SECESSION NOTES FOR PHILOSOPHY 13 DICK ARNESON

Similar documents
Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 26, No. 1. (Winter, 1997), pp

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Ethical Basis of Welfare Economics. Ethics typically deals with questions of how should we act?

The Forgotten Principles of American Government by Daniel Bonevac

RECONSIDERING CONTESTED SECESSIONS: UNFEASIBILITY AND INDETERMINACY

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

The Moral Value of Collective Self-determination and the Ethics of Secession. by Margaret Moore, Queen s University, Canada.

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

Questions. Hobbes. Hobbes s view of human nature. Question. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority?

Hobbes. Questions. What justification is there for a state? Does the state have supreme authority? What limits are there upon the state?

The Entitlement Theory 1 Robert Nozick

Debating at Chennai Worlds

CHAPTER 4, On Liberty. Does Mill Qualify the Liberty Principle to Death? Dick Arneson For PHILOSOPHY 166 FALL, 2006

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Introduction to Economics

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Self-determination, immigration restrictions, and the problem of compatriot deportation

- The Fast PR System is a proportional representation (PR) system. Every vote counts. But it offers significant differences from other PR systems.

Government Surveillance and Incentives to Abuse Power

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

AMERICAN FOREIGN POLICY. result. If pacificism results in oppression, he must be willing to suffer oppression.

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

War in the Middle East. Raymond Hinnebusch University of St Andrews

A political theory of territory

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

The Wilt/Shaquille argument ("How Liberty Upsets Patterns," pp ) It takes the form of a reductio ad absurdum.

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Research Note: Gaming NAFTA. March 15, Gaming NAFTA: Trump v. Nieto

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will

Reflection & Connection Task

Arguments for and against electoral system change in Ireland

Ideologies of Individualism & Collectivism

A Fair Division Solution to the Problem of Redistricting

Example 8.2 The Economics of Terrorism: Externalities and Strategic Interaction

LIBERTARIANISM AND IMMIGRATION

Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders

LEARNING FROM SCHELLING'S STRATEGY OF CONFLICT by Roger Myerson 9/29/2006

Great comments! (A lot of them could be germs of term papers )

Secession as a Remedial Right i. Michel Seymour Department of philosophy University of Montreal

Dworkin, selections from Taking Rights Seriously. Dworkin identifies these three propositions as forming the core of the legal positivist position:

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Summary of Social Contract Theory by Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau

National Integrity Study Czech Republic Authors: Petr Jansa, Radim Bureš & co., Transparency International

that keeps judges' hands off the economic system.

RATIONAL CHOICE AND CULTURE

This is a repository copy of Territorial rights and open borders.

SELF DETERMINATION IN INTERNATIONAL LAW

Matthew Adler, a law professor at the Duke University, has written an amazing book in defense

CHRISTOFOROS IOANNIDIS

Canadian electoral reform involves a befuddling

THE ORIGINAL POSITION PHILOSOPHY

The Dispensability of Allies

Does federalism decrease social cleavages and lead to greater political stability? 1

Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court *

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

Political Obligation 4

PSC/IR 106: The Democratic Peace Theory. William Spaniel /

THRESHOLDS. Underlying principles. What submitters on the party vote threshold said

Decision Making on Family Business Matters. By: Christopher J. Eckrich, Ph.D and Stephen L. McClure, Ph.D The Family Business Consulting Group

Aggregation and the Separateness of Persons

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Dr. Mohammad O. Hamdan

Phil 115, May 25, 2007 Justice as fairness as reconstruction of the social contract

Balancing Procedures and Outcomes Within Democratic Theory: Core Values and Judicial Review

A Trade Mark Symphony. Finale: EU Case law and judicial system: Cacophony or Harmony?

Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners

Towards Sustainable Economy and Society Under Current Globalization Trends and Within Planetary Boundaries: A Tribute to Hirofumi Uzawa

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

A Few Contributions of Economic Theory to Social Welfare Policy Analysis

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

PRESS SUMMARY. On appeal from R (Conway) v Secretary of State for Justice [2017] EWHC 2447 (Admin)

1 Repe, Božo. The view from inside: the Slovenes, the Federation and Yugoslavia's other republics: referat

Lesson Description. Essential Questions

A NORMATIVE POSITIVISM: LINKING STRUCTURAL AND PROCEDURAL PRINCIPLES TO CONCEPTIONS OF AUTHORITY USING HART S RULE OF RECOGNITION

Changes in immigration law and discussion of readings from Guarding the Golden Door.

DISSENTING OPINION OF JUDGE KOROMA

Phil 116, April 5, 7, and 9 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia

Part Three (continued): Electoral Systems & Linkage Institutions

idolatry. Claro Mayo Recto 10 Institute for Political and Electoral Reform

From The Collected Works of Milton Friedman, compiled and edited by Robert Leeson and Charles G. Palm.

Justice, fairness and Equality. foundation and profound influence on the determination and administration of morality. As such,

Forced to Policy Extremes: Political Economy, Property Rights, and Not in My Backyard (NIMBY)

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global

Can Negative Utilitarianism be Salvaged?

Lincoln s Election and Southern Secession

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

Towards a Symmetrical World: Migration and International Law

Reading vs. Seeing. Federal and state government are often looked at as separate entities but upon

Lesson Title: Redistricting in Pennsylvania

Philosophy 267 Fall, 2010 Professor Richard Arneson Introductory Handout revised 11/09 Texts: Course requirements: Week 1. September 28.

Exam Questions By Year IR 214. How important was soft power in ending the Cold War?

Social Contract Theory

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

Transcription:

1 SECESSION NOTES FOR PHILOSOPHY 13 DICK ARNESON In our time, secessionist aspirations and movements abound. How should we respond? Most Kurds today living in Turkey, Iraq, and Iran want to secede and form an independent sovereign Turkish state. Is this a just demand? Is there a fundamental moral right to secede, and if so who has such a right, and under what conditions? In today s course readings, Allen Buchanan and Christopher Wellman offer opposed views on these questions. Below, I summarize their positions. My own critical comments are enclosed in square brackets, like this [Buchanan and Wellman are full of beans.] A secession struggle is the attempt by a group of people, living under a government, to sever their connection to that government and form a separate independent state, taking a portion of the territory of the initial state. ALLEN BUCHANAN S VIEWS Allen Buchanan distinguishes two questions we could be addressing: (1) is there a basic moral right to secede (setting aside issues of institutional implementation), and (2) is there a moral right to secede that should be recognized as a matter of international institutional morality, including a morally defensible system of international law. He focuses on the latter question, which he takes to be more significant. [Comment. There is a gap between holding there is a right to X and holding that we should implement this right in law and social practices in a given setting at a given time. For example, one might consistently hold that there is a moral right to voluntary physician-assisted suicide (PAS), but that there should not be a legal right to PAS in the U.S. today, because enacting PAS in law would give rise to misconduct on the part of some physicians and relatives of very ill persons leading to wrongful killings of these ill persons. But the gap is not so great. If we think there is a moral right to PAS, we should strive swiftly to bring about conditions in which it can be implemented without undue cost to other moral values. A serious moral right is hardly ever an idle wheel. Moreover, if there is a serious moral right to something, that right weighs heavily in the scales and counts for a lot when there is practical conflict with other values. If we think there is a serious right to free speech, we won t favor banning political demonstrations on the ground that they cause extra litter. So noting as Buchanan does that there is a gap between asserting a right and asserting it should be implemented in some particular way does not deny the importance for practical choice of policy of deciding what people s moral rights are.] [Comment. Anyway, given there is a gap between a right and the best means of implementing it, why suppose the key or sole issue is how the right would or not fit within currently recognized international morality and international law? One might think current international morality is in a pretty crude and undeveloped state and current international law is little more than agreed rhetoric and dealmaking among the world s big powers.] Buchanan notes that a special right to secede might arise from contract, promise, or special relationship. We are interested in the shape of a general right to secede, one a group would have independently of contract, promise, or special relationship.

