Modern Equity. Emily Sherwin * justice which, were it not for the operation of the Judicature Acts, would be administered by

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Modern Equity. Emily Sherwin * justice which, were it not for the operation of the Judicature Acts, would be administered by"

Transcription

1 Modern Equity Emily Sherwin * Maitland defined equity as that body of laws administered by our English courts of justice which, were it not for the operation of the Judicature Acts, would be administered by courts that would be known as Courts of Equity. 1 The implication is that nothing unifies the various principles, doctrines, and remedies associated with equity other than their procedural origin. This is strictly true, and yet it raises the question why the concept of legal equity has not simply disappeared as procedural merger has become the norm. The answer may be that courts have administered the equitable principles, doctrines, and remedies in ways that are distinct from their administration of ordinary rules of law. The special roles that courts have assigned to equity continue to be important in our modern legal system. One distinguishing feature of equity is that courts have used it to correct unsatisfactory outcomes that sometimes result from the application of general, determinate rules.2 * Frank B. Ingersoll Professor of Law, Cornell Law School. 1 F.W. Maitland, Equity and Also the Forms of Action at Common Law (J.H. Chaytor & J. Whittaker, eds.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1929), 1. 2 This is equity in the Aristotelian sense. See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1138b25 (Hackett Pub., Terence Irwin, ed. & trans., 1985) ( And this is the nature of what is decent - rectification of law in so far as the universality of law makes it deficient. ). Although Maitland argued that equity did not follow a set of specifically equitable principles, he did view equity as a supplement or gloss on the common law, which softened the operation of common law rules. 1

2 Determinate rules serve a number of important legal and social purposes, the foremost of which is to enable individuals to coordinate their actions with the actions of others. Yet determinacy builds unacceptable outcomes into the administration of law. Strictly applied, a determinate rule may invite opportunism or it may impose undeserved hardship on a party. Traditionally, another distinguishing feature of equity has been its subordinate position in the system of law. Courts have treated equity as a branch of law that comes into play only when the resolutions offered by legal rules and remedies are objectionable in one way or another. Douglas Laycock has argued at length that courts no longer adhere in practice to traditional standards giving priority to legal remedies.3 Laycock admits, however, that whatever courts may do in fact, they still tend to speak of equity as a secondary component of the legal system. Another traditional feature of equity, both before and after procedural merger, is that equity has operated relatively obscurely within the system. Rules are comparatively easy to grasp, and courts tend to refer first to rules before turning to equitable exceptions. Further, corrective equity often takes the form of defenses that apply only to historically equitable forms See Maitland, Equity, ( if the legislature had passed a short act saying Equity is hereby abolished, we might still have got on fairly well, in some respects our law would have been barbarous, unjust, absurd, but still the great elementary rights... would have been decently protected. Id., See Douglas Laycock, The Death of the Irreparable Injury Rule 3-23 (New York: Oxford University Press 1991) 3-23 (arguing that although courts continue to cite the rule that equitable relief is not available if the plaintiff has an adequate legal remedy, they do not in practice withhold equitable relief unless there are functional reasons to do so). 2

3 of relief. The result is to decrease the perceived effects of equitable correction on legal rules: correction appears to be confined to one limited form of legal redress. The combined effect of these three features of equity is to maintain a precarious but useful balance between the benefits of determinate legal rules and the attraction of leniency. For reasons I will describe below, an system of law must provide in some way for corrective equity. At the same time, too much equity can undermine rules and consequently threaten other important ends of the legal system. The problem is that determinate rules, which allow for coordination, and corrective equity, which allows for justice, cannot easily coexist unless equity remains both subordinate to law and relatively obscure. The Legal Realists who shaped American law in the last century were skeptical of rules and enthusiastic about particularized, fact-based decisionmaking. They also disliked obscurity in law and insisted that the grounds of legal decisions should be clear: only through clarity can law be harnessed effectively to social scientific objectives. The result of this combination of attitudes was a program that altered the relation between law and equity by placing corrective equity front and center in the legal system. Pleading and procedure were geared toward facts rather than law and substantive rules were supplemented or replaced by explicitly particularistic doctrines such as unconscionability. If the Realists were wrong about rules, the strategies they pursued may be costly over time. By enlarging and spotlighting equity, they dispensed with the protective cover that once surrounded equitable decisionmaking and limited the effects of equity on general, determinate rules. When rules and equitable correction are equally open to view in a public system of law, the reliability of rules is significantly, and progressively, diminished. This is not to suggest that equity can or should be hidden deliberately from public view. 3

