Analysis of AV Voting System Rick Bradford, 24/4/11

Similar documents
(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

The search for a perfect voting system. MATH 105: Contemporary Mathematics. University of Louisville. October 31, 2017

As you may have heard, there has been some discussion about possibly changing Canada's electoral system. We want to ask people their views on this.

Electoral Reform Questionnaire Field Dates: October 12-18, 2016

Mathematics of Voting Systems. Tanya Leise Mathematics & Statistics Amherst College

Compare the vote Level 3

Compare the vote Level 1

Social choice theory

The Manipulability of Voting Systems. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

Executive Summary The AV Referendum in context The Voter Power Index 6. Conclusion 11. Appendix 1. Summary of electoral systems 12

Should Catholics support AV?

The Alternative Vote Referendum: why I will vote YES. Mohammed Amin

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007

CSC304 Lecture 14. Begin Computational Social Choice: Voting 1: Introduction, Axioms, Rules. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8

Complexity of Manipulating Elections with Few Candidates

REFORMING THE ELECTORAL SYSTEM IN ALBERTA: THE CASE FOR DUAL- MEMBER MIXED PROPORTIONAL Sean Graham

Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders

Comparison of Voting Systems

Electoral Reform Brief

What is the Best Election Method?

Voting System: elections

How Should Members of Parliament (and Presidents) Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study

c M. J. Wooldridge, used by permission/updated by Simon Parsons, Spring

Is Democracy Possible?

Local elections. Referendum on the voting system used to elect MPs to the House of Commons

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Easy Read Creating a Parliament for Wales

GOVERNMENT & POLITICS UNIT 1 GLOSSARY

Introduction to the Theory of Voting

F2PTP A VOTING SYSTEM FOR EQUALITY OF REPRESENTATION IN A MULTI-PARTY STATE FIRST TWO PAST THE POST. 1 Tuesday, 05 May 2015 David Allen

What is fairness? - Justice Anthony Kennedy, Vieth v Jubelirer (2004)

Theorising the Democratic State. Elizabeth Frazer: Lecture 4. Who Rules? I

Electoral Reform: Making Every Vote Count Equally

Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures*

Reading the local runes:

Incumbency Effects and the Strength of Party Preferences: Evidence from Multiparty Elections in the United Kingdom

Brexit Referendum: An Incomplete Verdict

THE SOUTH AUSTRALIAN LEGISLATIVE COUNCIL: POSSIBLE CHANGES TO ITS ELECTORAL SYSTEM

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

Simulating Electoral College Results using Ranked Choice Voting if a Strong Third Party Candidate were in the Election Race

Scottish Parliamentary election

HOW DUAL MEMBER PROPORTIONAL COULD WORK IN BRITISH COLUMBIA Sean Graham February 1, 2018

GCE AS 2 Student Guidance Government & Politics. Course Companion Unit AS 2: The British Political System. For first teaching from September 2008

Towards an Information-Neutral Voting Scheme That Does Not Leave Too Much To Chance

The impact of different voting systems on the type of government, party representation and voter choice

GOVERNMENT AND POLITICS Unit 1 Electoral Systems and Voting Behaviour

Trudeau approval soars

Voting Criteria April

Electoral Reform Proposal

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing

ONTARIO SUPERIOR COURT OF JUSTICE. JOAN RUSSOW and THE GREEN PARTY OF CANADA. - and -

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE

Main idea: Voting systems matter.

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1

4.1 THE DUTCH CONSTITUTION. The part of the government that makes sure laws are carried out 1 mark.

Public Choice. Slide 1

arxiv: v1 [physics.soc-ph] 13 Mar 2018

The probability of the referendum paradox under maximal culture

4 However, devolution would have better served the people of Wales if a better voting system had been used. At present:

Algorithms, Games, and Networks February 7, Lecture 8

Safe Votes, Sincere Votes, and Strategizing

Electoral Reform: Key Federal Policy Recommendations. Researched and written by CFUW National Office & CFUW Leaside East York and Etobicoke JULY 2016

Electoral systems for the Scottish Parliament and National Assembly for Wales

THRESHOLDS. Underlying principles. What submitters on the party vote threshold said

COULD THE LIB DEM MARGINAL MELTDOWN MEAN THE TORIES GAIN FROM A.V.? By Lord Ashcroft, KCMG 20 July 2010

Proportion? Trade unions and electoral reform

Font Size: A A. Eric Maskin and Amartya Sen JANUARY 19, 2017 ISSUE. 1 of 7 2/21/ :01 AM

Partisan Gerrymandering

The Case for Electoral Reform: A Mixed Member Proportional System for Canada. Brief by Stephen Phillips, Ph.D.

