Philosophy of social science

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Philosophy of social science"

Transcription

1 Philosophy of social science Turner, Stephen. The Social Theory of Practices: Tradition, Tacit Knowledge, and Presuppositions. University of Chicago Press, Pp. x, 145. $39.95 (cloth), $14.95 (paper). Ethics 1996 Stephen Turner proposes to provide a philosophical analysis of a family of concepts falling under the general heading of social practice : the notion of a tacit set of rules, norms, or presuppositions that inform behavior in a given cultural milieu and that are socially authoritative and causally influential. Examples include: skills of the carpenter, passed on from master to apprentice; knowledge of laboratory techniques passed on from senior scientist to graduate student; norms of etiquette and comportment, passed on from adults to children; frameworks of interpretation of literary or religious texts; social practices governing the use and significance of food; and many others. Especially important among such phenomena in Turner s account are epistemic practices: the notion that knowledge and belief are dependent upon schemes, worldviews, or frameworks that are not themselves amenable to rational standards of assessment. Turner makes the important point that we need a better conceptualization of the theory of practice. And he offers detailed and provocative analysis of a host of problems raised in this area. Turner s position is that the concept of practice is seductive but ultimately untenable. The central source of his skepticism has to do with the difficulty of assuring that the same practice is transmitted. Where does a social practice reside? How is it transmitted? How do the young absorb the mores of their elders? How are the rules of these practices represented internally within the individual? What guarantees that two practitioners each equally adept have the same practical knowledge, the same internal grammar? On the basis of skeptical answers to several of these questions, Turner concludes that there is no such thing as a social practice; rather, there are trained similarities of external performance. Turner s skepticism about social practices is ultimately unpersuasive. The reality of social customs, norms, mores, assumptions, worldviews, habits practices, in short is too compelling to be seriously doubted. The challenge, then, is to provide an account of embodiment and transmission of such skills and knowledge that makes sense of the facts of social experience and addresses the concerns that Turner raises. And in fact, the outlines of such an account are not hard to produce. We might postulate that each individual possesses a norm inference engine, on the basis of which the individual observes the social

2 behavior of those around him or her and arrives at a hypothesis about the underlying rule of behavior. As dissonant experience is encountered, the norm inference engine updates its hypotheses. The individual s conduct is generated through application of the current state of the social grammar. A cultural practice is embodied in the ensemble of individual social competences and performances at a given time. Individual social behavior is thus structured by the state of social knowledge embodied in the current generation. These structured behaviors in turn constitute paradigm examples for others grist for the norm inference engines of other members of the community. Through such mechanisms, a population of practitioners successfully transmit their knowledge to the next generation. This ultimate disagreement notwithstanding, Turner s book is a worthwhile contribution. Authors as diverse as Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and Bourdieu have made the notion of practice central to their social theories: language, conceptual schemes, and modes of behavior are to be understood as bearing the imprint of social practice. Turner is certainly right in holding that there is no collective entity underlying a social practice no occult system of mores or traditions that causally interact with individuals. And Turner s careful efforts to unpack the presuppositions of this concept serve well to clarify our thinking about social practices. Zalk, Sue Rosenberg and Janice Gordon-Kelter, eds. Revolutions in Knowledge: Feminism in the Social Sciences. Westview, $44.00 (cloth). Pp. ix, 170. Ethics 1994 This collection attempts to assess the import of recent feminist scholarship for various social science disciplines. A common theme throughout the volume is the importance of distinguishing between two objectives of feminist scholarship: to draw attention to issues pertaining to women s experience that have often been neglected by traditional scholarship, and to reformulate the concepts, methods, and frameworks in terms of which social science research is conducted in such a way as to provide a better basis for understanding women s experience. In line with these concerns, many of the essays attempt to document the need for substantial conceptual and methodological reform in the social sciences. Likewise, many of the essays provide detailed and interesting illustrations of some of the shortcomings of traditional research frameworks in various fields. Finally, a good deal of space is expended on detailing the institutional structure of the respective disciplines. 2

3 There is much to admire in this volume. This reader is struck, however, by the negative stance taken throughout toward the value of scientific objectivity. But it is possible to be both feminist and empiricist: to maintain both that the social sciences need to do a substantially better job of investigating and comprehending the experience of women and that social science knowledge depends on standards of empirical adequacy that are reasonably independent of one s prior convictions. And we had better hope that this is possible, if any of our critiques of the status quo are to have any warrant or intellectual conviction. Hollis, Martin. Reason in Action: Essays in the Philosophy of Social Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. ix, 283. $59.95 (cloth), $17.95 (paper). Ethics 1997 Martin Hollis has made significant contributions over many years to the theory of rationality and the role of this concept within the human sciences. Hollis s signal contribution is his persistent effort to bring these questions back to philosophy, and to locate the points of intersection between the theory of rationality and a host of important philosophical issues. Particularly important has been his continuing engagement with the topic of rationality and relativism roughly, the question of whether there may be profound differences in the mentality of persons within different cultures, and whether the assumption of individual rationality provides a legitimate lever for overcoming the potential incommensurability of systems of concepts and beliefs in different cultures. Readers will therefore find much to interest them in the essays included in Reason in Action. The essays in this volume were written over a period of almost thirty years; nonetheless, they show a remarkable level of consistency and coherence. The volume is organized around three themes: the concept of instrumental rationality as a theory of rationality in action; the relations between roles and reasons in human action; and the problem of other cultures, other minds. The first section discusses foundational issues in the theory of rationality: the problem of rational choice in the face of public goods ( Three Men in a Drought ), the problem of the formation of preferences ( Rational Preferences ), and the problem of strategic rationality ( Moves and Motives ). The problem of preferences is central to the theory of rational action. Given a set of preferences, the rational agent is one who chooses a line of action which maximizes the expected utility of the outcome. But what about the preference system itself? Are there any constraints imposed by reason on one s preferences? Are preferences truly exogenous? Or can one deliberate among 3

4 sets of preferences? Can one aim to change one s preferences? Hollis s general strategy is to recommend a broader conception of rational agency than the standard theory, by permitting rational agents to deliberate about their preferences; to adhere to moral commitments; and to adopt social identities that affect their choices. I want to loosen the usual tie between preferences, actions and outcomes by insisting that a rational agent has rational preferences (p. 54). To this reader the central section of the book is the most challenging and original. Here Hollis interrogates issues which contrast the notion of the rational actor as a transparent preference-maximizer, with the thicker notion of an actor as the bearer of an identity, a role, or a mask. On the first conception, agents have preferences and an ability to compare consequences of alternative courses of action; they then choose that course which has the prospect of producing the greatest expected utility. On the second conception, agents act out of complex identities which derive from their cultures, the roles they assume, and the masks they wear. Further, such actions are only partially deliberative and calculating. An interesting example which Hollis treats in several essays is the notion of a code of honor. Individuals sometimes appear to act out the implicatures of a code of honor which requires acts that are not narrowly prudent. How are we to understand this phenomenon within the context of a general theory of rational agency? Does the agent freely and autonomously choose the imprudent but honorable course? Is the agent programmed by an authoritative normative system? Has the agent adopted a role which compels his/her course of conduct? Hollis s discussion of these issues is richly informed by historical, anthropological, and literary evidence, and his observations take us to a deeper understanding of the complexities involved. In the third and final section of the book Hollis returns to the topic of cultural relativism and the related problem of the interpretation of the meaning of human conduct. Here he addresses the issue of cross-cultural rationality. In Reason and Ritual he confronts the issue of apparently irrational beliefs to which individuals in various cultures adhere. Here the central claim is that the ethnologist can only interpret the beliefs of members of the other culture if he/she is able to attribute shared standards of rationality to the other. The assumptions required for identifying everyday empirical beliefs are common perceptions, common ways of referring to things perceived and a common notion of empirical truth. Unless these assumptions work, the anthropologist cannot get a bridgehead (p. 210). In other words, we cannot maintain a radical relativism of conceptual system and modes of reasoning across cultures, and continue the project of interpreting other cultures. A similar point emerges in Say It With Flowers : in order to interpret an individual s motives in undertaking a given action, we need to know what the person has reason to do (p. 257), and this requires reference to a general and cross-person theory of rationality. The historian starts by trying an intellectual interpretation [of the actor s meaning] 4