4 At least in a system that aspires to maintain the allegiance of its citizens, deceptive tactics will backfire. My objective is simply to explain the need for equity and the dilemma that equity poses for law. A. Rules4 One way to look at legal decisionmaking is from the forward-looking perspective of a benevolent lawmaking authority. I assume for this purpose that the lawmaking authority aims to serve the interests of those who are governed by law. I assume also that it approaches this task in a competent way. From the authority s vantage point, legal rules perform a number of important functions. If the authority has better information about the consequences of behavior than most of its subjects have, it can guide decisionmaking by enacting rules to govern conduct or transactions. Whether or not the authority has superior information, it can enact rules that will enable private actors to coordinate their behavior.5 In the absence of reliable rules, self-regulation may be difficult and in any event individual actors cannot anticipate what others will do. Once a set of 4 The most comprehensive source on the benefits of rules and the problems they pose is Frederick Schauer, Playing By the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision- Making in Law and Life (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1991). The points made in this subsection are also discussed at length in Larry Alexander and Emily Sherwin, The Rule of Rules: Morality, Rules, and the Dilemmas of Law (Durham: Duke University Press 2001) 5 On the coordination effects of rules, see, e.g., Gerald J. Postema, Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law, 11 J. Legal Stud.(1982) 165,

5 rules is in place and regularly followed, it becomes easier to anticipate what others will do and so to plan around the predicted conduct. Finally, regularly followed rules settle controversy and uncertainty that might otherwise consume individual and social resources. To provide these benefits, rules must be general in application and reasonably determinate.6 Generality allows the rulemaker to provide in a single rule for similarly situated parties and like cases that cannot be fully specified in advance. Determinacy enables the rule to provide effective guidance, to serve as a basis for coordination, and to settle controversy in terms that do not revive the dispute when the rule is interpreted and applied. General and relatively determinate rules, however, will sometimes prescribe outcomes that are incorrect, all things considered. General language chosen in advance will cover unanticipated cases in which the rule s prescription is out of place. Determinate terms will sweep in some situations that a more open-ended inquiry would exclude. If the errors brought about by a general, determinate rule are too frequent or too great, the rule should be discarded or revised. In at least some cases, however, the benefits a rule provides through guidance, coordination, and settlement are more significant than the errors it periodically 6 See Schauer, Playing By the Rules, The arguments made here assume that rules have a core of determinate meaning, even if their meaning is uncertain in some contexts. See generally Kent Greenawalt, Law and Objectivity (New York: Oxford University Press 1992), 34-89; H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1961), ; Schauer, supra note 3, at 53-68; Jules L. Coleman and Brian Leiter, Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority, 142 U. Pa. L. Rev. 549 (1993); Lawrence B. Solum, On the Indeterminacy Crisis: Critiquing Critical Dogma, 54 U. Chi. L. Rev. 462 (1987) 5

