Poking Hobbes in the Eye: A Plea for Mechanism in Anarchist History

Similar documents
2 Anarchy Unbound Some readers may not be quite so optimistic about government, or quite so pessimistic about anarchy, as Hobbes was. Today it s widel

Pirates. Peter T. Leeson

The Origins of the Modern State

Government, Clubs, and Constitutions *

How much benevolence is benevolent enough?

Review of Virgil Henry Storr, Enterprising Slaves & Master Pirates: Understanding Economic Life in the Bahamas, New York: Peter Lang, 2004, 147pp.

enforce people s contribution to the general good, as everyone naturally wants to do productive work, if they can find something they enjoy.

Democracy, Exile and Revocation: a reply to Patti Lenard. David Miller

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Six. Social Contract Theory. of the social contract theory of morality.

Political Obligation. Dr Simon Beard. Centre for the Study of Existential Risk

Session 20 Gerald Dworkin s Paternalism

Lecture 11: The Social Contract Theory. Thomas Hobbes Leviathan Mozi Mozi (Chapter 11: Obeying One s Superior)

Interests, Interactions, and Institutions. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences. Interests: Actors and Preferences

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in a paragraph. (25 points total)

Law & Economics Lecture 1: Basic Notions & Concepts

Natural Law and Spontaneous Order in the Work of Gary Chartier

Notes toward a Theory of Customary International Law The Challenge of Non-State Actors: Standards and Norms in International Law

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

May 18, Coase s Education in the Early Years ( )

Political Obligation 2

Property Rights and the Rule of Law

Market Ethics The Vices, Virtues, and Values of Capitalism

An Austrian approach to law and economics, with special reference to superstition * Peter T. Leeson. Abstract

FREE EXCHANGE AND ETHICAL DECISIONS

Do Voters Have a Duty to Promote the Common Good? A Comment on Brennan s The Ethics of Voting

The origins of public finance, as a field of study though most certainly not

The future of Europe - lies in the past.

D. There are both positive and normative branches of the public choice literatures

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 854

The Market Failure Myth

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

J L S BOOK REVIEWS JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES VOLUME 21, NO. 2 (SUMMER 2007):

Waltz s book belongs to an important style of theorizing, in which far-reaching. conclusions about a domain in this case, the domain of international

Homo Economicus Lives: Some Implications for Humanitarian Assistance

Let's define each spectrum, and see where liberalism and conservatism reside on them.

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Social Contract Theory

Social order is perhaps the most enduring issue in the social sciences. Thirty years

Why do you deserve to be at UC Berkeley?

Political Science Introduction to American Politics

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

Lord of the Flies: We Tend Towards Entropy

FREE DOWNLOAD. NSDA LINCOLN-DOUGLAS DEBATE SAMPLING Member preparation throughout the tournament season. Sampling from Season 18 Monument Membership

preserving individual freedom is government s primary responsibility, even if it prevents government from achieving some other noble goal?

PS 0500: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/classes/worldpolitics

The Enlightenment. The Age of Reason

Coordination without Command: Stretching the Scope of Spontaneous Order

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Global Aspirations versus Local Plumbing: Comment: on Nussbaum. by Richard A. Epstein

The Enlightenment. Age of Reason

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Democracy is Bankrupt

POLITICAL SCIENCE 1101 SAMPLE ESSAY ANSWERS BUCKNER F. MELTON, JR.

III. PUBLIC CHOICE AND GOVERNMENT AS A SOLUTION

Book Review James Q. Whitman, Harsh Justice: Criminal Punishment and the Widening Divide between America and Europe (2005)

Human Standards of Commodious Living

Article 30. Exceptions to Rights Conferred

Why Do We Need Government?

BY CASSANDRA NELSDN in MDGADiSHU, SDMALiA

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Rational Choice. Pba Dab. Imbalance (read Pab is greater than Pba and Dba is greater than Dab) V V

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE!

PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/ps

THE CONSTITUTIONALIZATION OF MONEY James M. Buchanan

Political Science Introduction to American Politics

PSC/IR 106: Basic Models of Conflict and Cooperation. William Spaniel williamspaniel.com/pscir-106

Students will understand the characteristics of the Enlightenment by

Topic Page: Hobbes, Thomas,

VI. Rawls and Equality

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

ONE MORE TIME WITH FEELING: THE LAW MERCHANT, ARBITRATION, AND INTERNATIONAL TRADE

Liberal Peace. Erik Gartzke. 154A, Lecture 4 October 23, 2012

Criminal Constitutions *

The Nature of Law. Lesson One. Aims. Context. Note. The aims of this lesson are to enable you to

Non-global social contracts: A note on inefficient social institutions*

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Chapter 10 Thinking about fairness and inequality

Mr. Rarrick. John Locke

THE BINATIONAL FARM WORKER REBELLION Interviews with three farm worker leaders

RE: Less Spending and More Government: the Conflicting Views of Voters Under 40

An experimental investigation of Hobbesian jungles

Sociological Theory II SOS3506 Erling Berge. Introduction (Venue: Room D108 on 31 Jan 2008, 12:15) NTNU, Trondheim. Spring 2008.

Samaritanism and the Duty to Obey the Law

LOGROLLING. Nicholas R. Miller Department of Political Science University of Maryland Baltimore County Baltimore, Maryland

UNITED NATIONS GENERAL ASSEMBLY. Submission for the Democratic People s Republic of Korea (NORTH KOREA)

EM4721 OFFICER'S HANDBOOK

Political Science 200A Week 8. Social Dilemmas

PERTH COUNTER-PIRACY CONFERENCE JULY 2012 CHAIRMAN S FINAL STATEMENT OF THE MEETING

Motion 1: This House Would hold football clubs responsible for the behaviour of their fans

Why Government? Activity, pg 1. Name: Page 8 of 26

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

Inequality between the rich and poor is growing. Historically, what have been the best ways of reducing inequality?

Robert Nozick Equality, Envy, Exploitation, etc. (Chap 8 of Anarchy, State and Utopia 1974)

The Success of Clan Governance in Somalia: Beyond Failed State Discourse By: Abdullahi M. Cawsey May 3, 2014

John Locke. Source: John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government published 1689

I. Identify and or Define. III. Diagrams, Games, and Puzzles. II. Matching exercise: link the following philosophers with their ideas.

Summary of Social Contract Theory by Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau

Governance as a strategy in state-of-nature games

Transcription:

Poking Hobbes in the Eye: A Plea for Mechanism in Anarchist History Peter T. Leeson Thomas Hobbes famously described life in the state of nature as solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short. According to him, under anarchy humanity is engaged in a war of all against all. Government provides an exit from this barbaric world and an entrance to a civilized one. It follows that no sensible person would choose to live under anarchy if he had the option to live under government. Hobbes characterized anarchy this way in 1651. His characterization stuck. Today the view Hobbes expounded describes the vast majority of people s thinking about statelessness. Anarchy as chaos or at least as inevitably inferior to government is conventional wisdom. What s remarkable about this wisdom is that it s demonstrably false. A large and growing literature on self-governance finds that real-world anarchy needn t be dire. Nor must it be plagued by endless conflict (see, for instance, the work surveyed in Powell and Stringham 2009). On the contrary, many stateless societies display significant civilization. Some are more orderly, peaceful, and produce better material conditions than their state-governed counterparts (see, for instance, Leeson 2007; Leeson and Williamson 2009). Enter James Scott s (2009) book, The Art of Not Being Governed: An Anarchist History of Upland Southeast Asia. Scott s central thesis is simple and surely right: some people choose to live without government. And that choice is sensible. 1 Address: Department of Economics, George Mason University, MS 3G4, Fairfax, VA 22030, USA. Email: PLeeson@GMU.edu. 1