5 and, even where only partial explanation results, will have determined what is missing. This is what is involved in making the actors out as rational as possible (p. 258). The final essay in the book combines themes in the second and third parts, by interpreting the fascinating example of Marcus Atilius Regulus, a Roman general in the First Punic War. Did Regulus act rationally in his decision to keep his oath and return to Carthage to face death by torture? How do reasons of honor figure within a general theory of rationality? And how are we to interpret the actions of persons motivated by honor? Hollis s conclusion is that we must find a way of incorporating principled action into our theory of practical rationality. In short, Reason in Action is a highly successful volume which will reward the attention of a wide audience of philosophers and social scientists. Hollis sheds important light on foundational problems in the human sciences through his developed discussion of issues of individual rationality, cross-cultural standards of rationality, and standards of interpretation of human action. Mohr, Lawrence B. The Causes of Human Behavior: Implications for Theory and Method in the Social Sciences. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Pp. ix, 183. $37.50 (cloth). American Journal of Sociology 1997 Lawrence Mohr, a political scientist with empirical research interests in organizations and organizational behavior, offers a practitioner s analysis of some fundamental philosophical issues in the foundations of the social sciences. Two questions loom particularly large for Mohr: What is involved in providing a good causal explanation of social phenomena, and in what sense are intentional human actions caused? These are important questions for those of us interested in the philosophy and methodology of the social sciences. Mohr s treatment, however, adds less to our understanding of these issues than one might hope. Causal explanation is the central topic. But in addition to an extended discussion of causation, the author provides an analysis of the causes of intentional behavior (do thoughts cause behavior?), an examination of some possible implications of the author s findings for research methodology, and a discussion of the relationship between explanation and law (chapter 5). Mohr argues that there are strong reasons to doubt in principle whether there could be strong law-like generalizations in the social sciences. This conclusion depends on the fact that social outcomes are the result both of causal processes and encounters chance circumstances that do not fall under lawlike generalizations (pp ). 5

6 Consider first Mohr s analysis of causation. Mohr argues that current philosophical treatments of causation are unsatisfactory, particularly for the social sciences. He summarizes these theories under a Humean regularity view and a necessary conditions view. In place of these theories, he argues for a pair of conceptions of causation: physical causation and factual causation. Physical causation, he believes, is the fundamental notion; it involves a relation between a force on an object and a motion of the same object (p. 44). More generally, physical causation is mechanical causation, in which the physical characteristics of the causing factor produce or bring about the characteristics of the effect. Mohr regards this as the bedrock causal concept, but observes that many causal ascriptions do not in fact refer to physical cause couples. Instead, many causal ascriptions refer to relations among statements or facts: the fact that the road was slick caused the fact that the accident occurred. This is what Mohr refers to as factual causation. Mohr defines factual causation in the following terms: X was the factual cause of Y if and only if X and Y both occurred and X occupied a necessary slot in the physical causal scenario pertinent to Y (p. 27). (Parenthetically, it does seem odd to call X the factual cause if it is merely one out of many necessary slots in the physical causal scenario.) In this reader s view, this analysis of causation fails to illuminate. There are very hard questions to be answered if we are to have a satisfactory analysis of social causation, but the retreat to physical causation seems not to be helpful in attempting to answer such questions. (Does it make sense to ask what was the physical cause of the fall of the Roman Empire?) There is a substantial literature within the philosophy of science on the issues of causation and causal explanation (for example, work by Wesley Salmon, Nancy Cartwright, or Jon Elster). Within the context of the current state of debate, Mohr s analysis of physical and factual causation appears unhelpful. Turn now to Mohr s treatment of the causation of behavior. He asks a simple question do thoughts (purposes, reasons, wishes, desires) cause behavior (physical movements of the body)? His answer is negative, because we sometimes decide to do X but fail to do so (the irregularity problem). The connection between our thought categories and the appropriate behaviors does not seem to be necessary or lawlike (p. 63). He argues that we should here take our cue from the analysis of physical causation that preceded, and look for a set of physical circumstances that could be said to cause behavior. Here the likely suspect is neurophysiology. Agents have brains, and brains are the causal background of behavior. Thus Mohr believes that it is necessary to identify the physiological mechanism that underlies the reason-behavior nexus if we are to have adequate causal explanations of behavior at all (p. 58), and he offers the affect-object paradigm as the basis of further theorizing in this area (p. 70). This is a highly speculative account of how desire and thought might be embodied within the central nervous system. Here we are in deep and troubled 6

7 waters, for it seems fairly clear that cognitive science and neurophysiology are still very far from having convincing answers to questions like what is the physiological basis of thought?. Fortunately, most other observers have concluded that the sort of inter-theoretic reduction that Mohr aspires to is in fact unnecessary. We can give satisfactory answers to questions like how do falling interest rates cause rising levels of investment? without having a neurophysiology of investor decision making. More generally, it is not necessary to reduce causal assertions at one level of description to causal relations at a lower level of description. In summary, Mohr deserves credit for focusing on a series of issues that are fundamental to our understanding of social research. Mohr s discussions of many of these issues ask some of the right questions, but his answers are often less than satisfying. Gilbert, Margaret. On Social Facts. Princeton University Press, Pp. x, 521, index. Cloth $69.50; paper $ International Studies in Philosophy 1995 This is an intelligent, closely argued and extensively analyzed treatment of the problem of social collectivity. What is a social group? What distinguishes a group from a random set of individuals e.g. the set consisting of W. V. O. Quine, Madonna, and Napoleon? Is a social class e.g. the English working class in the 1880s a social group? Gilbert s primary contention is that the notion of a collectivitity individuals constituting a group is the central feature of social ontology and the chief focus of empirical social science. And she maintains that this concept can best be analyzed by the idea of a plural subject the referent of the first-person plural pronoun, we. The core of Gilbert s theory of social groups involves the idea of the mutual recognition by a set of persons that they are engaged in some joint actions or beliefs. A set of people constitute a social group if and only if they constitute a plural subject ; and a plural subject is a set of people each of whom shares with oneself in some action, belief, attitude, or similar attribute (p. 204). Gilbert argues that the pronouns us and we are the linguistic elements through which we refer to plural subjects in English. And she believes that plural subjects exist; they are not fictions or constructions, but agents which have beliefs, perform actions, and succeed or fail in carrying out their intentions. In later chapters Gilbert extends her conception of collectivities and plural subjects by considering several other important social notions: the idea of a social fact in Durkheim s sense, the idea of a collective belief, and the idea of a social convention. In each case Gilbert argues that the concept of a plural subject 7

8 supports a plausible and intuitively convincing analysis of the social concept in question. According to Gilbert, social groups are plural subjects, collective beliefs are the beliefs of plural subjects, and social conventions are the fiats of plural subjects (p. 408). Gilbert s account of social conventions is developed through extensive discussion of David Lewis s influential formulation of this concept. Gilbert argues against the individualism of Max Weber (and by implication, the premises of rational choice theory), by arguing that collectivities are the central subject of the social sciences, and that collectivities cannot be subsumed under (narrowly) individualist concepts. Thus Gilbert suggests that her theory offers support for holism over individualism (p. 3). Does it? I think not. An individualist is free to acknowledge that individuals have beliefs that refer to other persons and groups of persons; the position permits reference to shared purposes and actions involving a collection of persons deliberately orienting their actions towards a shared purpose. What individualism requires is simply that these are all the aggregate results of individual states of mind, and that the behavior of the ensemble is to be explained by reference to the beliefs and intentions of the participants. An important test case for Gilbert s account is the problem of collective action. Rational choice theory places much emphasis on public goods problems and the phenomenon of free-riding. How does Gilbert s conception of plural subjects treat the problem? It appears to this reader that Gilbert makes collective action too easy. Plural subjects (groups) have purposes; individuals within these groups express quasi-readiness to perform their part of the shared action; and when circumstances are right the group acts collectively to bring about its collective goals. The people concerned would be jointly ready jointly to perform a certain action in certain circumstances (p. 409). She speaks of group will or communal will (p. 410). But the actions of a group are still the result of the choices made by constituent individuals. And however much the individual may align him- or herself with the collective project, the collective behavior is still no more than the sum of the actions taken by particular individuals. Moreover, it is necessary to acknowledge the endurance of private, individual interests that remain prominent for individual agents with the result that we should expect individuals actions to sometimes involve free-riding, defection, and favoring of private over collective interests. It seems to this reader, then, that Gilbert leans too far in the direction of the Rousseauvian general will interpretation of social action. How important for the social sciences is the notion of a social group or collectivity? Gilbert s view is that this concept is foundational; it is the basis for a unitary definition of the subject matter of the social sciences. This overstates the importance of collectivities, it seems to this reader: there are important instances of social explanation that do not involve analysis of groups in Gilbert s 8