6 generates. In that case, the rule is a good rule and should be retained.7 I will assume, for the purpose of this essay, that the rules at issue are good rules in this sense, despite some flawed results. It might be thought that the flawed results of justified rules can be eliminated by adding a general exception for all cases in which, as a result of a rule s generality and determinate language, the rule prescribes a wrong result. In other words, it might be thought that the solution is a policy of unlimited corrective equity. An general equitable exception of this kind would come into play at the time the rule is applied to a particular set of facts, when more is known about the likely consequences of following the rule. If it appears at the time of application, after taking into account the damage that a violation of the rule will cause to values such as future guidance, coordination, and settlement, that following the rule is a mistake, then an equitable modification would be called for; otherwise, it would not. The difficulty with this solution, from the point of view of a benevolent lawmaking authority, is that a general equitable exception must be applied by human agents, who are not omniscient and do not reason flawlessly from the evidence they have. The rule-applier may be a rule-subject deciding whether to obey, or a judge deciding whether to enforce the rule according to its terms. Either way, she is likely to have incomplete evidence about the consequences of breaking or following the rule. Moreover, the rule-applier will be subject to common reasoning biases. Like most human agents, she will tend to overvalue relatively immediate and salient 7 If the rule is a good rule, but revisions could reduce the number of bad results, then ideally the rule should be revised. In the law/equity debate, however, this is a secondary problem. 6

7 facts, as compared to facts about long-term consequences of violating the rule such as diminished capacity for interpersonal coordination.8 As a result, the rule-applier is likely to undervalue reasons to follow the rule in a systematic way. For example, she may focus on the cost or unfairness of following the rule in this case, omitting to consider that violating the rule, or failing to enforce the rule, may affect general perceptions that the rule is regularly followed, and so reduce its usefulness as a source of coordination.9 Accordingly, it is more likely than not that the rule-applier will err in deciding when corrective equity is warranted. Another possible compromise solution is to add both a general exception for recalcitrant cases and a presumption in favor of following the rule unless it appears that there are reasons of considerable magnitude to violate the rule.10 Presumptive rule-following, however, is also 8 For overviews of the problem of cognitive biases and studies documenting the availability heuristic and similar patterns of human reasoning, see Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic, & Amos Tversky, eds., Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases 163)(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1982); Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic, & Amos Tversky, eds, Heuristics & Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002). 9 The rulemaker might build an exception into the rule, for cases with special features. To avoid the reasoning errors the rule is designed to prevent, however, the exception must be stated in fairly objective terms. Consequently, an exception of this type is really just an additional term of the rule. 10 This is Schauer s preferred solution. See Schauer, Playing By the Rules, , Frederick Schauer, Rules and the Rule of Law, Harv. J.L. & Publ. Pol y 14 (1991): 645,

8 subject to error at the point of application. A general practice of presumptive rule-following may also tend to erode over time: a presumption in favor of compliance assumes that subjects will weigh the immediate reasons to break a rule against reasons to follow the rule, such as the potential harm to coordination and other benefits of the rule. Each decision to violate the rule slightly decreases the perception that the rule is generally followed, and therefore slightly decreases the weight that other potential rule-followers will assign to the benefits associated with the rule. For these reasons the best resolution, from authority s point of view, is for all persons to follow the rule in all cases. Thus if, on average, the benefits of the rule outweigh the errors it will cause, the rule is justified. And if, on average, the rule outperforms individual judgment at the point of application, a general equitable exception is unwarranted. Another way to put this is that, from the authority s point of view, it is best that all those who apply the rule should treat the existence of the rule as an exclusionary reason for action.11 An exclusionary reason is one that functions both as a first-order reason to act in a certain way and as a second-order reason not to consider, or at least not to act on, a range of possible contrary reasons for action.12 Treating rules as exclusionary reasons for action solves the problem of error, and preserves the benefits of the 11 On exclusionary reasons for action, see Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986), 57-62; Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1979), 16-19, 22-23, See Joseph Raz, Promises and Obligation, in Law, Morality, and Society, P.M.S. Hacker & J. Raz, eds. (Oxford: Clarendon Press), (indicating that the exclusion is limited). 8