Governments are wont to prey on their citizens. They engage in conscription, slavery, taxation, forced labor, and costly interstate conflicts. If state predation is severe enough, or one s tolerance for state predation is low enough, rather than living under government, a person may choose, quite rationally and quite literally, to head for the hills. Here he can live outside the state s reach. To illustrate this point and the strategies of state repellency that those who make this choice employ, Scott examines the Zomia people who inhabit the hills of southeast Asia. I see Scott s book as giving Thomas Hobbes a much-needed, and much-deserved, poke in the eye. My goal in this note is consider how to make that poke more effective. My plea for anarchist histories is simple: focus on mechanisms. If people choose to live under anarchy instead of government, this strongly suggests that for them life under anarchy is less solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short than life under government or at least not more so. This is what Scott s discussion suggests in the case of the hill people of southeast Asia. But there s a puzzle here. Return to Hobbes. Hobbes didn t pull his imagined description of anarchy, and the resultant notion of government superiority, out of thin air. He grounded it in a reasonable argument. The crux of that argument is found in what the parlance of modern game theory calls a prisoners dilemma. Here s how that dilemma looks. We can think of people in the state of nature as having two basic choices in their interactions with others: they can cooperate with the persons they interact with or they can defect in those interactions. The former refers to keeping one s promises, respecting other persons lives and belongings, and so on. The latter refers to the opposite kinds of behavior. (2007). 1 I ve made a similar point myself in the context of statelessness in contemporary Somalia. See Leeson 2

If both you and the person you interact with behave cooperatively with the other, both of you do well. There s peace. However, if you defect against the person you interact with but he cooperates, you do even better while he does much worse. There s plunder. Likewise, if the person you interact with defects against you but you cooperate, he does better but you do much worse. There s again plunder. If both of you defect in your interactions with each other, both of you do poorly. There s war. But neither person does as poorly as when he s the sucker the person who cooperates when the other defects. It turns out that in such a game, both you and the person you interact with always find it in your interest to defect in your interactions rather than to cooperate. No matter what the other person does, you do best for yourself by behaving uncooperatively. The result is an uncooperative world a world of perpetual war in which both you and the persons you interact with are worse off. There s a solution to this dilemma, however. If some external agency with a monopoly on the legitimized use of force existed call it Leviathan that agency could use its might to compel everyone to cooperate. Then neither you nor the persons you interact with have to worry about other persons defecting. In this way Leviathan can replace the barbarism of anarchy with the civilization of government. The basic logic of the prisoners dilemma though, as I discuss below, not the conclusion commonly drawn from it seems pretty much right. People commonly confront situations of potential conflict. That conflict can be initiated unilaterally, such as when one person seeks to steal your car, or bilaterally, such as when you and the person you forge a contract with seek to get the upper hand in the deal. 3

To overcome such conflicts peaceably, people need some mechanism for producing social order. If no such mechanism exists, something like what Hobbes described in the case of anarchy is likely to result. People will end up fighting each other. Or, to prevent that situation, they will become recluses and avoid interpersonal interactions altogether, living solitary and thus poor lives instead. Anarchy skeptics, such as Hobbes, are skeptical of the claim that anarchy is a viable alternative to the state precisely because they doubt the existence of mechanisms other than government that could sole the prisoners dilemma-type problems that individuals in any society routinely confront. In their view government is the only mechanism that can provide effective governance. Indeed, they view government and governance as synonyms. But they re not. The former is a subset of the latter. Governance refers to some set of rules that regulate interpersonal interactions and institutions for enforcing those rules. Government is one particular (and in the modern world, a particularly popular) mechanism of governance. It s one based on a monopoly on the legitimized use of force. But there are plenty of other sources of social rules of law and plenty of other sources of rule enforcement of order that have nothing to do with government. Even Scott, who clearly doesn t view government and social order as synonyms, treats the concepts of government and government as if he did. Consider his book s title: The Art of Not Being Governed. Are the hill people of southeast Asia really ungoverned? I hope not. If they are, this would cast serious doubt on Scott s central claim that those people choose to live outside the state. Given the logic of the prisoners dilemma described above, if living outside the state means living without any governance at all without any rules or institutions of their enforcement, and thus without any law and order it would seem that 4

