Feminism and the Idea of Law

Similar documents
CRITIQUING POSTMODERN PHILOSOPHIES IN CONTEMPORARY FEMINIST JURISPRUDENCE

Clive Barnett, University of Exeter: Remarks on Does democracy need the city? Conversations on Power and Space in the City Workshop No.

BOOK REVIEW: WHY LA W MA TTERS BY ALON HAREL

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

WHY NOT BASE FREE SPEECH ON AUTONOMY OR DEMOCRACY?

Keynote: Reforming Law The Role of Theory

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

Chantal Mouffe: "We urgently need to promote a left-populism"

What Is Contemporary Critique Of Biopolitics?

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

RESEARCH METHODOLOGY IN POLITICAL SCIENCE STUDY NOTES CHAPTER ONE

Theories of Conflict and Conflict Resolution

Bruno Latour, Law and International Justice: An Interview with Dr Kirsten Campbell

[ features: PUBLIC CRIMINOLOGY ] Critical Reflections on Public Criminology : An Introduction

Book Review: Women and the Canadian Welfare State: Challenges and Change, By Patricia M. Evans and Gerda R. Wekerle (eds)

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions

Deep Democracy: Community, Diversity, Transformation. In recent years, scholars of American philosophy have done considerable

Programme Specification

Margaret Thornton, dissonance and distrust: women in the legal profession

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights

Marcelo Lopes de Souza, Richard J. White and Simon Springer (eds)

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D

Ina Schmidt: Book Review: Alina Polyakova The Dark Side of European Integration.

Maureen Molloy and Wendy Larner

The Democracy Project by David Graeber

Cultural Diversity and Social Media III: Theories of Multiculturalism Eugenia Siapera

WIKIPEDIA IS NOT A GOOD ENOUGH SOURCE FOR AN ACADEMIC ASSIGNMENT

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

BOOK PROFILE: RELIGION, POLITICS,

Introduction. Animus, and Why It Matters. Which of these situations is not like the others?

Themes and Scope of this Book

Panelli R. (2004): Social Geographies. From Difference to Action. SAGE, London, 287 pp.

The Politics of reconciliation in multicultural societies 1, Will Kymlicka and Bashir Bashir

UNDERSTANDING AND WORKING WITH POWER. Effective Advising in Statebuilding and Peacebuilding Contexts How 2015, Geneva- Interpeace

Sociological Marxism Volume I: Analytical Foundations. Table of Contents & Outline of topics/arguments/themes

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

CHANTAL MOUFFE GLOSSARY

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Rechtsgeschichte. WOZU Rechtsgeschichte? Rg Dag Michalsen. Rechts Rg geschichte

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Critical Social Theory in Public Administration

POLI 359 Public Policy Making

Course Descriptions 1201 Politics: Contemporary Issues 1210 Political Ideas: Isms and Beliefs 1220 Political Analysis 1230 Law and Politics

1100 Ethics July 2016

Book Review James Q. Whitman, Harsh Justice: Criminal Punishment and the Widening Divide between America and Europe (2005)

Understanding Social Equity 1 (Caste, Class and Gender Axis) Lakshmi Lingam

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

LEGAL THEORY/ JURISPRUDENCE SUMMARY

Introduction[1] The obstacle

Canadian Journal of Women and the Law, Volume 24, Number 2, 2012, pp (Review)

SOCIOLOGICAL JURISPRUDENCE: JURISTIC THOUGHT AND SOCIAL INQUIRY by ROGER COTTERRELL (Abingdon: Routledge, 2018, 256 pp., 29.99)

Rawls, Islam, and political constructivism: Some questions for Tampio

1 What does it matter what human rights mean?

Party Autonomy A New Paradigm without a Foundation? Ralf Michaels, Duke University School of Law

2. Tovey and Share argue: In effect, all sociologies are national sociologies Do you agree?

political domains. Fae Myenne Ng s Bone presents a realistic account of immigrant history from the end of the nineteenth century. The realistic narrat

COMMENTS ON AZIZ RANA, THE TWO FACES OF AMERICAN FREEDOM

Graduate School of Political Economy Dongseo University Master Degree Course List and Course Descriptions

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Programme Specification

SUBALTERN STUDIES: AN APPROACH TO INDIAN HISTORY

Grassroots Policy Project

Summary of Papers. xxvii

Mark Scheme (Results) Summer Pearson Edexcel GCE in Government and Politics (6GP04/4B) Paper 4B: Other Ideological Traditions

Review of Teubner, Constitutional Fragments (OUP 2012)

Hegemony and Education. Gramsci, Post-Marxism and Radical Democracy Revisited (Review)

Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ix pp. $19.95 (cloth).