9 sense, and whose explanatory frameworks do not refer to groups, their behavior, their shared beliefs, or their collective intentions and self-understandings. A few examples might include neo-malthusian analysis of the relation between economic change and demographic variables; analysis of the effects of changes of the transport system on patterns of settlement and economic activity; and explanation of patterns of historical processes of urbanization in terms of changing economic and political institutions. These examples explain social phenomena as the aggregate result of large numbers of rational individual actions. They commonly refer to impersonal social structures and circumstances that function as constraints and opportunities for individuals. And they make no inherent reference to the forms of group collectivity to which Gilbert refers. This is a rich book, and one that repays careful reading. It will be of particular interest to philosophers of social science and social philosophers, and the level of philosophical rigor will interest philosophers in other fields as well. Bunge, Mario. Finding Philosophy in Social Science. Yale University Press, Pp. xii, 432. $45.00 (cloth). American Journal of Sociology 1999 This is an ambitious book. Mario Bunge is an accomplished and learned philosopher who has written for decades on topics in the philosophy of science, metaphysics, and epistemology. In this work Bunge turns this erudition to the task of constructing a systematic philosophy of the social sciences from first principles. Moreover, he aims to produce a system that will be recognizable to practitioners as addressing conceptual and methodological issues that arise in their work. The results should be of substantial interest to philosophers and philosophically minded social scientists. Bunge offers a new, science-oriented philosophical system (12), within the context of which he looks to redesign the philosophy of social science. Philosophy of social science, according to Bunge, includes answers to questions in seven areas: logic, semantics, epistemology, methodology, ontology, axiology, and ethics. And the standards of evaluation for a proposed philosophy of social science are equally explicit: relevance, intelligibility, exactifiability, internal consistency, external consistency, size and depth, truth, universality, fertility, and originality (11). As this treatment suggests, Bunge brings a Cartesian exactness to his inquiry. His theorizing follows from an exacting analysis and classification of the problems to be considered. The book is organized into three parts: From Fact to Theory, From Explanation to Justification, and General Philosophical Problems in Social Science. The first part focuses on problems of explanation and theory. What is 9

10 a fact? What is a generalization? What is an explanation? Bunge puts it forward that the heart of explanation is systematization: the effort of the scientist to place a given fact within an orderly system or pattern (108 ff.). Systematization may proceed through classification (ranging individuals into groups or classes); more fundamentally, it may proceed through the construction of a theory whose concepts and hypotheses allow the scientist to place the given fact or state within a broader context of law-governed order. The treatment places the notion of nomothetic order at the center of the account. A fact is explained when it is placed within the context of a hypothetico-deductive system of laws and boundary conditions. It is worth noting that Bunge s account does not give much weight to the concept of social causation; his theory of explanation does not emphasize causal relations as a central basis of social explanation. Another central concern in Part A is the logic of scientific inquiry. What is involved in formulating a scientific research hypothesis? What is involved in asserting, or assessing, the truth of a hypothesis? How are scientific theories corrected and criticized? Bunge describes what he calls the methodics of science in these terms: the methodics of a scientific approach is constituted by all the relevant scrutable procedures: that is, all the rule-directed procedures that yield objective knowledge and can be justified theoretically as well as empirically (p. 80). Bunge regards scientific research as a process that is partially rule guided, but ultimately underdetermined by empirical constraints: data filtering and hypothesis formation depend on background assumptions that are not themselves empirically constrained at a particular moment in the history of science. Part B turns to a treatment of the epistemology of social science: the empirical and logical procedures through which scientific hypotheses and theories are tested or validated. Bunge s analysis displays an admirable confidence in the objectivity of science and the possibility of rationality and method in the social sciences. Throughout the author endeavors to establish the rational grounds of social science knowledge. A noteworthy discussion of upward and downward explanation of social facts occurs in Chapter 5. Here Bunge addresses issues that fall within the general framework of reductionism and methodological individualism; but he offers a clear, logically articulate account of the relations that obtain between higher-order theory and micro-level events. Bunge distinguishes between macro- and micro-facts in the following terms: A macro-fact is a fact occurring in the system as a whole. A micro-fact is a fact occurring in or to some or all of the members of the system at the given level (p. 147). He then distinguishes between top-down and bottom-up explanations: A top-down (or micro) explanation of a macro-fact is the deduction of the proposition(s) describing it from propositions describing (micro-) facts in components of the system where 10

11 the macro-fact occurs (147). A methodologically individualist explanation, then, is an instance of a top-down explanation in Bunge s parlance, as is an explanation of the properties of a cloud in terms of the properties of the water drops which compose it. Against both individualism and holism, Bunge maintains that adequate social explanation requires both kinds of systematization. Individuals constitute social facts; but individuals act within social contexts. Bunge refers to this alternative as systemism an approach to social explanation that identifies agents within structures as the unit of analysis (264). There are few traditional topics in the philosophy of the social sciences that do not find at least a few pages of discussion in this book. The topic of verstehen, for example apparently very distant from the logical positivist tone of much of the book receives brief but helpful treatment in Chapter 5. Bunge argues that there are two strands of thought underlying the verstehen methodology Dilthey and Weber and that Weber s rational motivation interpretation is the superior (154). An especially original contribution in this part of the book is Bunge s extensive and useful account of the epistemology of social indicators e.g. longevity as an indicator of quality of life. The discussion is interesting and original, and raises a topic not often discussed by philosophers, or by social scientists with the philosophical acuity which Bunge brings to the discussion (170 ff.). The general question is this: what are the epistemic features of an adequate social indicator? What conditions must a given indicator satisfy in order for us to be confident that the measure serves to indicate an underlying social characteristic? The topic is of importance because it constitutes the empirical link between theory and the social world in most instances: empirical observation in the social sciences depends on construction of indicators that permit the researcher to observe social phenomena poverty, social unrest, prejudice. But it is all too common in social science research that an investigator sets out to probe theoretical property X; asserts that observable property P indicates X; finds that P behaves thus-and-so; and concludes uncritically that X behaves thus-and-so. Before drawing such conclusions, however, it is crucial to establish the conditions of validity and veridicality which pertain to the relation between the indicator and the underlying social characteristic. In Part C Bunge turns to topics which have often been discussed under the rubric of philosophical problems raised by the social sciences (as opposed to philosophical frameworks which can be applied to the social sciences). Central among these problems are individualism and holism; idealism and materialism; subjectivism and realism; and the status of the assumption of rationality in social science explanations. Here again the careful reader will be repaid with ample philosophical insight into the problems Bunge treats. 11

12 As this survey indicates, Finding Philosophy in Social Science is an original and fruitful work. Bunge offers a systematic effort to apply contemporary philosophy of science to the logic of research in the social sciences, and he successfully identifies a handful of intriguing philosophical problems raised by contemporary social science research. Barnes, Barry. The Elements of Social Theory. Barry Barnes. Princeton University Press, p. $29.95 cloth. Giddens, Anthony. Politics, Sociology and Social Theory: Encounters with Classical and Contemporary Social Thought. Stanford: Stanford University Press, p. $45.00 cloth, $16.95 paper. American Political Science Review 1996 These two recent books, both by respected social theorists, offer a valuable look at the development of classical social theory since the middle nineteenth century and its relevance at the end of the twentieth century. In the final years of the twentieth century, it is highly pertinent to ask whether social theorizing largely produced before the end of the nineteenth century can possibly serve to illuminate contemporary society. (By classical social theory these authors mean roughly the theories of Marx, Durkheim, and Weber, along with subsequent elaborations and criticisms of these theories.) Are the classics of social theory of continuing relevance for our own attempts to understand and explain important social processes? Or have events and ideas superseded them? Giddens and Barnes have each done deep and important work on the traditions of social theory, so one reads these books with interest and high expectation. The books are highly complementary, in that Giddens provides a thoughtful historical discussion of the traditions of social theory, while Barnes offers a developed account of how the currents of this tradition ought to be deployed in contemporary social theorizing. Barnes wishes to provide a synthesis of an adequate social theory, taking account of the theoretical insights of classical social theory as well as well-developed criticisms of those theories. There are several foundational questions to raise in the context of the topic of these books. What is the intellectual role of social theory? And how should the micro-macro problem be handled in good social research what is the relationship between the individual level and the social level in social processes, structures, and functions? Barnes offers one possible answer to the first question in the first sentence of his book: The most widely read theories are those that serve as the basis for commentary on the nature of present-day industrial societies and on how they are likely to develop and change (1). Later he writes, 12