Political Statistics, Devolution and Electoral Systems

Democratic Rules in Context

PCs Lead in Ontario FOR IMMEDIATE RELEASE. MEDIA INQUIRIES: Lorne Bozinoff, President

Many Social Choice Rules

Getting it in. Proportion? Trade unions and electoral reform

The Electoral College

Electoral Reform National Dialogue INFORMATION BOOKLET

Strategy in Law and Business Problem Set 1 February 14, Find the Nash equilibria for the following Games:

An Integer Linear Programming Approach for Coalitional Weighted Manipulation under Scoring Rules

The League of Women Voters of Pennsylvania et al v. The Commonwealth of Pennsylvania et al. Nolan McCarty

Voting Methods for Municipal Elections: Propaganda, Field Experiments and what USA voters want from an Election Algorithm

Supplementary Materials for Strategic Abstention in Proportional Representation Systems (Evidence from Multiple Countries)

Party Lists and Preference Voting

ELECTING CANDIDATES WITH FAIR REPRESENTATION VOTING: RANKED CHOICE VOTING AND OTHER METHODS

Social Choice: The Impossible Dream. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

Voting with Bidirectional Elimination

If a party s share of the overall party vote entitles it to five seats, but it wins six electorates, the sixth seat is called an overhang seat.

How do parties contribute to democratic politics?

Math of Election APPORTIONMENT

Mechanism design: how to implement social goals

Approaches to Analysing Politics Variables & graphs

CAN FAIR VOTING SYSTEMS REALLY MAKE A DIFFERENCE?

THE ALTERNATIVE VOTE AND COOMBS RULE VERSUS FIRST-PAST-THE-POST: A SOCIAL CHOICE ANALYSIS OF SIMULATED DATA BASED ON ENGLISH ELECTIONS,

Paper C: Influencing and Changing Decisions in Society and Government

Interdisciplinary Teaching Grant Proposal. Applicants:

CS 886: Multiagent Systems. Fall 2016 Kate Larson

State redistricting, representation,

Mathematics of the Electoral College. Robbie Robinson Professor of Mathematics The George Washington University


Transcription:

Analysis of AV Voting System Rick Bradford, 24/4/11 In the 2010 UK General Election, the percentage of votes for the three principal parties were in the proportion 41% (Con), 33% (Lab), 26% (Lib), ignoring the smaller parties and rescaling to 100%. These figures contrast sharply with the proportion of seats won: 49% (Con), 42% (Lab), 9% (Lib). The proportion of seats won by the third party (Liberals) is far smaller than their proportion of the votes. Simulations have been carried out based on the simplification that only the three major parties are involved, and based on random voting. It was assumed for simplicity that all voters placed all three candidates (though this is not a requirement of the proposed UK system). Three things are presented, [1] Results assuming all three parties attract one-third of the total vote; [2] Results assuming a weaker third party (representative of the UK); [3] Some known rigorous voting theorems. 1. All Parties Have One-Third of the Total Vote Remarkably the AV and first-past-the-post (FPTP) system were found to produce a different winning candidate in 23% of cases. If this were characteristic of the UK (it isn t) it would suggest that the adoption of AV would have a dramatic effect on the resulting government. 2. Unequal Split of Votes Representative of the UK Figure 1 plots the proportion of seats won by the 3 rd Party (Liberals) against the proportion of 1 st place votes they receive over the whole country. 35.0 30.0 Figure 1: Percentage of Seats Won by Liberals 25.0 20.0 FPTP AV Reference "scored" system Fair Line 15.0 10.0 5.0 0.0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 Percentage of 1st Place Votes to Liberals (whole country) This simulation assumes that the first two parties are separated by 5% (though assuming them equal made negligible difference to Figure 1). The simulation appears

to be representative in that a 26% Liberal vote would be predicted to give them ~10% of the seats, compared with the 9% which they actually won in 2010. The main outcome of the simulation is that, whilst AV would give the Liberals more seats (perhaps 15-20 more) even AV is a very long way from proportional representation. The blue curve in Figure 1 is the result of a system assigning a score of 2 to a 1 st place vote, a score of 1 to a 2 nd place vote, and zero to a 3 rd place vote. It could be argued that, based on simplistic left/centre/right considerations, the Liberals might be placed 2 nd more often than 3 rd (i.e., Con/Lib/Lab and Lab/Lib/Con would be more common than Lab/Con/Lib and Con/Lab/Lib). The simulation was repeated assuming that the Liberals were placed 2 nd twice as frequently as 3 rd. And repeated again, assuming the Liberals were placed 2 nd three times as frequently as 3 rd. The results are shown in Figure 2. 35.0 30.0 25.0 20.0 15.0 Figure 2: Percentage of Seats Won by Liberals - Effect of Greater Probability of 2nd Place FPTP AV (Liberals biased x2 2nd place) Reference "scored" system (Liberals biased x2 2nd place) Fair Line AV (no bias) Reference "scored" system (no bias) AV (Liberals biased x3 2nd place) 10.0 5.0 0.0 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 Percentage of 1st Place Votes to Liberals (whole country) A 2 nd place bias of x3 results in the Liberals taking a greater number of seats (perhaps ~15%, or an increase of 36 seats compare with their current number, assuming 26% of 1 st place votes). However, even in this case the number of Liberal seats falls far short of proportionality. The simple scored system (blue curve) is far more sensitive and much closer to proportionality. 3. Rigorous Voting Theorems Arrow s Theorem (1950) You need not waste your time searching for a fair voting system: there isn t one when there are three or more candidates. This is the burden of Arrow s Theorem, Ref.[1]. It is a rigorous mathematical theorem provided that a certain specific definition of fair is adopted. The strict mathematical statement of what constitutes fairness in this

