Choice Rule We start with all m alternatives, and we compute the Borda count. 1

But we don t stop there. After this initial calculation, we then eliminate one alternative, the alternative with the lowest Borda count. 1 Then we re do the Borda count, for the remaining m 1 alternatives. Again we find the alternative with the lowest Borda count among these m 1, and we eliminate this alternative. Then we re do the Borda count again, for the m 2 alternatives still remaining on the ballot. We keep doing this m 1 times until there is only one alternative left. This last alternative standing is the alternative chosen, under the Baldwin rule. This rule is quite similar to Nanson s rule below. In fact, Nanson devised his procedure first, and Baldwin proposed his as a modification of Nanson s rule. 4 Black s Social Choice Rule This rule was proposed by Duncan Black, who is (primarily) responsible for the Median Voter Theorem. He proposed choosing the Condorcet winner, if there was a Condorcet winner. If there is no Condorcet winner, Black s rule will pick the alternative with the highest Borda count. 5 Bucklin s Voting Rule Condorcet actually thought of this rule first, but it was discovered independently a century later by James W. Bucklin of Grand Junction, Colorado. Each voter must provide an ordered list of alternatives, from most preferred down to least preferred. In the first stage, the only information used is the most preferred alternative of each voter. So we start out with standard plurality voting, counting the number of first place votes which each alternative gets. If some alternative gets a majority of the votes, then we are done : that alternative is chosen. But if no single alternative gets a majority of the votes, then we go into the second stage. We add in all the second place votes. So the vote total for alternative x in stage 2 is : the number of voters who rank x first plus the number of voters who rank x second. Again, we check whther any single alternative gets a majority of the votes (that is, whether any single alternative is ranked either first or second by a majority of the voters). If the answer is yes, then the alternative with the most votes is chosen. [Note : because each voter gets two votes in this second stage, there might be more than one alternative which gets a majority of votes. We ll 1 If two or more alternatives are tied for last, we choose one of them, at random, to be eliminated, and leave the rest in.

choose the one with the most votes, from among those alternatives which get a majority.] If no alternative gets a majority of votes in stage 2, then we go to stage 3, in which we add everyone s third place votes to their first and second place votes. And we continue in this fashion, until we get to a stage in which at least one alternative gets a majority of the votes. Then the process ends, and the alternative with the most (1st plus 2nd plus 3rd plus...) votes is chosen. 6 Carey s Voting Rule This procedure involves a sequence of plurality rule votes. So we start, in stage 1, with plain plurality rule : each voter votes for her most preferred alternative. Then we eliminate all candidates who received lower than average vote totals. So if there were 300 voters, and 4 alternatives, in the first stage we would eliminate all alternatives with fewer than 75 votes. Then we run the plurality vote again. Except now, some of the alternatives have been eliminated from the ballot, so the people who voted initially for those alternatives will have to switch their votes, to the alternative still on the ballot which they like best. After this second stage, we again eliminate all candidates with fewer than average vote totals. (So, with 300 voters, if only one of the 4 alternatives had been eliminated in the first ballot, then in the second stage we will eliminate all alternatives which get fewer than 300/3 = 100 votes.) We keep eliminating alternatives in this manner, until one alternative gets a majority of the votes. That alternative is the one chosen. 7 Coombs s Voting Rule This rule was proposed by Clyde Coombs in 1964, and seems to have been borrowed (without attribution) by many (extremely tedious) reality shows. Under Coombs s procedure, each voter ranks all the alternatives, from best to worst. Then the alternative which has the highest number of last place votes is eliminated. The procedure is then repeated, with the alternative ranked last among the remaining m 1 alternatives in this second stage being eliminated. The process continues, with the alternative ranked last by the most voters being eliminated in each stage, until one alternative winds up getting a majority of the first place votes. That alternative is then chosen. 8 Copeland s Voting Rule This rule is based on pairwise majority rule.