13 The formulation of links and connections between particulars is what theorizing is (2). This is to say, evidently, that theory serves to identify the generalized processes which underlie specific social occurrences. Barnes takes explicit issue with what is sometimes referred to as the toolbox model of social theory: that social theory identifies a range of distinct social processes and mechanisms, and that the empirical researcher should be broadly acquainted with these theoretical alternatives and choose the theory that best fits the empirical problem that she is currently studying. Against this view, Barnes argues for theoretical unity (33). It bears saying, however, that it may be that social phenomena are in fact diverse, deriving from a number of non-reducible causal processes. In this case, one would be best advised to the more eclectic or pluralistic view of the role of theory. If the social world is causally diverse, then there will be no grand unification theory possible in the social sciences. A similarly foundational question focuses on the social in social theory: what is involved in asserting that human beings are social beings? Barnes is at pains to question a broadly individualist answer to this question, according to which social institutions constrain and impel rational individuals who are defined independent from social facts. He argues instead for the irreducibility of the social. (It might be noted that Barnes s critique does not merely apply to rational choice theorists; he believes that there is a pernicious individualism lying at the foundation of Parsonian sociology as well; pp. 54 ff.) Against these individualistic social theories, Barnes stresses that we must understand individuals as thoroughly socialized: their motives, beliefs, norms, inhibitions, and conceptions of themselves and their relations to others, are thoroughly imprecated in social facts and circumstances. As Barnes puts it, to insist that we are social creatures and to treat this as a matter of profound and pervasive significance is to announce a strongly anti-individualistic sociological theory (4). He gives substantial attention to a number of social concepts: norms, groups, movements, practices, knowledge, class, and hierarchy. And he aims to persuade readers that an acceptable social theory will be one which gives full recognition to the supra-individual properties that such concepts invoke. Barnes appears to believe that familiar problems of suboptimality of rational individual choice in circumstances of interactive action freerider problems and prisoner s dilemma problems indicate a defect in the theory of individual rationality. But it is surely no critique of evolutionary theory to demonstrate that suboptimal adaptations may emerge through natural selection; it is rather a feature of the world that evolutionary theory discerns and explains. Likewise, the fact that rational individuals when placed in a one-time prisoner s dilemma situation will choose strategies that lead to a predictable suboptimal equilibrium does not refute the theory of economic rationality; it indicates only that individual rationality does not always lead to collective optimality. 13

14 Barnes believes that an appropriately constructed theory of the social individual permits a solution to the collective action problem (4, 76-85). Barnes is right in focusing on collective action as a theoretically central problem for the social sciences. But it is a problem for all stripes of social theory, not merely rational choice theory. It is true that unadorned rational choice theory predicts too little collective action. But a lavishly social theory of collective action surely predicts too much collective action. The assumption of social behavior (that is, behavior oriented toward group purposes) makes the problem of collective action too easy. If individuals always choose to act according to their assessment of collective interests, strikes should never collapse, revolutions should never fail, and ground water sources should never be polluted. Barnes gives substantial attention to the topic of social norms: What is involved in an individual following a norm? He writes, Conforming to norms is a collective activity (57). More broadly, Barnes maintains that the phenomenon of normative action gives strong support to the anti-individualist methodology that he favors. This position is unpersuasive, however, in that it appears relatively simple to provide microfoundations for the fact that individuals are influenced by norms, practices, and worldviews that extend beyond their own psychological states. To put it crudely, the Parsonian model of the internalization of norms that Barnes criticizes appears to be more credible than Barnes s own account. In general, this reader judges that Barnes overestimates the difficulties of framing an empirically adequate individualist (or microfoundational) theory of norms and institutions. In sum, Barnes s book repays close study. He is a thoughtful commentator on foundational questions in the social sciences, and even if one ultimately disagrees with his position, the reader will learn much from his discussion of these topics. Turn now to the Giddens volume. This collection of previously published essays provides a fine discussion and commentary on the main contributors to classical social theory Marx, Weber, Durkheim, Comte, and Parsons, and a suggestive reflection on more recent social theorists Garfinkel, Habermas, Foucault, and Nietzsche. Giddens has much of interest to say about the development of social theory and sociology over the past century and a half. Giddens himself is a distinguished contributor to this tradition, so his discussion will be sure to interest many readers. The heart of classical social theory is the trio of Marx, Durkheim, and Weber. Giddens takes pains to scrutinize the routes by which the thought of these thinkers made its way into the English-speaking world of social theory and sociology. Giddens treatment of Weber is particularly thorough and useful; he makes a sustained effort to explore the connections between Weber s intellectual development and the social and political circumstances in which he found himself in Wilhelmine Germany, through an analysis of Weber s political 14

15 writings. Giddens also provides a nuanced discussion of the relationship between Marx and Weber (chapter 2). Here the issue largely concerns the status of historical materialism as an explanatory framework. Giddens argues that Marx and Weber in fact shared a good deal of common ground concerning their interpretations of Roman history and pre-capitalist forms of economy and society (pp ). (Refreshingly, Giddens also defends the view that Marx remains a classical social theorist, with important contributions to make to our understanding of the dynamics of modern capitalist society and economy, in spite of the collapse of communism.) Durkheim s thought is reconsidered through the lens of his political sociology. Giddens takes the view that other readers have given too little attention to Durkheim s efforts to make sense of forms of authority in modern society. This concept cuts across typically sociological discussions of order with political discussions of power. Durkheim is most commonly associated with the regulative authority of norms and of organizations of civil society, but Giddens argues that there is equally a concern for the exercise of the coercive power of the state ( ). Giddens offers the summary assessment: Durkheim s sociology had its origins in an attempt to reinterpret the claims of political liberalism in the face of a twin challenge: from an anti-rationalist conservatism on the one hand, and from socialism on the other (115). Giddens also provides an extended discussion of Durkheim s relationship to individualism. Durkheim is plainly hostile to methodological individualism as a principle of sociological explanation; less well understood is his relation to moral individualism. In Giddens telling of the tale, moral individualism is, according to Durkheim, a defining characteristic of modern Western social life. Respect for the individual, and the concomitant demand for equality, became moral imperatives: as such, they implied that the welfare and self-fulfillment of every member should be sought after (pp ). In a central essay in the volume, Comte, Popper and Positivism, Giddens gives an historical treatment of the development of the philosophy of science in relation to sociology. The general framework of the chapter is a careful and developed analysis of positivism as a conception of the methodology of the social sciences. Tracing the concept from Comte through the Vienna school philosophers (Schlick, Neurath, Carnap, and Hahn, for example), to the logical empiricism of Hempel, Oppenheimer, and Nagel, Giddens carefully works through the relationships between philosophical debates about positivism and the development of empirical sociology. This discussion sheds much light on the profound impact which logical positivism had on the formation of sociological thought and method. This chapter by itself would serve as an admirable introduction to the philosophy of science for graduate students in the social sciences. 15

16 The final few chapters offer discussion of several important contributors to social theory in the twentieth century Habermas, Marcuse, Garfinkel, and Foucault. These essays have the feeling of occasion pieces rather than fully developed analysis, but each essay provides some insight into the subject at hand. In sum, each of these books must be counted at an important contribution to contemporary discussions of social theory. Giddens book shows a remarkable erudition in the full range of social theory. Giddens offers insight into the logic of the views he discusses, as well as the complicated relations which obtain among them. The book will appeal as strongly to readers who know a good deal about these traditions as it will to the novice. The Barnes book has a distinctive point of view, and makes a substantive case for a particular approach to social theory. Some readers will find this approach highly congenial to their own work, and others will not. But all will be stimulated by Barnes s capable argumentation and exposition of the issues. Barnes and Giddens each give evidence to what is surely true: that the traditions of classical social theory continue to provide insight into modern society. Hands, D. Wade. Testing, Rationality, and Progress: Essays on the Popperian Tradition in Economic Methodology. Lanham, Maryland, Pp $40.00 (cloth). Ethics 1994 This book is a thoughtful, sustained reflection on the suitability of the methodological ideas of Karl Popper and Imre Lakatos in application to the history of economics. As Hands notes, Popper and Lakatos have been the philosophers of science who have had the greatest influence on methodologically minded economists. Wade Hands is himself a methodologically sophisticated economist, and he does a fine job of bridging between current work in philosophy of science and the methodological debates that have occurred within the economics profession in the past fifteen years. The central themes of the book are these: Is it useful to consider whether economic theories are falsifiable? And can we understand the development of economic thought within the framework of Lakatos s theory of progressive research programs? Hands is in general rather skeptical about the utility of either Popper s falsifiability criterion (pps. 67 ff.) or Lakatos s more complex criteria of novelty and progressivity (pp ) as a basis for evaluating economic thought and theory. Particularly useful are the author s efforts to consider various methodological maxims in light of specific episodes in recent economic thought. The book is a valuable contribution to the growing literature in the philosophy of economics. 16