9 rule, by blocking evidence of special particular circumstances, as least if they fall within the general range of circumstances the lawmaker considered in designing the rule. B. Equity A strict approach to rules, in which rules function as exclusionary reasons for action, has significant practical benefits as long as the rules are good rules and perform better on average than human judgment at the point of application. Why, then, might there be a need for corrective equity? 1. Opportunism One answer, proposed by Henry Smith, is that equity allows judges to police the opportunism that determinate rules inevitably attract.13 Relatively sophisticated players can profit through bad behavior that is accidentally allowed, or not quite covered, by the terms of the rule. Corrective equity allows judges to intervene after the fact and eliminate unfair gains obtained in this way. 13 See, e.g., Henry E. Smith, Why Fiduciary Law Is Equitable, in Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law 261 (Andrew S. Gold & Paul B. Miller, eds., Oxford University. Press 2014); Yuval Feldman & Henry E. Smith, Behavioral Equity, 170 J. of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 137 (2014); Henry E. Smith, Equity as Second-Order Law: The Problem of Opportunism, available at (January 15, 2015); Henry E. Smith, Equitable Defenses as Meta-Law, forthcoming in Defences in Equity, eds. Paul S. Davies, Simon Douglas, and James Goudkamp (London: Hart Publishing). 9

10 This is an appealing argument, which assigns a function to equity in a procedurally merged legal system without endorsing the sort of open-ended correction that does most damage to the value of rules. The opportunism argument, however, raises several questions. One of these is empirical. From the point of view of the lawmaking authority, it may or may not be the case that the instrumental benefits of penalizing opportunists counterbalance the loss of rulebased benefits such as coordination that occurs when rules are not enforced according to their terms. Moreover, if judges can recapture enough opportunistic gain to outweigh the benefits of full enforcement, then the rule probably is not a good rule and its terms should be amended. Another problem that enters into the empirical balance is the possibility that judges may fail to distinguish accurately between deliberate advantage-taking and innocent reliance on rules that generate losses for one party. Smith characterizes the anti-opportunism function of equity as a second-order function in a system that otherwise enforces the rules. Equity, in other words, is a type of law about law, distinct from the ordinary business of enforcing legal rules. This characterization seems designed in part to limit the effects of equity on rules. The distinction between first-order and second-order law, however, is not likely to affect actors practical assessments of their legal reasons for action unless equity is not only second-order but also hidden from full view. In a legal system in which all judicial decisions, legal and equitable, are publically accessible, what matters is which set of reasons ultimately will prevail. To the extent that equity wins, legal rules are inert This seems to have been Hohfeld s view: Though it may represent an important stage of thought in the solution of a given problem... as regards the very relation in which it suffers 10

11 2. The Rules Gap My argument for equity is somewhat different, and depends on gap between the point of view of the rulemaking authority and the point of view of those who act under rules.15 Rule subjects and rule-appliers encounter rules in the context of a particular case, in which adverse consequences of a general, determinate rule are likely to be both evident and salient. From this perspective, correction will sometimes seem necessary, and limited correction based on opportunistic behavior may not be enough. Consider the position of an conscientious actor who confronts a case governed by a general rule. The actor agrees with the rulemaking authority that the rule is a good rule and understands the various reasons why, from the authority s point of view, she should follow the rule in this case. She understands that rules yield important practical benefits when regularly followed. She also understands that individual reasoners are prone to errors, especially when confronted with the salient facts of a single situation. Consequently, she understands that in the long run, the sum of outcomes will be best if all actors, including her, follow the rule in all cases that fall within its terms. direct competition with a rule of equity, the law is, pro tanto, of no greater force that an unconstitutional statute. Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, The Relations Between Law and Equity, 11 Mich. L. Rev. (1913) 537, Frederick Schauer has used the term asymmetry of authority to describe this difference in perspective. Schauer, Playing by the Rules, Larry Alexander refers to the problem as The Gap. Larry Alexander, The Gap, 14 Harv. J. L. & Public Pol y (1991), 695, 695. For further discussion, see Alexander & Sherwin, Rule of Rules,