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED

What is 'transversal politics'?

1 Many relevant texts have been published in the open access journal of the European Institute for

Re-constructing the West: Beyond the Prophecies of Globalization. Matteo Stocchetti. The West: Concept, Narrative and Politics

Dinerstein makes two major contributions to which I will draw attention and around which I will continue this review: (1) systematising autonomy and

Human rights concern much more than only racial differences and discrimination

IS LAW DETERMINED BY MORALITY? Dworkin and Inclusive Legal Positivism

Action Theory. Collective Conscience. Critical Theory. Determinism. Description

Chapter 1 Sociological Theory Chapter Summary

Post-Print. Response to Willmott. Alistair Mutch, Nottingham Trent University

From the "Eagle of Revolutionary to the "Eagle of Thinker, A Rethinking of the Relationship between Rosa Luxemburg's Ideas and Marx's Theory

REGIONAL POLICY MAKING AND SME

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Book Review: Social Protection After the Crisis: Regulation Without Enforcement. Steve Tombs

The Challenge of Multiculturalism: Beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism

Online publication date: 21 July 2010 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

University of Florida Spring 2017 CONTEMPORARY SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY SYA 6126, Section 1F83

The public vs. private value of health, and their relationship. (Review of Daniel Hausman s Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering)

Cultural Diversity and Justice. The Cultural Defense and Child Marriages in Romania

Museums, Equality and Social Justice Routledge by Richard Sandell and Eithne

Book Review. Pratiksha Baxi*

A Necessary Discussion About International Law

Peacebuilding and reconciliation in Libya: What role for Italy?

The Morality of Conflict

Early Childhood Institutions as Loci of Ethical and Political Practice

NEWSLETTER Volume 14 Number 3 SPECIAL EDITION

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

Globalization and food sovereignty: Global and local change in the new politics of food

Transcription:

Margaret Davies * A Challenge Reimagining Law In recent years feminist legal scholars in Canada and the United Kingdom have set themselves an intriguing task to expose the politics embedded in major appeal court decisions by rewriting certain judgments from a feminist point of view. The Women s Court of Canada, devised over dinner at an Italian restaurant in Toronto in 2004 (Majury 2006: 1) was born of frustration at the narrowing focus of the Canadian Supreme Court in its equality jurisprudence. With the assistance of organisations such as the Women s Legal Education and Action Fund and under the influence of the Canadian Charter for Rights and Freedoms, the Supreme Court had once been willing to innovate, but feminists had noticed it becoming increasingly less progressive. The Women s Court, established as a loose coalition of feminist lawyers, scholars and activists, was established with the intention of illustrating that any judicial opinion is always just one possibility among many. Alternative opinions and decisions can always be made which are based on more imaginative approaches to the equality (and other) jurisprudence. The UK-based Feminist Judgments Project (Hunter, McGlynn and Rackley 2010a) took some inspiration from this approach, but applied the feminist judgment concept to a broader range of cases, including medical, property, criminal, family, and public law matters. The Women s Court, the Judgments Project, and other similar activist interventions 1 consciously perform a paradox: they are established to refuse and resist a dominant jurisprudence, yet of necessity they deploy the techniques and substance of that jurisprudence in their processes. This very personal as well as institutional conflict is nicely captured by Diana Majury in her introduction to the first series of judgments of the Women s Court: A successor Women s Court might try to envision a very different legal system from the existing one and explore what judicial decisions might look like in that context. We are a bit aghast at ourselves as a Women s Court issuing thirty-five page decisions written in technical legal language. Future Women s Court judges may opt to be bolder and more visionary (2006: 6). There are two open challenges contained in this statement first to try to envision a very different legal system and second to explore what judicial decisions might look like in that context. For a * Professor of Law, Flinders University, Adelaide, Australia. margaret.davies@flinders.edu.au. 1 Such as the Women s International War Crimes Tribunal. See Chinkin (2001). 1