17 Gordon, Scott. The History and Philosophy of Social Science. Routledge, London, Pp. x, 668, index, $ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 1994 It is difficult to characterize the genre of The History and Philosophy of Social Science. The book contains much discussion of many of the great texts and authors in the history of the social sciences Marx, Spencer, Comte, Durkheim, Weber, Bentham and yet it is not really a developed history of the social sciences. It is interspersed with discussions of problems of methodology in the social science the role of laws in social science, the role of modeling, the concepts of progress and order in social theory, the logical character of social and historical explanation and yet it is something less than a coherent exposition of a theory of the philosophy of social science. It is too long and intricate to be a popular exposition of social theory; and yet it is underdocumented for a scholarly contribution. And finally, it is a dense scholarly book that contains neither footnotes nor bibliography. (Books and articles are referred to only by title and date, internal to the text.) The reader is thus left with a sense of puzzlement about the audience the author has in mind. I can think of only one group: beginning graduate students in social philosophy or political science who want to get a preliminary synopsis of the historical development of the social sciences. This is a book of almost 700 pages, treating a great variety of topics. So it is perhaps useful to begin by offering a recital of some of the themes Gordon raises: problematic social concepts society, science, progress, order (chapters 1, 2, 8, 10) philosophy of social science themes (chapters 3, 14, 18) history of economics and political economy (chapters 5, 6, 9, 17) history of social theory (chapters 11, 12, 13, 15) history of political theory (chapters 4, 7) biology and social science (chapter 16) Given the length of the book, it is impossible to summarize or evaluate all the main points. So a reviewer may perhaps be permitted to turn to a venerable social science technique: sampling. History of the social sciences. Most of the book falls generally within the history of the social sciences. The author provides an exposition of the central ideas of an imposing list of figures in the history of the social sciences broadly construed. The breadth of knowledge represented is impressive; Gordon writes with confidence on subjects as diverse as Montesquieu s interpretation of the 17

18 English Constitution (pp. 82 ff.), Plato s account of the division of labor (pp. 59 ff.), and Comte s stages of human evolution (pp. 292 ff.). Most subjects are treated with a broad brush, however: a quick review of the philosophical precursors, a brief account of the intellectual environment, and an account of the theoretical ideas. Most satisfactory and substantive is Gordon s exposition of the history of political economy. About 300 pages are devoted to this topic (dispersed over non-consecutive chapters). Gordon provides fairly detailed exposition of the main stages of development of political economy since the seventeenth century: the evolution of classical political economy (Quesnay, Smith, Malthus, Ricardo); Marxist economic theory; the marginalist revolution (Marshall, Pareto); and the Keynsian revolution. It is disappointing, however, that few substantive connections are made between developments in the history of political economy and the other historical topics discussed. Thus Gordon s exposition of the history of economics as a discipline is essentially free-standing within the book, and one is tempted to think that this material would have been better published separately in a volume devoted to the topic. At the same time, it should be noted that there are already reasonably authoritative books available on this topic: Joseph Schumpeter s magisterial History of Economic Analysis (Oxford, 1954) and Mark Blaug s Economic Theory in Retrospect (Irwin, 1968). Gordon offers little on the history of political economy that could not be found in these two books. The next largest topic treated by Gordon is the history of sociology and social theory: Spencer, Marx, Durkheim, and Weber, as well as a number of lesser figures. Spencer, Durkheim, and Weber each receive exposition of about 25 pages, while Marx s sociology and economics are treated together in a separate chapter of greater length. The exposition is brief but adequate; Gordon identifies and explains the central ideas of each author fairly clearly and accurately. As is the case in the history of political economy, there already exist a number of standard books on the history and development of sociology and social theory. A History of Sociological Analysis, edited by Tom Bottomore and Robert Nisbet (Basic, 1978), covers the history of sociology in perhaps more insightful terms. And Raymond Aron s Main Currents in Sociological Thought (Basic, 1965) is a coherent and insightful treatment of the full range of its subject. It is not obvious that Gordon s book has added much to the existing literature in this area. Least satisfactory is Gordon s treatment of the history of political theory. Much of his discussion falls in the domain of political philosophy. In a chapter on political theory and political philosophy (chapter 4) Gordon offers a discussion of the political theories of Plato, Hobbes, Locke, and Montesquieu; later chapters present the thought of Hume and Smith (chapter 7), and Mill (chapter 11). Much of this material is fairly distant from Gordon s own 18

MAIN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ISSUES IN THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

MAIN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ISSUES IN THE SOCIAL SCIENCES Tosini Syllabus Main Epistemological Issues in Social Sciences (2017/2018) Page 1 of 7 University of Trento School of Social Sciences PhD Program in Sociology and Social Research 2017/2018 MAIN EPISTEMOLOGICAL

More information

National identity and global culture

National identity and global culture National identity and global culture Michael Marsonet, Prof. University of Genoa Abstract It is often said today that the agreement on the possibility of greater mutual understanding among human beings

More information

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh

Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice as public reasoning and the capability approach. Reiko Gotoh Welfare theory, public action and ethical values: Re-evaluating the history of welfare economics in the twentieth century Backhouse/Baujard/Nishizawa Eds. Economic philosophy of Amartya Sen Social choice

More information

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis Eastern Economic Journal 2018, 44, (491 495) Ó 2018 EEA 0094-5056/18 www.palgrave.com/journals COLANDER'S ECONOMICS WITH ATTITUDE On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis Middlebury College,

More information

International Relations. Policy Analysis

International Relations. Policy Analysis 128 International Relations and Foreign Policy Analysis WALTER CARLSNAES Although foreign policy analysis (FPA) has traditionally been one of the major sub-fields within the study of international relations

More information

Note: Principal version Equivalence list Modification Complete version from 1 October 2014 Master s Programme Sociology: Social and Political Theory

Note: Principal version Equivalence list Modification Complete version from 1 October 2014 Master s Programme Sociology: Social and Political Theory Note: The following curriculum is a consolidated version. It is legally non-binding and for informational purposes only. The legally binding versions are found in the University of Innsbruck Bulletins

More information

Review of Roger E. Backhouse s The puzzle of modern economics: science or ideology? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, 214 pp.

Review of Roger E. Backhouse s The puzzle of modern economics: science or ideology? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, 214 pp. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 4, Issue 1, Spring 2011, pp. 83-87. http://ejpe.org/pdf/4-1-br-1.pdf Review of Roger E. Backhouse s The puzzle of modern economics: science or ideology?

More information

Review of Law and Social Process in United States History, By James Willard Hurst

Review of Law and Social Process in United States History, By James Willard Hurst Washington University Law Review Volume 1961 Issue 2 1961 Review of Law and Social Process in United States History, By James Willard Hurst Lewis R. Mills Follow this and additional works at: http://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_lawreview

More information

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents

Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 4, Issue 2, Autumn 2011, pp. 117-122. http://ejpe.org/pdf/4-2-br-8.pdf Review of Christian List and Philip Pettit s Group agency: the possibility, design,

More information

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017)

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017) MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017) This document is meant to give students and potential applicants a better insight into the curriculum of the program. Note that where information

More information

Chapter 1 Sociological Theory Chapter Summary

Chapter 1 Sociological Theory Chapter Summary Chapter 1 Sociological Theory Chapter Summary Like most textbooks, Chapter 1 is designed to introduce you to the history and founders of sociology (called theorists) who have shaped our understanding and

More information

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1 András Szigeti Linköping University andras.szigeti@liu.se Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1 If you have ever had to move

More information

Western Philosophy of Social Science

Western Philosophy of Social Science Western Philosophy of Social Science Lecture 7. Marx's Capital as a social science Professor Daniel Little University of Michigan-Dearborn delittle@umd.umich.edu www-personal.umd.umich.edu/~delittle/ Does

More information

RESEARCH METHODOLOGY IN POLITICAL SCIENCE STUDY NOTES CHAPTER ONE

RESEARCH METHODOLOGY IN POLITICAL SCIENCE STUDY NOTES CHAPTER ONE RESEARCH METHODOLOGY IN POLITICAL SCIENCE STUDY NOTES 0 1 2 INTRODUCTION CHAPTER ONE Politics is about power. Studying the distribution and exercise of power is, however, far from straightforward. Politics

More information

Power: Interpersonal, Organizational, and Global Dimensions Wednesday, 14 September 2005

Power: Interpersonal, Organizational, and Global Dimensions Wednesday, 14 September 2005 Power: Interpersonal, Organizational, and Global Dimensions Wednesday, 14 September 2005 TOPIC: continue elaborating definition of power as capacity to produce intended and foreseen effects on others.