context is rather opaque. I have translated it below into language appropriate to the UK electoral system. (Apologies if this looses some rigour). Fairness requires, [1] All voters are equal; [2] If all voters prefer party A to party B then party A wins more seats than party B; [3] Whether party A wins more seats than party B depends only upon the proportion of voters who prefer party A to party B (not upon the relative preference of other parties). These seem like reasonable requirements, but actually there is no voting system which respects all three conditions (assuming three or more candidates). Condition [1] can be weakened and the theorem remains true. It is only necessary that there is no dictator who decides the outcome unilaterally by fiat. The underlying assumption is that people vote by specifying a preference order for each candidate. (FPTP is not discounted the candidates for whom you do not vote are regarded as joint bottom place). Arrow s Theorem can be circumvented if voters are allowed to score each candidate (e.g., 80 points for your favoured candidate, 20 points for a poor second choice, and none for the hated other candidates). Both FPTP and AV fail to meet condition [3]. Gibbard Satterthwaite Theorem (1973) The Gibbard Satterthwaite Theorem, Refs.[2,3], states that providing there is no dictator and that anyone can win, there is always an opportunity for tactical voting in any electoral system. Tactical voting is defined as the ability to increase the likelihood of your desired outcome (or reduce the likelihood of your most undesirable outcome) by voting in a manner which does not reflect your true preferences. Tactical voting is possible only when the likely pattern of voting is predictable (e.g., on the basis of previous elections). A corollary to the Gibbard Satterthwaite Theorem is that voting systems can never be a straightforward means of joint decision making, but will always be a non-trivial game (in the strict game-theoretical sense). The first recognition of this fact has been attributed to Lewis Carroll (in his other guise as the mathematician Charles Dodgson). Implications of the rigorous theorems for AV? The fact that there is no system which respects all three of Arrow s requirements for fairness does not mean that all voting systems are equally unfair. It is perfectly possible for one system to be less unfair than another, and this is surely desirable. Arguably, AV is less unfair than FPTP, but both are grossly unfair with respect to proportional representation (Figures 1 and 2). Proponents of AV have been claiming that AV eliminates the need for tactical voting. Mathematicians (e.g., David Broomhead in The Guardian, 23/4/11) have opined that this cannot be so since the Gibbard Satterthwaite Theorem rules out this possibility. The true situation is that AV cannot entirely eliminate the opportunity for tactical voting, but nevertheless AV does make it far less common for tactical voting to be relevant. So the Electoral Reform Society and other AV - Yes campaigners are essentially correct despite the Gibbard Satterthwaite Theorem.

Conclusions [1] There is no fair voting system but some systems are less unfair than others. [2] If the three major parties each received about one-third of the overall vote, the effect of AV on the outcome of an election could be dramatic. However this is not representative of the UK. [3] Random simulation successfully predicts that a third party (Liberal) vote of 26% translates into ~9%-10% of the seats under FPTP. [4] AV results in the third party (Liberals) obtaining more seats for the same percentage of the overall votes. [5] Assuming the same total votes as in 2010 (i.e., 26%), under AV the Liberals would win 12% of the seats (75 MPs) compared with the current 9% (57 MPs). [6] If there is also a strong tendency to place the Liberals 2 nd, a total of 26% of first place votes would win the Liberals 15% of seats (93 MPs) under AV. [7] The AV system is therefore more likely to result in hung Parliaments and coalition governments. [8] But if most people only voted for their first choice, AV would degenerate to FPTP anyway. [9] Fairness is not the only consideration. There is also stability and decisiveness. In view of [7], FPTP may be preferable in these respects. [10] It doesn t matter how you vote anyway it will always be some b****y politician in charge. References [1] Kenneth J. Arrow, A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare, The Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 58, No. 4. (Aug., 1950), pp. 328-346. [2] Allan Gibbard, Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result, Econometrica, Vol. 41, No. 4 (1973), pp. 587 601. [3] Mark A. Satterthwaite, Strategy-proofness and Arrow's Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Functions, Journal of Economic Theory 10 (April 1975), 187 216

This document was created with Win2PDF available at http://www.win2pdf.com. The unregistered version of Win2PDF is for evaluation or non-commercial use only. This page will not be added after purchasing Win2PDF.