We calculate an alternative s score by looking at its record in pairwise contests against every other alternative. For example, suppose that there are 11 alternatives. To calculate the score for alternative x, we look at how it does against each of the other 10 alternatives, in a pairwise election. So if a majority of voters prefer alternative x to alternative y, we say that x wins the contest against alternative y. Alternative x gets 1 point for each win, and 1 points for each loss (with 0 points for a tie). So if alternative x won pairwise elections against 6 of the 10 other alternatives, and lost to the other 4, then its score would be 6 4 = 2. We rank the alternatives by the scores computed in this way, and choose the alternative with the highest score. 9 Dodgson s Voting Rule This rule was devised by the British mathematician Charles L. Dodgson, who also wrote Alice in Wonderland. It s an attempt to find the closest thing to a Condorcet winner, in cases where there is no Condorcet winner. So (as in Copeland s rule above), we look at all the pairwise comparisons. We then calculate how close each alternative is to being a Condorcet winner. For example, if alternative w defeats 8 of the other 10 alternatives in pairwise votes, but loses to y by 3 votes and loses to z by 2 votes, then w is 5 votes away from being a Condorcet winner : if 3 voters had changed their ranking of w versus y, and 2 voters had changed their ranking of w versus z, then w would have been a Condorcet winner. So the alternative chosen is the alternative which is closest to being a Condorcet winner, the alternative for which the fewest of these vote changes would be needed. To calculate this number of changes, find each pairwise election which the alternative loses, and then add up the margin of defeat over all those losing elections. Dodgson s rule chooses the alternative with the smallest number of vote changes needed. If there is a Condorcet winner, then it will require 0 changes of votes, and so will be chosen under Dodgson s rule. 10 Hare s Voting Rule [a.k.a. Single Transferrable Vote ] This rule was devised by a nineteenth century English barrister, Thomas Hare. It is similar in style to Coombs s rule above (although it predates Coombs s rule by more than a century). In fact, Hare s rule is plurality with a lot of runoffs, exactly the rule used in many political conventions 2. 2 Such as the 2012 NDP convention, mentioned in the lecture on plurality.

We start with plurality voting, each voter voting for a single alternative. Then we eliminate the alternative with the fewest first place votes, and run another round of plurality voting with only m 1 alternatives on the ballot. Then we eliminate the alternative with the fewest (first place) votes in that election, and run another round with the remaining m 2 alternatives. The process continues until an alternative gets a majority of the votes, and that alternative is then chosen. 11 Nanson s Voting Rule This rule is similar to (and precedes) Baldwin s rule described above. Like Baldwin s rule, Nanson s rule involves a sequence of Borda counts. So we start by computing the Borda count with all m alternatives on the ballot. Then we eliminate all the alternatives which got less than the average score on that ballot. (So if there were 4 alternatives, and 5 voters, the average score under the Borda count would be 12.5, and we would eliminate all alternatives with a Borda count lower than 12.5.) Then we compute the Borda count again, for the reduced ballot with the remaining alternatives on it which have not yet been eliminated. Again, we find all the alternatives with below average scores on this ballot, and eliminate them. We keep repeating this process until only one alternative remains, and that alternative is our choice. 12 Raynaud s Voting Rule Like Copeland s and Dodgson s rules, Raynaud s rule is based on the pairwise votes between alternatives. First, we look at all the pairwise votes. So if there were 10 alternatives, there would be 45 different pairs of alternatives. We look at the margin of victory and defeat in each of these pairwise elections. Then we eliminate the alternative which lost by the biggest margin. We throw that alternative out, and begin again, with only m 1 alternatives. We look at all the pairs (36 of them, if m = 10), find the biggest margin, and eliminate the loser (that is, the alternative which had the biggest margin of defeat in a pairwise contest). That leaves us with m 2 alternatives. And we continue this process until we are left with one alternative standing (that is, the winner of the pairwise election between the last two alternatives left standing). And that s our choice.