12 Yet, the actor may still believe that she should not follow the rule in this case. The authority s position is a position that holds on average, subject to the further understanding that any general and determinate rule will sometimes dictate the wrong result for a particular case. A reflective actor will consider not only which action best fits the circumstances, but also whether others are likely to observe her conduct and if, so, what effect a violation would have on the coordination value of the rule. She must also consider the likelihood that her own reasoning is biased or otherwise faulty and the chance that authority possesses special expertise that exceeds her own. Nevertheless, after taking all these considerations into account, the actor may conclude that it is best to violate the rule in this case. In these circumstances, the perspective of the actor diverges from that of the rule-making authority. From the actor s point of view, following the rule will seem irrational and wrong. In fact, the actor may be incorrect: she may have underestimated the probability of harm to the rule and overestimated her reasoning abilities. Nevertheless, if she complies with the rule she is acting against her own best understanding of current reasons for action. This dilemma can be restated in terms of practical rationality. Practical rationality is the rationality of agents in choosing and taking action.16 I assume a primarily instrumental understanding of practical rationality, in which it is rational for an agent to choose the action that will best advance her ends A classic discussion appears in Derek Parfit, REAsons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1984). 17 See, e.g., Michael E. Bratman, Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), 52. Instrumental benefit can be defined broadly to 12

13 Traditionally, practical rationality is evaluated in terms of the agent s current reasons for action.18 More recently, a number of writers have suggested that it is a mistake to think about practical rationality solely in terms of present reasons for action. Instead, practical rationality is a condition that extends over time: actors often can achieve greater instrumental benefits by forming intentions and sticking with them over time than by focusing exclusively on current reasons for action.19 Thus, if the actor will do better in the long run by always following the rule than by always exercising her best judgment, then the rational choice is to follow the rule. encompass moral values of the agent. 18 Edward McClennen calls this the principle of Separability and illustrates with a decision tree in which each new decisional node starts fresh with current forward-looking reasons. A decision tree of this type separates rationality into slices of time and rationality at each slice tied to current reasons for action. See Edward F. McClennen, Pragmatic Rationality and Rules, in Phil. & Publ. Affairs 23 (1997), See Bratman, Intentions, 2-3, 83-91; David Gauthier, Intention and Deliberation, in Modeling Rationality, Morality, and Evolution, ed. P. Danielson (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1998); David Gauthier, Assure and Threaten, Ethics 104 (1998); Edward F. McClennen, Pragmatic Rationality and Rules, in Phil. & Publ. Affairs 26:3(1997), 23; Edward F. McClennen and Scott J. Shapiro, Rule-Guided Behavior, in III New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, ed. Peter Newman (New York: Stockton Press 1998), 367; Scott J. Shapiro, Legality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011), ; Scott J. Shapiro, The Difference that Rules Make, in Analyzing Law: New Essays in Legal Theory, ed. Brian Bix (Oxford: Clarendon Press (1998). 13

14 There are difficulties with this temporally extended approach to rationality, particularly in the context of rule-following. First, rationality seems to presuppose the possibility of a reasoned change of mind when the agent confronts circumstances that she did not specifically anticipate when she formed her intention.20 Sticking doggedly to a plan when current reasons for action appear to support a change in course may be a practical mistake. Second, it is hard to explain the cognitive mechanism that would allow a rational actor to act on a prior intention in the face of a contrary belief about what she now should do. Arguably, deliberation can only conclude in action when the action is supported by the agent s will.21 Once the actor forms a belief about reasons for action, based on current evidence, she will lack the will necessary to support the act. One possible way to explain the rationality of acting on prior intentions is to argue that once the actor has settled on a plan, rationality does not require further reflection at the time of action. In other words, although it might not be rational for an actor to act against her present reflective understanding of reasons for action, it can be rational to act on prior intentions without reflection at the point of action. Michael Bratman, in particular, has argued that it is rational to act unreflectively on prior intentions as long as the actor is guided by practically reasonable general dispositions toward intentions, meaning dispositions that achieve good results over time. 20 This is most clear in Bratman s discussion. See Bratman, Intentions, 60 (suggesting that whenever an agent spontaneously reflects on reasons for an action, she effectively reconsiders prior intentions relating to that action). 21 Raz, for example, argues that deliberation does not lead directly to action but instead requires the assistance of both intention and an element of will. See Joseph Raz, From Normativity to Responsibilty (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2011),