More information

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague E-LOGOS ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN 1211-0442 1/2010 University of Economics Prague Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals e Alexandra Dobra

More information

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process TED VAGGALIS University of Kansas The tragic truth about philosophy is that misunderstanding occurs more frequently than understanding. Nowhere

More information

Course Title. Professor. Contact Information

Course Title. Professor. Contact Information Course Title History of economic Thought Course Level L3 / M1 Graduate / Undergraduate Domain Management Language English Nb. Face to Face Hours 36 (3hrs. sessions) plus 1 exam of 3 hours for a total of

More information

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions Socio-Legal Course Descriptions Updated 12/19/2013 Required Courses for Socio-Legal Studies Major: PLSC 1810: Introduction to Law and Society This course addresses justifications and explanations for regulation

More information

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes * Crossroads ISSN 1825-7208 Vol. 6, no. 2 pp. 87-95 Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes In 1974 Steven Lukes published Power: A radical View. Its re-issue in 2005 with the addition of two new essays

More information

NTNU, Trondheim Fall 2003

NTNU, Trondheim Fall 2003 INSTITUTIONS AND INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN Erling Berge Part X: Design principles I NTNU, Trondheim Fall 2003 30-10-2003 Erling Berge 2003 1 References Institutions and their design, pages 1-53 in Goodin, Robert

More information

Chapter 1: Theoretical Approaches to Global Politics

Chapter 1: Theoretical Approaches to Global Politics Chapter 1: Theoretical Approaches to Global Politics I. Introduction A. What is theory and why do we need it? B. Many theories, many meanings C. Levels of analysis D. The Great Debates: an introduction

More information

Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. Cloth $35.

Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. Cloth $35. Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006. 416 pp. Cloth $35. John S. Ahlquist, University of Washington 25th November

More information

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi REVIEW Clara Brandi We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Terry Macdonald, Global Stakeholder Democracy. Power and Representation Beyond Liberal States, Oxford, Oxford University

More information

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Abstract: This paper develops a unique exposition about the relationship between facts and principles in political

More information

Course Descriptions 1201 Politics: Contemporary Issues 1210 Political Ideas: Isms and Beliefs 1220 Political Analysis 1230 Law and Politics

Course Descriptions 1201 Politics: Contemporary Issues 1210 Political Ideas: Isms and Beliefs 1220 Political Analysis 1230 Law and Politics Course Descriptions 1201 Politics: Contemporary Issues This course explores the multi-faceted nature of contemporary politics, and, in so doing, introduces students to various aspects of the Political

More information

Max Weber. SOCL/ANTH 302: Social Theory. Monday, March 26, by Ronald Keith Bolender

Max Weber. SOCL/ANTH 302: Social Theory. Monday, March 26, by Ronald Keith Bolender Max Weber 1 SOCL/ANTH 302: Social Theory Background http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=tbmndjzheei&feature=fvst Born in Thuringia, Germany (1864) Eldest of eight children Weber was a sickly child Suffered

More information

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE

POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE POLI 111: INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF POLITICAL SCIENCE SESSION 4 NATURE AND SCOPE OF POLITICAL SCIENCE Lecturer: Dr. Evans Aggrey-Darkoh, Department of Political Science Contact Information: aggreydarkoh@ug.edu.gh

More information

Detailed Contents. The European Roots of Sociological Theory 1

Detailed Contents. The European Roots of Sociological Theory 1 Detailed Contents Preface xxi A Note to Students xxvii S E C T I O N I The European Roots of Sociological Theory 1 1 The Origins of Sociological Theory 3 The Contours of Sociological Theory 4 Deductive

More information

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights Part 1 Understanding Human Rights 2 Researching and studying human rights: interdisciplinary insight Damien Short Since 1948, the study of human rights has been dominated by legal scholarship that has

More information

SAMPLE CHAPTERS UNESCO EOLSS POWER AND THE STATE. John Scott Department of Sociology, University of Plymouth, UK

SAMPLE CHAPTERS UNESCO EOLSS POWER AND THE STATE. John Scott Department of Sociology, University of Plymouth, UK POWER AND THE STATE John Department of Sociology, University of Plymouth, UK Keywords: counteraction, elite, pluralism, power, state. Contents 1. Power and domination 2. States and state elites 3. Counteraction

More information

Individualism. Marquette University. John B. Davis Marquette University,

Individualism. Marquette University. John B. Davis Marquette University, Marquette University e-publications@marquette Economics Faculty Research and Publications Economics, Department of 1-1-2009 John B. Davis Marquette University, john.davis@marquette.edu Published version.

More information

Chapter 1 Understanding Sociology. Introduction to Sociology Spring 2010

Chapter 1 Understanding Sociology. Introduction to Sociology Spring 2010 Chapter 1 Understanding Sociology Introduction to Sociology Spring 2010 Define sociology as a social science. Sociology is the scientific study of social behavior and human groups. It focuses on social

More information

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1. Introduction There are two sets of questions that have featured prominently in recent debates about distributive justice. One of these debates is that between universalism

More information

changes in the global environment, whether a shifting distribution of power (Zakaria

changes in the global environment, whether a shifting distribution of power (Zakaria Legitimacy dilemmas in global governance Review by Edward A. Fogarty, Department of Political Science, Colgate University World Rule: Accountability, Legitimacy, and the Design of Global Governance. By

More information

REALIST LAWYERS AND REALISTIC LEGALISTS: A BRIEF REBUTTAL TO JUDGE POSNER

REALIST LAWYERS AND REALISTIC LEGALISTS: A BRIEF REBUTTAL TO JUDGE POSNER REALIST LAWYERS AND REALISTIC LEGALISTS: A BRIEF REBUTTAL TO JUDGE POSNER MICHAEL A. LIVERMORE As Judge Posner an avowed realist notes, debates between realism and legalism in interpreting judicial behavior

More information

APPROACHES & THEORIES IN POLITICAL SCIENCE

APPROACHES & THEORIES IN POLITICAL SCIENCE Syllabus APPROACHES & THEORIES IN POLITICAL SCIENCE - 56865 Last update 02-08-2016 HU Credits: 4 Degree/Cycle: 2nd degree (Master) Responsible Department: political science Academic year: 0 Semester: 2nd

More information

Public and Academic History: a Philosophy and Paradigm

Public and Academic History: a Philosophy and Paradigm The Annals of Iowa Volume 51 Number 4 (Spring 1992) pps. 428-430 Public and Academic History: a Philosophy and Paradigm ISSN 0003-4827 Copyright 1992 State Historical Society of Iowa. This article is posted

More information

Student Text Student Practice Book Activities and Projects

Student Text Student Practice Book Activities and Projects English Language Arts III Correlation with TEKS 110.39. English Language Arts and Reading, English IV (One Credit), Adopted 2017. Knowledge and skills. Student Text Student Practice Book Activities and

More information

Social Capital and Social Movements

Social Capital and Social Movements East Carolina University From the SelectedWorks of Bob Edwards 2013 Social Capital and Social Movements Bob Edwards, East Carolina University Available at: https://works.bepress.com/bob_edwards/11/ Social

More information

1100 Ethics July 2016

1100 Ethics July 2016 1100 Ethics July 2016 perhaps, those recommended by Brock. His insight that this creates an irresolvable moral tragedy, given current global economic circumstances, is apt. Blake does not ask, however,

More information

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction

POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, The history of democratic theory II Introduction POL 343 Democratic Theory and Globalization February 11, 2005 "The history of democratic theory II" Introduction Why, and how, does democratic theory revive at the beginning of the nineteenth century?