Margaret Davies legal theorist they are calls towards a positive renewal, reconstruction, or even revolutionary understanding of law. At the same time, there are some critical doubts about certain aspects of such a challenge is it really possible to envision a different legal system when we are so embedded in our own legal paradigm? More to the point, perhaps Majury is unnecessarily self-deprecating about the work of the Court: doesn t a Women s Court or a Feminist Judgment already perform a large part of that particular task (insofar as it is possible) in the sense that it imagines a legal system peopled by reflective judges sensitive to questions of gender and aware of the implications of their interventions? It is difficult if not impossible to envision a completely different legal system. But it is always possible to envision incremental changes to the existing legal system which go beyond simple reform to touch upon the underlying ethos or culture of the legal system. Such incremental changes might, for instance, consist of an increased level of reflexivity among decision-makers regarding gender (as indeed modelled by the Women s Court of Canada and the Feminist Judgments Project) or an increased emphasis upon alternative modes of dispute settlement. The editors of Feminist Judgments: From Theory to Practice make the point (to my mind) persuasively: The Feminist Judgments Project represents a form of academic activism, an attempt to tackle power and authority not from the distance of critique but on their own ground. By appropriating judgment-writing for feminist purposes the judgment writers engage in a form of parodic and hence subversive performance. In much the same way as Judith Butler describes drag as a performance that subverts gender norms, these feminist academics dressed up as judges powerfully denaturalise existing judicial and doctrinal norms, exposing them as contingent, and as themselves (the product of) performances (Hunter, McGlynn and Rackley 2010b: 8). But this is only one part of the feminist judgments story. It is not only a parodic exposure and critique of normal judicial decision-making. It has an equally powerful constructive dimension because it also (like drag) has the potential to alter our perception of the normal. Feminist and other critical judgments help to bring narratives of diversity and otherness into the legal consciousness, thereby disrupting the comfortable hegemony of legal doctrinal tradition and to some degree normalising the alternative perspective (see Hunter 2010). Of course, the very notion of a judgment is about determination and fixity inevitably a judge makes a decision which enforces a particular norm and excludes alternative possibilities (Cover 1983; Davies 1996) meaning that any underlying diversity and contestation is at one moment overtaken by the very practical and immediate need for determinacy and coherence. 2

Whatever our scepticism about envisioning a different legal system therefore, from a theoretical point of view, it is certainly possible to envision the same legal system differently. Such a project is in many ways implied in these activist feminist projects to re-imagine legal doctrine and decision making. The emphasis of such projects is upon a practical rather than a theoretical purpose, to envision essentially the same law coming up with different answers, sometimes using slightly altered methods, in specific doctrinal contexts. But what if we try to imagine the legal system itself from a different perspective? What if we look at the same legal system but with different conventions of looking? What, for instance, if we change the scale of legal theory away from the nation state to the micro-interactions of legal actors, and its perspective away from the expert insider typically the judge to anyone who engages with law (that is, anyone at all)? In the remainder of this paper, I want to respond further to the feminist challenge by identifying a key epistemological point of departure for contemporary understandings of law, and then ask what law looks like when we subvert or reorient that framework. Law and the Subject The perspective I wish to reconsider is that of the positivist separation of law. Traditionally, this separation was cast as a separation (or separability) of law from some vague notion of morality (Hart 1958; Naffine 2010). A more contemporary iteration of positivist separation concerns the separation or autonomy of law from a general non-legal sphere politics, social norms, religion, and other normative pluralities. The emphasis of positivist separation is on the limits of law, in other words the idea that law is defined by certain limiting features differentiating what is law from what is not law. One such limit or division which has received patchy theoretical attention is the separation of law from the subject. The positivist presumption is that law and all of these other normative pluralities exist in a sphere separate from individual human beings. Law is seen as a system or set of institutions which is simply imposed upon us as an external code affecting our actions, perhaps our status, but not our inner identity. Feminists and critical theorists have of course challenged this separation, but the emphasis has often been on how the law (as institution, system, abstract set of doctrines, or concrete disciplinary procedures) subjects, constrains, or constructs. Identity and subjectivity become an effect of law, and to a certain degree this is clearly right. We are made as subjects by a multiplicity of normative legal, cultural, psycho-social, and political contexts. Although such approaches correctly diagnose the reliance of subjectivity on environments which normalise and constrain, they often maintain the image of law as a superstructural, essentially abstract but nonetheless existing, phenomenon. Law effects individuals, but the reliance of law on the mundane, everyday microprocesses of human action and interaction is more rarely perceived or theorised, except where such actions are channelled through the proper avenues for change already laid down by legal procedure winning a case with a novel argument, promoting a law reform, and so forth. 3