15 In Bratman s view, intentions are special cognitive states that carry with them an element of volitional commitment as long as they remain in place. As a result, unless the actor pauses to reconsider, her prior intention will support current action without the need to form new beliefs about current reasons for action.22 In this way, the actor can obtain the benefits of making and acting on stable plans without sacrificing rationality. Bratman s account of temporally extended practical rationality provides a cognitive explanation for adherence to rules, and for the idea that legal rules provide exclusionary reasons for action. A rational actor can form an intention to follow a set of good rules, then act directly on her intention without considering contrary reasons for action, based on her prior volitional commitment to follow the rules. In seems to follow that there is rationality does not require equitable exceptions to rules. If it is rational over the long run to follow the governing rules, rational actors can and should adopt the authority s point of view and follow the rules unreflectively in particular cases. Yet, the argument that it is always rational to act on a prior intention to obey sound rules has several weaknesses. One is that nothing other than the force of habit requires actors to follow or apply rules without reflection. At least according to Bratman s account of rationality, the volitional commitment associated with rules dissipates if the actor chooses to reflect. As a result, there may still be cases in which the actor reflects, reconsiders, and then must face a 22 See Bratman, Intentions, 15-16, 64-65, Bratman s approach also provides an answer to Raz s point that deliberative action depends on will. Volitional commitment can be understood to carry the element of will and so to satisfy the requirement of will. See text at note XX, supra. 15

16 conflict between the demands of the rule and what she perceives to be the rational choice of action. A second problem is this. Assume the actor does not reflect before complying with a rule, and assume that it is practically rational for her to do so, in the sense that regular unreflective compliance with rules will be instrumentally beneficial over time. In this type of case, practical rationality appears to lead the actor into epistemic irrationality. A very plausible understanding of epistemic rationality holds that individuals must advert to evidence in their possession that defeats beliefs they currently hold.23 This standard of responsibility can easily be extended to the case of rule-follower who believes that it is generally best follow a rule but has evidence suggesting that she should not follow the rule in a particular case. The evidence does not defeat her belief that is it is generally best to follow the rule, but it indicates that her belief is misplaced in her current circumstances and that she should adjust her belief to suit the case. Thus, although the practically rational course may be to treat the rule as an exclusionary rule and follow it without reflection, an actor who does this may not be epistemically rational. 23 See Richard Feldman, The Ethics of Belief, in Earl Conee and Richard Feldman, Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), (beginning with a very limited view of epistemic responsibility but later qualifying it by requiring agents to take account of defeating evidence); Alvin Goldman, Toward a Synthesis of Reliabilism and Evidentialism, in Evidentialism and Its Discontents, ed. Trent Doherty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 23 (writing from a process reliabilist point of view, but adding a standard of epistemic responsibility to process defeating evidence) 16

17 C. Judicial Equity Equity enters in because the foregoing observations about discomfort and irrationality in particular cases apply not only to actors who are called on to follow rules but also to judges who must apply rules to individual actors after the fact. Judges often act as rulemakers, and so are likely to understand the long-term benefits of regular application of rules. Yet judges are also rule-appliers, who confront rules in the setting of particular cases and face difficulties similar to those actors fact when a general rule produces a result that seems unintended or wrong. Morever, judges are human reasoners, who are similarly susceptible to the type of cognitive bias in favor of immediate, salient facts that affects any fallible reasoner.24 From the point of view of the rulemaking authority, it is best that judges apply good rules according to their terms, even when the judge believes the outcome the rule calls for is wrong. Because judges are not perfect reasoners, regular enforcement of the rule according to its terms often will produce better results over time than particularistic decisionmaking by judges. Moreover, when judges err, the risk of harm to rule values is especially high. If actors perceive that judicial decisions do not regularly conform to rules, they will not expect other actors to follow the rules and can no longer rely on them as focal points for coordination. From the point of view of the judge, however, enforcing the rule when the judge believes the outcome is wrong will appear irrational and unfair to the parties affected. 24 See Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, Bottom-Up and Top-Down Decisionmaking, 73 U. Chi. L. Rev. (2006) 933, (discussing the effects of affect and availability biases in judicial decisionmaking); Frederick Schauer, Do Cases Make Bad Law?, 73 U. Chi. L. Rev. 883, 895 (2006) 883, 895 (observing that judges, as rulemakers, are subject to the availability bias). 17