2 Buchanan divides theories asserting a general right of secession into categories, Primary Right Theories and Remedial Right Only Theories. The difference is that the latter hold that a group has a right to secede only if it suffers violations of its rights other than the alleged right of secession itself. The right to secede on this approach always rides piggy-back on other rights violations. In contrast, according to Primary Right Theories, under appropriate circumstances a group can have the right to secede from a nation even if the group is suffering no violations of its rights other than the right to secede itself. Buchanan distinguishes two varieties of Primary Right Theories, Ascriptive and Associative. According to the former, a group must have some specified special characteristics in order to acquire a primary right to secede. For example, one might hold that nations and only nations have a right of self-determination that includes a right to secede, and stipulate that a nation is a group of people united by common language, shared history and culture, and perhaps more. According to Associative Primary Right Theories, there is no requirement that a group, to have the right to secede, must have any special characteristics. Any collection of people could form a group that has the right to secede. What confers a right to secede on a group is rather the voluntary choice of its members or sufficiently many of its members to secede and form a separate and independent nation. Perhaps other conditions must be met as well, but these further conditions do not involve the characteristics of the group. As Buchanan puts it, Any group, however heterogeneous, can qualify for the right to secede. The extra conditions rather involve questions such as whether the group whose members voluntarily choose to secede is capable of forming an independent state and whether it would form a state that enforces the basic rights of its members and whether its departure leaves the members of the rump left behind in an unfairly precarious position. (The Remedial Right Only (RRA) Theory can add similar extra conditions; the key difference is that for the RRA theorist, a just claim to secession by a group must appeal to violations of the group s rights other than the alleged right of secession itself.) Buchanan proposes four criteria for evaluating proposals for an international legal right to secede: 1. Minimal realism. A proposal must be morally progressive (would improve overall rights fulfillment if implemented) but also be minimally realistic, meaning the proposal must have a significant prospect of actually being adopted in the foreseeable future, through the processes by which international law is actually made (p. 42). 2. Consistency with well-entrenched, morally progressive features of current international law. 3. Absence of perverse incentives. A proposal, if implemented under reasonably favorable incentives, should not encourage bad behavior, behavior that leads to bad consequences, especially lesser overall fulfillment of people s important basic moral rights. 4. Moral accessibility. A proposal for reforming international law should be morally accessible to a broad international audience. It should not require acceptance of a particular religious ethic or of ethical principles that are not shared by a wide range of secular and religious viewpoints (p. 44). Buchanan proceeds to argue that the Remedial right Only Theories he favors score better on these four criteria than the Primary Right Theories of the right of secession. [Comment. As noted already, we have to decide what we should be for before we can sensibly address the question, how best to implement what we should be for. Buchanan mixes up these discussions in an odd way. We need to decide whether there is a right to secede and if so, of what strength, before we can decide whether trying to establish such a right in international law is a good idea. Also, implementing might take a form other than implementation-byincorporation-in-international-law. Compare: There surely was a time in world history when trying to get a right against enslavement enacted in (what passed