More information

WIKIPEDIA IS NOT A GOOD ENOUGH SOURCE FOR AN ACADEMIC ASSIGNMENT

WIKIPEDIA IS NOT A GOOD ENOUGH SOURCE FOR AN ACADEMIC ASSIGNMENT Understanding Society Lecture 1 What is Sociology (29/2/16) What is sociology? the scientific study of human life, social groups, whole societies, and the human world as a whole the systematic study of

More information

A Brief History of the Council

A Brief History of the Council A Brief History of the Council By Kenneth Prewitt, former president Notes on the Origin of the Council We start, appropriately enough, at the beginning, with a few informal comments on the earliest years

More information

Lecture 11 Sociology 621 February 22, 2017 RATIONALITY, SOLIDARITY AND CLASS STRUGGLE

Lecture 11 Sociology 621 February 22, 2017 RATIONALITY, SOLIDARITY AND CLASS STRUGGLE Lecture 11 Sociology 621 February 22, 2017 RATIONALITY, SOLIDARITY AND CLASS STRUGGLE Solidarity as an Element in Class Formation Solidarity is one of the pivotal aspects of class formation, particularly

More information

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics

Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics Chapter Two: Normative Theories of Ethics This multimedia product and its contents are protected under copyright law. The following are prohibited by law: any public performance or display, including transmission

More information

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.). S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: 0-674-01029-9 (hbk.). In this impressive, tightly argued, but not altogether successful book,

More information

FRED S. MCCHESNEY, Northwestern University, Chicago, IL 60611, U.S.A.

FRED S. MCCHESNEY, Northwestern University, Chicago, IL 60611, U.S.A. 185 thinking of the family in terms of covenant relationships will suggest ways for laws to strengthen ties among existing family members. To the extent that modern American law has become centered on

More information

How to approach legitimacy

How to approach legitimacy How to approach legitimacy for the book project Empirical Perspectives on the Legitimacy of International Investment Tribunals Daniel Behn, 1 Ole Kristian Fauchald 2 and Malcolm Langford 3 January 2015

More information

Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy with Aristotle s. Political Philosophy

Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy with Aristotle s. Political Philosophy Original Paper Urban Studies and Public Administration Vol. 1, No. 1, 2018 www.scholink.org/ojs/index.php/uspa ISSN 2576-1986 (Print) ISSN 2576-1994 (Online) Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy

More information

Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ix pp. $19.95 (cloth).

Philosophy and Real Politics, by Raymond Geuss. Princeton: Princeton University Press, ix pp. $19.95 (cloth). NOTE: this is the final MS, before copy-editing, of Patchen Markell, review of Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics, published in Political Theory 38, no. 1 (February 2010): 172 77. 2010 SAGE Publications.

More information

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating Tanja Pritzlaff email: t.pritzlaff@zes.uni-bremen.de webpage: http://www.zes.uni-bremen.de/homepages/pritzlaff/index.php

More information

Economic Sociology I Fall Kenneth Boulding, The Role of Mathematics in Economics, JPE, 56 (3) 1948: 199

Economic Sociology I Fall Kenneth Boulding, The Role of Mathematics in Economics, JPE, 56 (3) 1948: 199 Economic Sociology I Fall 2018 It may be that today the greatest danger is from the other side. The mathematicians themselves set up standards of generality and elegance in their expositions which are

More information

Rethinking critical realism: Labour markets or capitalism?

Rethinking critical realism: Labour markets or capitalism? Rethinking critical realism 125 Rethinking critical realism: Labour markets or capitalism? Ben Fine Earlier debate on critical realism has suggested the need for it to situate itself more fully in relation

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

Book Review: The Calligraphic State: Conceptualizing the Study of Society Through Law

Book Review: The Calligraphic State: Conceptualizing the Study of Society Through Law Drexel University Thomas R. Kline School of Law From the SelectedWorks of Tabatha Abu El-Haj 2003 Book Review: The Calligraphic State: Conceptualizing the Study of Society Through Law Tabatha Abu El-Haj

More information

ANALYSIS OF SOCIOLOGY MAINS Question Papers ( PAPER I ) - TEAM VISION IAS

ANALYSIS OF SOCIOLOGY MAINS Question Papers ( PAPER I ) - TEAM VISION IAS VISION IAS www.visionias.wordpress.com www.visionias.cfsites.org www.visioniasonline.com ANALYSIS OF SOCIOLOGY MAINS Question Papers 2000-2005 ( PAPER I ) - TEAM VISION IAS Q.No. Question Topics Subtopics

More information

Are Asian Sociologies Possible? Universalism versus Particularism

Are Asian Sociologies Possible? Universalism versus Particularism 192 Are Asian Sociologies Possible? Universalism versus Particularism, Tohoku University, Japan The concept of social capital has been attracting social scientists as well as politicians, policy makers,

More information

Theories of the Historical Development of American Schooling

Theories of the Historical Development of American Schooling Theories of the Historical Development of American Schooling by David F. Labaree Graduate School of Education 485 Lasuen Mall Stanford University Stanford, CA 94305-3096 E-mail: dlabaree@stanford.edu Web:

More information

The uses and abuses of evolutionary theory in political science: a reply to Allan McConnell and Keith Dowding

The uses and abuses of evolutionary theory in political science: a reply to Allan McConnell and Keith Dowding British Journal of Politics and International Relations, Vol. 2, No. 1, April 2000, pp. 89 94 The uses and abuses of evolutionary theory in political science: a reply to Allan McConnell and Keith Dowding

More information

POLITICS AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS

POLITICS AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS POLITICS AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 2013-2014 Catalog POLITICS MAJOR 11 courses distributed as follows: POLI 100 Issues in Politics MATH 215 Statistical Analysis POLI 400 Research Methods POLI 497 Senior

More information

2. Realism is important to study because it continues to guide much thought regarding international relations.

2. Realism is important to study because it continues to guide much thought regarding international relations. Chapter 2: Theories of World Politics TRUE/FALSE 1. A theory is an example, model, or essential pattern that structures thought about an area of inquiry. F DIF: High REF: 30 2. Realism is important to

More information

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D 25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY Frankfurt am Main 15 20 August 2011 Paper Series No. 055 / 2012 Series D History of Philosophy; Hart, Kelsen, Radbruch, Habermas, Rawls; Luhmann; General

More information

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI)

POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI) POLITICAL SCIENCE (POLI) This is a list of the Political Science (POLI) courses available at KPU. For information about transfer of credit amongst institutions in B.C. and to see how individual courses

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Theory and the Levels of Analysis

Theory and the Levels of Analysis Theory and the Levels of Analysis Chapter 3 Ø Not be frightened by the word theory Ø Definitions of theory: p A theory is a proposition, or set of propositions, that tries to analyze, explain or predict

More information

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at: ABSTRACT By tracing the development and evolvement of certain legal theories over the centuries, as well as consequences emanating from such developments, this paper highlights how and why a shift from

More information

Chapter II European integration and the concept of solidarity

Chapter II European integration and the concept of solidarity Chapter II European integration and the concept of solidarity The current chapter is devoted to the concept of solidarity and its role in the European integration discourse. The concept of solidarity applied

More information

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG SYMPOSIUM POLITICAL LIBERALISM VS. LIBERAL PERFECTIONISM POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG JOSEPH CHAN 2012 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 2, No. 1 (2012): pp.

More information

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts) primarysourcedocument Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical, Excerpts John Rawls 1985 [Rawls, John. Justice As Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14, no. 3.

More information

HISTORICAL AND INSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS IN ECONOMICS

HISTORICAL AND INSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS IN ECONOMICS HISTORICAL AND INSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS IN ECONOMICS THE CASE OF ANALYTIC NARRATIVES Cyril Hédoin University of Reims Champagne-Ardenne (France) Interdisciplinary Symposium - Track interdisciplinarity in

More information

Enlightenment of Hayek s Institutional Change Idea on Institutional Innovation

Enlightenment of Hayek s Institutional Change Idea on Institutional Innovation International Conference on Education Technology and Economic Management (ICETEM 2015) Enlightenment of Hayek s Institutional Change Idea on Institutional Innovation Juping Yang School of Public Affairs,

More information

Ideology COLIN J. BECK

Ideology COLIN J. BECK Ideology COLIN J. BECK Ideology is an important aspect of social and political movements. The most basic and commonly held view of ideology is that it is a system of multiple beliefs, ideas, values, principles,

More information

Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question *

Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate on an Old Question * RMM Vol. 4, 2013, 39 43 Special Topic: Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? http://www.rmm-journal.de/ Bernd Lahno Can the Social Contract Be Signed by an Invisible Hand? A New Debate

More information

Programme Specification

Programme Specification Programme Specification Title: Social Policy and Sociology Final Award: Bachelor of Arts with Honours (BA (Hons)) With Exit Awards at: Certificate of Higher Education (CertHE) Diploma of Higher Education

More information

The Global Constitutional Canon: Some Preliminary Thoughts. Peter E. Quint (Maryland) What is the global constitutional canon?