Margaret Davies There are a number of problems, well known to feminist legal scholars, with regarding law as an autonomous and abstract set of institutions. The view of law as separate from human life is both theoretically inadequate as an understanding of law, as well as limiting as a framework for achieving feminist transformation. It is a theoretically inadequate account of law because it reifies law and removes it from the actual and the practical contexts in which law is experienced and lived it represents law as having a particular identity and shape at the systemic and institutional level, but masks the empirical substance of law, obscuring in consequence law s own participation in distributions of power. The separatist account of law also arguably limits our appreciation of the potential avenues for legal transformation. By emphasising methods of legal change which are prescribed by law itself (notably legislative reform or intervention in litigation), positivist/separatist accounts fail to recognise the openness of law to resistance and renewal from other less formal channels. In arguing that the positivist conception of law is theoretically inadequate and politically limited, I am not claiming that it is useless or even that it is false in some simplistic way. Rather, I am claiming that despite the fact that it is useful in some contexts and carries its own fictive and self-defining truth, it is nonetheless important to look at law from other perspectives and in other dimensions. The point is not that we ought to abandon positivist ideas about law (or for that matter the critique of positivism), but rather that it is also possible to regard law as a different set of interactions altogether. Part of my motivation is to respond to what has so often been seen as the fatal gap of all forms of legal critique that they fail to provide positive reconstructions of the concept of law. Feminist judgments reconstruct law in the practical dimension, but it is also important to think about our general image, concept or understanding of law. The Norm-Subject 2 Instead of starting with law as an object of expert knowledge which is separate from human subjectivity, legal theory also needs to consider the primacy of the subject in the construction of law. When we go out into the legal world, act and interact with others, perform, practice, mimic, contest and create the law, we live in a completely disjointed legal world. It has a horizontality where meaning is being made and understood in the immediate context, but there is no totality of meaning attached to law. My experience of law is simply one of fragments of interactions, held together in the first instance by the fact that they all involve me. Numerous legal and other messages pass through me (as one instantiation of Lyotard s famous nodal point : 1984: 15) but these messages do not collectively amount to a general or systematic understanding of law. They coalesce in various ways across diverse sections of the population without necessarily being fixed in any particular form. Of course, many of the messages I receive about law are in fact informed or underpinned by some 2 More extensive analysis of the ideas in this section can be found in Davies (2007, 2008). 4

total or general view of law, which everyone, especially those with a legal education, has probably internalised to some degree: this is unavoidable since the very idea of law is normally now based around the ideal or concept of a totality or system. But it is important to remember that that ideal is simply a fiction an influential one, but nonetheless a fiction or assumption held in place by large numbers of people acting as if it is true. Starting then from the bottom up, experiential position of the ordinary (non-expert) subject what changes about our understanding of law and why is this of any significance to feminist legal theory? First and most obviously, regarding law from the non-reified perspective of ordinary subjects exposes the mythical nature of the separation thesis. Law as an abstract and fictional object might be separate from religious, moral, or social norms similarly abstracted from selves, but there is little sense in saying that law is experientially or existentially separate in any sense. On the contrary, law is a facet of a complex social existence, and is intertwined with many other dimensions of everyday life. Law infuses social life and takes back from it the conventions, cultural values, interpretive imperatives and other practice-based norms which comprise our everyday existences. Secondly, in looking at law from the perspective of the legal subject, we disrupt the conceptuality of law, and expose gaps in it. To speak of a concept of law, or even of several concepts, erases the non-conceptual empirical facticity of law experienced in its everyday manifestations. As Adorno stated, the concept does not exhaust the thing conceived (Adorno 1973: 5; cf Cook 2005). Legal theory has tended to fetishise the concept of law, presuming that individual events, people, interactions and so forth can and must be understood within the identity/unity created by the concept. The philosophical (and legal) obsession with fitting objects into a finite conceptual structure obscures the material and experiential nature of law. While practical legal thought may have some justification for such an approach, there is no excuse for legal philosophy to be so constrained: Philosophical objects can only be grasped where philosophy does not impose them (ibid: 13, cf 149). Looking at law from the perspective of the subject helps to undo this theoretical imperialism and promotes a somatic, dynamic, and somewhat particularistic understanding of law. Thirdly then (and getting to the point of why this is of interest to feminists), the fragmented perceptions, experiences, practices and interactions of legal subjects bring diversity, materiality and alternative logics into the interior of our image of law. This image of legal diversity is eschewed both by conventional legal images of coherence and predictability as well as by some feminist and critical discourses which emphasise hegemonic inclusion (masculinity, heterosexuality, whiteness) and exclusion (female, LGBTI, and non-white identities). I am not arguing that claims of exclusion in specific contexts are wrong because clearly they are nearly always well-grounded. Generalising this pattern of exclusions to the point where we say that law is masculine, white and 5