3 for) international law would have been a waste of time or counterproductive. From this it does not follow that there is not a right against enslavement or that the right does not have strong weight in determining what we should do even in circumstances when trying to get such a right enacted in international law would be a bad idea. Leaving this point aside, one might argue that Buchanan exaggerates the practical difficulties in building a right to secession into international law in the foreseeable future. We could do this; the real question is, should we do so is there such a moral right in the first place?] CHRISTOPHER WELLMAN S VIEWS In A Defense of Secession and Political Self-Determination Christopher Wellman points out that a secession struggle involves a claim to jurisdiction over territory as well as over people. A secession struggle involves an attempt to redraw the boundaries of an existing state. The secession movement aims to withdraw people and territory from the jurisdiction of the current state. (Note to claim jurisdiction over territory is to claim that one legitimately makes and enforces law on the territory one claims. This need not be a claim involving ownership of the land.) So we need to understand when an existing state has a legitimate right to jurisdiction over the territory it rules and when a secession movement has the right to sever an existing state, taking jurisdiction over some of the territory the existing state rules. Wellman contrasts two traditional accounts of state legitimacy, which he calls the consent account and he teleological or functional account. These two accounts are perhaps mixed together in Locke s discussion. Wellman rejects both accounts and proposes a hybrid account. The consent account holds that a state rules territory legitimately only to the extent that the individuals residing on the territory voluntarily consent to its rule. Wellman holds that if this account were taken seriously, we would have to accept the implication that existing states have not gained such consent and are not legitimate. Also, if individuals were not actually to consent in future, the state would not rule those individuals legitimately. These implications are hard to swallow. Worse, the consent account implies that a single individual has a right to secede and set up a tiny one-person state or a state with just a few members. This is hard to accept. Third, Wellman notes that most consent accounts if examined closely really turn out to retreat to a different type of account hypothetical not actual consent. But if the state legitimately rules over people if it would be rational for them to consent (whether or not they actually do), we are really moving to a teleological position. The reasons it would be rational to consent, specifically, the degree to which the state protects basic rights, are what confer legitimacy on the hypothetical consent account. Finally, Wellman asks, if you suddenly had state power, would you believe it would be wrong for you to rule unless and until you secured the voluntary consent of all those you rule? He thinks we should answer NO, which involves rejecting the consent account. The teleological or functional account holds that the state legitimately rules the territory it claims just in case the state efficiently carries out appropriate state functions, namely, the protection of people s basic moral rights. This account implies that a secession movement is legitimate if and only if its success results in more efficient fulfillment of appropriate state functions. However, the account turns out to be too permissive, in Wellman s view. The teleological account implies that if Canada attempts to annex Mexico, this attempt is morally legitimate if the legitimate state function of protecting people s rights would be better fulfilled if Mexico came under the control of the Canadian state. Wellman thinks we should accept that in this scenario the Mexicans have a right to political self-determination, which rules out justified Canadian annexation.

4 Objection: The teleological account can say that if an existing state fulfills legitimate state functions of protecting rights to an adequate extent, it has the right to exist, and not be swallowed up by annexation. Wellman: This restriction would be arbitrary. The teleological account is inherently a maximizing account: whatever works out to fulfill best the legitimate state functions is morally legitimate. Wellman thinks we can pick out what is most attractive in the consent and teleological accounts and affirm the resulting hybrid position. The basic idea of the hybrid model is to limit the consent account by a teleological/functional condition. According to Wellman, individuals have a right to autonomy or individual self-determination, but no right to political self-determination, because an individual alone cannot form a well functioning state. But individuals banded together in a like-minded group do have a right to political self-determination including a right to secede, withdrawing themselves and territory (their per capita share?) from the jurisdiction of the existing state that rules them, provided two conditions are met. The conditions are that both the seceding group and the remainder group must be able to form a state that performs its political function of protecting rights (p. 161). Wellman applies his proposed hybrid account of state legitimacy and justifiable secession to four historical examples: The American revolution of 1776, the American Civil War of 1860-65; the secession of Lithuania from the former Soviet Union, and the movement of Quebecois to secede from Canada. [COMMENTS ON WELLMAN.] [1. As stated, Wellman s account is unclear in its application to cases in which there is disagreement among the people inhabiting a region of an existing state as to whether they will to secede. Buchanan interprets Wellman as adhering to a plebiscitary view of the right to secede: If a majority of people on a territory favor secession and both the state that secession would form and the rump state left behind will be able to carry out effectively what was referred to earlier as the legitimating functions of a state (preeminently the provision of justice and security), those who seek to secede have a moral right to do so. So consider Wellman so construed.] [A right of an individual to self-determination is unlike a right of a group to selfdetermination in that the exercise of the latter right may leave some individuals living in a way they oppose. Suppose 51 per cent of the people on a territory favor secession and 49 per cent of the inhabitants vehemently oppose it. Perhaps the minority will lose more if secession occurs than the majority loses if secession does not occur. A group right to secede in these circumstances is a right of the majority to determine to some degree the life of the minority] [2. I am not quite sure how the majority rule principle regulating the right to secede is to be applied. Suppose the nation is divided from North to South and a majority in the North votes to secede, then the same nation is split from East to West and a majority in the East votes to secede. What happens to those in the northwest and southeast? Do we keep holding plebiscites in these territories until no one calls for a further vote? But suppose after voting this way, a group proposes voting on a different basis a snakelike cut is made throughout North, East, West, and South of the nation and a majority of the snake votes for secession. There are regions that end up in the secession zone under the first procedure and not in the second. Then someone else proposes a different division of the nation, cutting it like a doughnut, and the inside of the doughnut