The Global Constitutional Canon: Some Preliminary Thoughts. Peter E. Quint (Maryland) What is the global constitutional canon? The Global Constitutional Canon: Some Preliminary Thoughts Peter E. Quint (Maryland) What is the global constitutional canon? Its underlying theory certainly must differ, in significant respects, from

More information

Curriculum for the Master s Programme in Social and Political Theory at the School of Political Science and Sociology of the University of Innsbruck

Curriculum for the Master s Programme in Social and Political Theory at the School of Political Science and Sociology of the University of Innsbruck The English version of the curriculum for the Master s programme in European Politics and Society is not legally binding and is for informational purposes only. The legal basis is regulated in the curriculum

More information

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba

Jan Narveson and James P. Sterba 1 Introduction RISTOTLE A held that equals should be treated equally and unequals unequally. Yet Aristotle s ideal of equality was a relatively formal one that allowed for considerable inequality. Likewise,

More information

Iran Academia Study Program

Iran Academia Study Program Iran Academia Study Program Course Catalogue 2017 Table of Contents 1 - GENERAL INFORMATION... 3 Iran Academia... 3 Program Study Load... 3 Study Periods... 3 Curriculum... 3 2 CURRICULUM... 4 Components...

More information

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum

Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum 51 Criminal Justice Without Moral Responsibility: Addressing Problems with Consequentialism Dane Shade Hannum Abstract: This paper grants the hard determinist position that moral responsibility is not

More information

Models of Social Science L98 AMCS 4023 M/W 10-11:30. Andrew Rehfeld Office: Seigle 233. American Culture Studies

Models of Social Science L98 AMCS 4023 M/W 10-11:30. Andrew Rehfeld Office: Seigle 233. American Culture Studies Models of Social Science L98 AMCS 4023 M/W 10-11:30 Andrew Rehfeld Office: Seigle 233 Political Science rehfeld@wustl.edu American Culture Studies 935-5812 Office Hours: Fri: 1:30-2:30 and by appointment.

More information

REVIEW OF FOUNDATIONS OF HUMAN SOCIALITY: ECONOMIC EXPERIMENTS AND ETHNOGRAPHIC EVIDENCE FROM FIFTEEN SMALL-SCALE SOCIETIES

REVIEW OF FOUNDATIONS OF HUMAN SOCIALITY: ECONOMIC EXPERIMENTS AND ETHNOGRAPHIC EVIDENCE FROM FIFTEEN SMALL-SCALE SOCIETIES REVIEW OF FOUNDATIONS OF HUMAN SOCIALITY: ECONOMIC EXPERIMENTS AND ETHNOGRAPHIC EVIDENCE FROM FIFTEEN SMALL-SCALE SOCIETIES ANITA JOWITT This book is not written by lawyers or written with legal policy

More information

Book review for Review of Austrian Economics, by Daniel B. Klein, George Mason

Book review for Review of Austrian Economics, by Daniel B. Klein, George Mason Book review for Review of Austrian Economics, by Daniel B. Klein, George Mason University. Ronald Hamowy, The Political Sociology of Freedom: Adam Ferguson and F.A. Hayek. New Thinking in Political Economy

More information

Class on Class. Lecturer: Gáspár Miklós TAMÁS. 2 credits, 4 ECTS credits Winter semester 2013 MA level

Class on Class. Lecturer: Gáspár Miklós TAMÁS. 2 credits, 4 ECTS credits Winter semester 2013 MA level Class on Class Lecturer: Gáspár Miklós TAMÁS 2 credits, 4 ECTS credits Winter semester 2013 MA level The doctrine of class in social theory, empirical sociology, methodology, etc. has always been fundamental

More information

Justice as fairness The social contract

Justice as fairness The social contract 29 John Rawls (1921 ) NORMAN DANIELS John Bordley Rawls, who developed a contractarian defense of liberalism that dominated political philosophy during the last three decades of the twentieth century,

More information

Scope and Methods in Political Science Ole J. Forsberg Proposed Syllabus

Scope and Methods in Political Science Ole J. Forsberg Proposed Syllabus Ole J. Forsberg Proposed Syllabus Course Purpose: The purpose of this course is to introduce students to the nature, language, forms, and methods of empirical social science inquiry. This course will focus

More information

Structure-agency and micro-macro integration. Antonio Montalbán Espinosa, Anastasiia Volkova

Structure-agency and micro-macro integration. Antonio Montalbán Espinosa, Anastasiia Volkova Structure-agency and micro-macro integration Antonio Montalbán Espinosa, Anastasiia Volkova The debate: Social structure vs human agency Social structure determines social life; individual activities =

More information

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted.

Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted. Theory Comp May 2014 Choose one question from each section to answer in the time allotted. Ancient: 1. Compare and contrast the accounts Plato and Aristotle give of political change, respectively, in Book

More information

Natural Resources Journal

Natural Resources Journal Natural Resources Journal 43 Nat Resources J. 2 (Spring 2003) Spring 2003 International Law and the Environment: Variations on a Theme, by Tuomas Kuokkanen Kishor Uprety Recommended Citation Kishor Uprety,

More information

CONTENTS PART ONE INTRODUCTORY REFLECTIONS

CONTENTS PART ONE INTRODUCTORY REFLECTIONS CONTENTS Preface Table of Cases Table of Statutes xiii XV xix PART ONE INTRODUCTORY REFLECTIONS 1. THE PLACE AND FUNCTION OF LEGAL THEORY 3 2. GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND THE BASIC PROBLEMS OF LAW 5 From Homer

More information

Morality and Foreign Policy

Morality and Foreign Policy Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy Volume 1 Issue 3 Symposium on the Ethics of International Organizations Article 1 1-1-2012 Morality and Foreign Policy Joseph Cardinal Bernardin Follow

More information

Meeting Plato s challenge?

Meeting Plato s challenge? Public Choice (2012) 152:433 437 DOI 10.1007/s11127-012-9995-z Meeting Plato s challenge? Michael Baurmann Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2012 We can regard the history of Political Philosophy as

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Comment on Steiner's Liberal Theory of Exploitation Author(s): Steven Walt Source: Ethics, Vol. 94, No. 2 (Jan., 1984), pp. 242-247 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2380514.

More information

The historical sociology of the future

The historical sociology of the future Review of International Political Economy 5:2 Summer 1998: 321-326 The historical sociology of the future Martin Shaw International Relations and Politics, University of Sussex John Hobson's article presents

More information

The Restoration of Welfare Economics

The Restoration of Welfare Economics The Restoration of Welfare Economics By ANTHONY B ATKINSON* This paper argues that welfare economics should be restored to a prominent place on the agenda of economists, and should occupy a central role

More information

The Philosophy and Methods of Political Science. Keith Dowding

The Philosophy and Methods of Political Science. Keith Dowding The Philosophy and Methods of Political Science Cologne University 10 15 March 2016 Keith Dowding Keith.dowding@anu.edu.au Australian National University The course is based around my new book of this

More information

Standing in the Judge s Shoes: Exploring Techniques to Help Legal Writers More Fully Address the Needs of Their Audience

Standing in the Judge s Shoes: Exploring Techniques to Help Legal Writers More Fully Address the Needs of Their Audience UNIVERSITY OF SAN FRANCISCO LAW REVIEW FORUM Standing in the Judge s Shoes: Exploring Techniques to Help Legal Writers More Fully Address the Needs of Their Audience By SHERRI LEE KEENE* LEGAL DOCUMENTS

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition

CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition CHAPTER 19 MARKET SYSTEMS AND NORMATIVE CLAIMS Microeconomics in Context (Goodwin, et al.), 2 nd Edition Chapter Summary This final chapter brings together many of the themes previous chapters have explored

More information

Feminist Critique of Joseph Stiglitz s Approach to the Problems of Global Capitalism

Feminist Critique of Joseph Stiglitz s Approach to the Problems of Global Capitalism 89 Feminist Critique of Joseph Stiglitz s Approach to the Problems of Global Capitalism Jenna Blake Abstract: In his book Making Globalization Work, Joseph Stiglitz proposes reforms to address problems

More information