Hobbes conclusion about anarchy is correct. Life will indeed be solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short. And if Hobbes conclusion about anarchy is correct, it s difficult to believe that any sensible person would opt to live without government. There s a way out of this conundrum. That way is this. The logic of the prisoners dilemma is correct: in all societies people confront problems of conflict that must be overcome. 2 But government isn t the only mechanism for overcoming them. Other mechanisms of governance may do the job just as well perhaps even better. To distinguish these mechanisms of governance from state-supplied ones, we might call them mechanisms of private governance. What are the mechanisms of private governance that can support social order and thus render anarchy, at least in principle, preferable to government? Unfortunately, in the case off the hill people of southeast Asia who he considers, Scott doesn t tell us. But if Scott is right that these people consciously chose to live outside the state and his work leaves little doubt that they did it stands to reason that they must have relied on some mechanisms of private governance to prevent hill-life without government from becoming fodder for the Hobbesian worldview. To be persuasive, arguments that want to construe anarchy as a viable alternative to government must identify and analyze mechanisms of private governance. These mechanisms are the means by which the logic of the prisoners dilemma under anarchy is overcome. They are the potential source of a reasonable foundation for the claim that life under anarchy needn t be worse than, and may even be better than, life under government. 2 Note that in beginning this way, we begin by agreeing with Hobbes and nearly everyone else that conflict is a genuine and universal social problem. In doing so we found our position on decidedly non-utopian grounds, removing from discourse this common red-herring which crops up in conversations about anarchy. 5

Social norms are one prevalent example of such mechanisms (see, for example, Leeson and Coyne 2011). When you first meet someone (in the United States, at least), you extend your hand and introduce yourself. You don t ignore your counterpart or curse him. There s no statecrated law mandating or enforcing this social rule. Yet nearly everyone follows it. This greeting rule emerged spontaneously as a product of interactions over time because it facilitates cooperative interaction. 3 This rule is enforced through ostracism and gossip. Cold fish are disliked and distrusted. When we can, we avoid them. Or we say unkind things about them behind their backs. This gives persons strong incentives to greet others in the expected manner. There s no government here. But we have a kind of law and order of first interactions nonetheless. Norms aren t the only mechanisms of private governance. Stateless societies have developed a large variety of others to cope with the problem Hobbes posed. Consider Gypsy societies, which Scott invokes numerous times to draw parallels to his hill people. Gypsy societies are stateless. Their members are historically nomadic. And one can reasonably think about their decision to live apart from the governments in the areas they populate as a sensible, consciously made choice given how those governments have treated them. Gypsy societies, like all others, require some governance mechanisms to function some basis for law and order. Since they live outside the state, their governance mechanisms can t be government. They must be private. One such mechanism in Gypsy societies is Romaniya, or Gypsy law (see, for instance, Leeson 2010). That law is based on Gypsies spiritual beliefs. In very broad strokes those beliefs involves the upper half of the human body being spiritually pure and the lower half 3 On the concept of spontaneous order, see Hayek (1948). 6

being spiritually polluted and thus carefully avoided. Gypsies leverage this belief system to define and help enforce basic social rules governing their interactions. For example, under Romaniya stealing from a fellow-gypsy puts one in the same state of spiritual contamination as unguarded contact with a woman s skirt (which is polluted owing to its contact with her lower half). The fear of supernatural rule-breaking is brought to bear on wordly rule-breaking, recruiting spiritual beliefs to promote cooperation in corporeal affairs. Many Gypsy communities also have a private court system called a kris. Here Gypsy elders adjudicate conflicts between other Gypsies, such as those emerging from economic partnerships, and render judgments backed by the threat of social ostracism (a punishment that itself leverages Gypsy spiritual beliefs since unguarded contact with the non-gypsy world into which an ostracized person is necessarily thrust also contaminates him spiritually according to Gypsy belief). Gypsies aren t not governed, to use Scott s terminology. They re not governed by government. But that requires them to develop alternative governance mechanisms private ones which are found in Romaniya and the kris. The fact that Gypsy societies, like many of Scott s hill societies, are basically acephalous and egalitarian doesn t alter this fact. If anything, this makes more elaborate mechanisms of private governance more important to their functioning. The say-so of an unquestioned leader at least when that leader is voluntarily abided may be considered a mechanism of private governance. But when such a leader is absent, other, more complex mechanisms of private governance become more important. Consider another example: the case of 18 th -century Caribbean pirates. Many of these fellows came to pirating having spent time on English merchant vessels or ships of the Royal 7