5 votes for secession. The three divisions between seceding state and rump state, arrived at by the different voting cuts, differ. What should be done? Perhaps Wellman holds that whoever proposes the first voting procedure gets to determine the subsequent sequence of votes. Voting proceeds until no further division and revote of a subdivision will yield a different division of territory and all who do not get their way in the vote are permitted to emigrate to the other side of the line of secession if they wish to do so.] [3. Suppose that a group in an existing nation claims the right to secede and both it and the rump state left behind will be able to establish and sustain functioning states. This seems to leave it open that people s rights (other than the disputed right to secede) would be better protected under the status quo. There is still a right to secede in these circumstances, according to Wellman. In effect, the teleological or functional condition on justified secession as he construes it is a threshold condition: rights in both seceding and rump states must be secure at least at a good enough threshold level. This allows that some people s rights, perhaps very important rights, would be better secured if the secession does not occur. One might dispute this aspect of Wellman s view.] [4. On the other hand, one might hold that for the group of would-be seceders, Wellman s teleological condition is too strong and wrongfully takes priority over the right of self-determination. Suppose (before the formation of the present Norway) Norwegians unanimously want to live in a sovereign state whose boundaries are those of present-day Norway, separate and independent of Sweden. Let s stipulate that basic rights other than the right of secession itself would be better secured for Norwegians if they remain part of Sweden. In fact, seceding Norway would be very likely to fall into anarchy or some other scenario that lacks a well-functioning state. But the Norwegians unanimously are willing to bear this risk; they still want independence. If Wellman affirms a strong individual right of self-determination and rejects paternalism, it seems he should accept the right of the Norwegians in this imaginary example to secede and risk anarchy. Another case to consider: The Norwegians want to secede from greater Sweden, and the rump group of Swedes could form a viable state but predictably will not do so. They could but they won t. The Norwegians might say: We still have the right to secede. We aren t depriving you of your right to maintain a viable state. But one might say one has duties to the people in rump Sweden who through no fault or choice of their own would suffer severe rights violations if Norway seceded and Sweden s political stability degenerates. Implicit in Wellman s account is the idea that one s obligation to support a state and cooperate to see that those affected by one s choices are not deprived of state protections is a Good Samaritan obligation: an obligation to do one s part to see to it that others do not severe significant violations of their rights. But then it seems Wellman ought to hold people have a right to secede and forego the protections of the state if they voluntarily choose to do so (perhaps steps must be taken to assure no harm to nonconsenting third parties like children). If we deny an individual has such a strong right to individual self-determination as Wellman supposes, the basis for the Wellman version of the right of groups to selfdetermination is weakened.] [5. One might hold that there is a right to do whatever one wants so long as one does not thereby wrongfully harm others. This would include a right to engage in trivial actions one does not much care about. Such a right could then be easily overridden. Is the right to secession stronger than this? Wellman clearly wants to defend a right to secession stronger than this, a right with teeth, a serious moral right. On what grounds?]

6