13 Schulze s Voting Rule This rule is somewhat complicated. But it is used to choose executives for several organizations 3 This rule is based on pairwise comparisons. But what distinguishes it from some of the other pairwise comparison based rules (such as Copeland s or Dodgson s) is that it allows for indirect comparisons. So suppose that a majority of voters prefer x to y, and that a majority of voters prefer y to z. Then x can defeat z by a sequence of two votes. If we have a sequence of this nature, let me described it as x beats z indirectly. That is, x defeats z indirectly if I can find a sequence of pairwise votes, in which x defeats a 1, a 1 defeats a 2, a 2 defeats a 3, and so on, up to a k defeats z. In the previous paragraph, k = 1 and a 1 = y. If I can find such a path, so that x defeats z indirectly, then the margin of victory is defined as the smallest of the margins of victory of the k pairwise elections, in the path from z to a k to a k 1 to a 1 to x. That is, if x defeats y by a vote of 54 to 45, and y defeats z by a vote of 53 to 46, then the margin of victory for this path is 7 : the smaller of the margins in the two votes on the path. Now the problem with this indirect beating is that we can have x defeating z indirectly, but also z defeating x indirectly. That s what the Condorcet paradox showed. So the way we re going to rank alternatives when this cycling occurs is to look at the margin of victory. We define p(x, z ) as the largest margin of victory from all the indirect victories x has over z. If z cannot defeat x indirectly that is if there is no path of pairwise votes which gets us from x to z then define p(z, x ) as equalling 0. Finally, we use this margin of victory to rank our alternatives. We ll rank x above z if and only if p(x, z ) > p(z, x ). And our choice will be any alternative x which is ranked above all other alternatives. There are two very nice features about this measure p(x, z ). First, it s transitive. If p(x, y ) > p(y, x ) and p(y, z ) > p(z, y ) then it must be true that p(x, z ) > p(z, x ). Second, there must always be a Schulze winner : there must be some alternative x such that p(x, a) p(a, x ) for every other alternative a. So this second property ensures that we can use this measure of margin of victory to choose a best alternative. And the first property ensures that we can also use this measure of margin of victory to generate a social ordering. 14 Simpson s Voting Rule Simpson s rule predates Schulze s. It s simpler, but also seems to have more potential weaknesses. 3 Wikimedia, and Debian Gnu/Linux software, for example.

Simpson s rule is based on pairwise votes. For alternative x, we take all the pairwise contests against the other m 1 alternatives, and we find the biggest defeat x suffers. So if x defeats 8 of the other 10 candidates in a pairwise vote, but loses to w by 3 votes, and loses to z by 2 votes, then the biggest defeat margin for x is 3. We then rank the alternatives in reverse order of this largest margin of defeat. We choose the alternative for which the largest margin of defeat is smallest. 15 Small s Voting Rule Small s rule is a refinement of Copeland s. Copeland s rule looked simply at the number of alternatives that x defeated. It ranks the candidates in order of the number of pairwise contests they win. The problem is, that very often we ll have ties. Small s rule helps break some of those ties. It starts with Copeland s rule. We look at all pairwise votes, and give a score of +1 to the winner, 1 to the loser and 0 if it s a tie. Then we add up each alternative s score over all the pairwise votes it has, and rank the alternatives by these total scores. Then, if more than one alternative is tied for best overall, we do another round. We eliminate all the alternatives that are not tied for best, anbd re calculate the score, using only the pairwise votes among the alternatives remaining. If this second stage results in a tie, then we eliminate all alternatives which are not tied for the top, and recalculate again. And we keep doing this until there is only one alternative left (that will be our social choice), or until there are several alternatives left, and they re all tied with each other (those will be our choices). 16 Tideman s Voting Rule Tideman s rule is another rule based on pairwise votes. We look at all of the pairwise votes (45 of them if there were 10 alternatives), and we try to use the margin of victory as a basis for generating a ranking. So we look at all the pairwise votes, and we find the one with the biggest margin. We lock that vote. That is, if the biggest margin is in the vote of x versus y, and it s won by x, we ll lock x in above y. Then we look for the next largest margin. Say it s the victory of y over z. So next we lock that vote in, ranking y above z. Now suppose the third largest victory is z over x. We d like to rank z above x, but that would generate a problem with transitivity, since we already have locked in x above y, and y above z. So we ignore this third result. That is, whenever a result contradicts the rankings that we have already locked, then we ignore that result. We move on to the 4th biggest margin, say w over z,

and if that doesn t contradict any rankings we ve already generated, we ll lock that in, ranking w above z. So we keep going down the list of margins of victory, using them to rank pairs of alternatives unless this would generate a cycle when combined with the rankings we already have. And we keep doing this until we have generated a complete top to bottom ranking. That s our social ordering, and our choice will be the top alternative in this ordering.