Margaret Davies heteronormative claims I have often made myself is more complicated theoretically, but also often justifiable as long as we are not claiming that these are necessary characteristics of law. Outsider perspectives are in this way often regarded as alternative narratives about law, narratives beyond law and critical of it. However, looking at law from the perspective of subjects and expanding it to incorporate all types of legally-affected practices may bring diversity and the experience of exclusion into the interior of a social understanding of law comprised of contradiction and contestation. And finally, reorienting our perspective of law towards its actual material existence in everyday contexts allows us to perceive the essentially performative nature of law and the prefigurative potential of feminist legal politics. From the conventional point of view, law is an institutionalised set of practices which can be described and understood as a basically static theoretical object with its own reasonably definable limits and identity. As I have indicated, this is a comfortable and useful understanding of law, one which lawyers need to rely upon unquestioningly. On the other hand, (and extending Kelsen somewhat) it is possible to see this image as a fiction made plausible by everyday performances of law in an endlessly diverse range of situations and with an endlessly diverse range of possibilities for change. Feminist legal politics can and does draw upon these possibilities by prefiguring different narratives about law, and it is important to see these not as extra-legal experiments but as integral to the dynamic reconstruction of law in its culture, practices, institutions, and identity. Conclusion It is difficult to see law as radically diverse when it so often seems to speak with a single voice and from a very limited range of perspectives. Activist events such as the Women s Court and Feminist Judgments Project help to bring alternative narratives into our view of legal doctrine and thereby expose the potentialities of law to express difference. They remind us that law is a process made of decisions, actions, choices, relationships and values, and not simply a set of abstract or hypostatised doctrines. In my opinion, it is possible to broaden such insights to the idea of law, eschewing images of totality in favour of an altogether more grounded, material, and open-ended understanding of law. References Adorno, Theodor. 1973. Negative Dialectics. New York: Continuum. 6

Chinkin, Christine. 2001. Women s International Tribunal on Japanese Military Sexual Slavery. American Journal of International Law 95: 335-340. Cook, Deborah. 2005. From the Actual to the Possible: Nonidentity Thinking. Constellations 12: 21-35. Cover, Robert. 1983. Nomos and Narrative. Harvard Law Review 97: 4-68 Davies, Margaret. 1996. Delimiting the Law. London: Pluto Press. Davies, Margaret. 2007. Beyond Unity. In Sexuality and the Law: Feminist Engagements, ed Vanessa Munro and Carl Stychin, 151-170. Abingdon: Routledge-Cavendish. Davies, Margaret. 2008. Feminism and the Flat Law Theory. Feminist Legal Studies 16: 281-304. Hart, HLA. 1958. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard Law Review 71: 593-629. Hunter, Rosemary. 2010. An Account of Feminist Judging. In Feminist Judgments: From Theory to Practice, ed Rosemary Hunter, Clare McGlynn and Erika Rackley, 30-43. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Hunter, Rosemary, Clare McGlynn and Erika Rackley (eds). 2010a. Feminist Judgments: From Theory to Practice. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Hunter, Rosemary, Clare McGlynn and Erika Rackley. 2010b. Feminist Judgments: An Introduction. In Feminist Judgments: From Theory to Practice, ed Rosemary Hunter, Clare McGlynn and Erika Rackley, 3-29. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Lyotard, Jean-Francois. 1984. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Majury, Diana. 2006. Introducing the Women s Court of Canada. Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 18: 1-25. Naffine, Ngaire. 2010. The Common Discourse of Hart and Fuller. In The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century, ed Peter Cane, 217-225. Oxford: Hart Publishing. 7