Navy. On those vessels authority was concentrated in the hands of captains and a few smaller officers. The result was an autocratic organization that often led to seaman abuse at the hands of unscrupulous captains. To escape this predation, some legitimate sailors turned to piracy. This gave them the opportunity to live outside the state and its maritime manifestations. Thus there s some similarity to situation of the hill peoples that Scott describes. As pirates, such sailors were of course criminals. Thus they couldn t rely on government to create or enforce social order among them. Yet law and order was necessary if these sailors wanted to pirate at all. A pirate crew whose members stole from one another, fought constantly, and so on wouldn t have lasted long. To address their need for governance without government, pirates pioneered a private system of constitutional democracy (see, for instance, Leeson 2009). Pirate ships required captains and other officers, just like legitimate ships did. But to prevent these persons from abusing their authority as they frequently did on legitimate vessels, pirates elected and deposed them democratically. What s more, to make the laws governing their societies explicit, pirates codified them in written constitutional documents they called articles. These articles prohibited intercrewmember theft, violence, and so on, and stipulated penalties to be administered by democratically elected officers called quartermasters for breaking them. Pirates private governance system was democratic and egalitarian. And it was so by design. But that doesn t mean that mechanisms of governance were absent in pirate societies. On the contrary, democracy was a key mechanism of pirates private governance. When hierarchy is more-or-less absent, this necessitates different mechanisms of private governance to avoid the 8

Hobbesian Jungle. It doesn t preclude the need for such mechanisms, which remains as important as ever. As a final example, consider the American pioneers. Lured by tales of wealth and perhaps eager to escape the thumb of government in settled parts of the United States, in the early 19 th century American pioneers headed westward to start new lives. Government was at this point unestablished in the American West. Its absence is largely responsible for the popular perception of the early American West as wild and lawless. But popular perception is wrong. In lieu of state-supplied governance, pioneers developed mechanisms of private governance to help them secure social cooperation in formally ungoverned territories (see, for instance, Anderson and Hill 2004). They created land clubs to privately define and enforce property rights in unowned land. They created cattlemen associations to defend against cattle rustlers thieves who sought to exploit the absence of formal government. And they created mining camps that delineated the laws of mining where conflicting claims were likely to arise. The result was a tame and orderly West, not a violent and disorderly one. Mechanisms of private governance filled the void left by absence of formal government. There was no government. But there was plenty of governance. Returning to Scott s book: Scott argues that the state-based society was undesirable for many inhabitants of southeast Asia. Thus these persons chose to head for the hills and live without government. My complaint is that this argument skips a crucial step. What mechanisms of private governance existed in hill-based, stateless societies that made these societies capable of functioning, and thus conceivably preferred to those available under government? In passing over this step in near silence, Scott s poke in Hobbes eye ends up being producing a rather 9

glancing blow. Then again, poking Hobbes in the eye is my desired outcome of Scott s book, not Scott s. But my point is a more general one: compelling anarchist histories must, in my view, focus on mechanisms of private governance under anarchy. This isn t only the source of more powerful pokes in Hobbes eye. It s the source of improved understanding about how people in most of the world, for most of its history, have lived. 10

References Anderson, Terry L., and Peter J. Hill. 2004. The Not So Wild, Wild West: Property Rights on the Frontier. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1948. Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Leeson, Peter T. 2010. Gypsies. Mimeo. Leeson, Peter T. 2009. The Invisible Hook: The Hidden Economics of Pirates. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Leeson, Peter T. 2007. Better Off Stateless: Somalia Before and After Government Collapse. Journal of Comparative Economics 35: 689-710. Leeson, Peter T., and Christopher J. Coyne. 2011. Conflict-Inhibiting Norms. In Michelle Garfinkel and Stergios Skaperdas, eds. Oxford Handbook of the Economics of Peace and Conflict. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Leeson, Peter T., and Claudia R. Williamson. 2009. Anarchy and Development: An Application of the Theory of Second Best. Law and Development Review 2: 77-96. Powell, Benjamin, and Edward P. Stringham. 2009. Public Choice and the Economic Analysis of Anarchy: A Survey. Public Choice 104: 503-538. Scott, James C. 2009. The Art of Not Being Governed: An Anarchist History of Southeast Asia. New Haven: Yale University Press. 11