18 In cases involving equitable defenses, judges often self-consciously invoke the corrective function associated with the equity side of law. For example, in Panco v. Rogers, Panco agreed to sell his house to Rogers.25 Mr. Panco, a retired carpenter who had built his own house, agreed to sell the house to the Rogers. After discussing the transaction with Mrs. Panco, who was not a native English speaker, Mr. Rogers prepared an agreement naming a price of $5500. Panco, who was elderly and deaf, signed the agreement without reading it, then later refused to convey. Panco testified that he intended to ask $12,500 for the house and the court found the house was worth at least $10,000. The court found no evidence that Rogers had engaged in fraud, concealment, or undue influence, and determined that Panco had breached the contract. It nevertheless denied Rogers claim for specific performance, saying that an application for specific performance is directed to the sound discretion of a court of equity... [T]he court must be satisfied that the claim is fair, reasonable, and just, and in judging of its fairness, the court will look not only at the terms of the contract itself, but at all of the surrounding circumstances, including the relations the parties.... Where the enforcement of a contract for the sale of land would be harsh, oppressive or manifestly unjust to one of the parties thereto, its specific performance will not be decreed, but the parties will be left to their remedy at law. 26 This is a classic example of corrective equity, applied to deny equitable relief. The applicable rules did not recognize unilateral mistake as a ground for rescission, so the contract 25 Panco v. Rogers, 87 A.2d 770 (N.J. Ch. Div. 1952) 26 Id. at

19 was valid and Panco theoretically was liable for breach. In fact, the equitable defense probably was conclusive. A damage claim would require Rogers to incur additional expense, and in any event a jury fixing damages for the value of the Rogers lost bargain would likely fix a low sum based on the same considerations that led the court to deny an equitable remedy. Therefore, the decision amounts to an exception to court s stated rule, that a unilateral mistake is not a defense to contract obligation. Panco v. Rogers can be viewed as a case of opportunism. Rogers had reason to believe that the Pancos were not experienced bargainers, may have known the price was low, and may have suspected that Panco had not read the contract. If so, the case fits well with the view that corrective equity operates, or should operate, as a mechanism by which courts can detect and penalize parties who taken advantage of general, determinate rules to obtain unjustified gains. The potential for equitable correction, however, goes beyond opportunism. Suppose instead that, on the best understanding of the facts, Rogers acted in good faith: he was an inexperienced buyer who was not familiar with prices, he believed that Mrs. Panco stated and intended a price figure of $5500, and he did not realize that Panco was mistaken about the contents of the written agreement. Although there are no signs of opportunism in this case, the bargain is one-sided and there is no reason to believe that the exchange is efficient. Thus, the judge in this revised case would still be under rational and sympathetic pressure to depart from the rules and deny full enforcement of the contract. Another example is Patel v. Ali.27 Mrs. Ali, a young mother, agreed to sell her home to the Patels in what appears to have been a fair transaction. Closing was significantly delayed for 27 Patel v. Ali, [1984] 48 P. & C.R

20 various reasons that were not attributable to the Patels, including a claim by Mr. Ali s bankruptcy trustee that eventually was dismissed. In the interim, Mrs. Ali had a second and third child. She also developed bone cancer, which resulted in amputation of a leg. By the time of the closing, she was dependent on help from her sister, who lived nearby, and other sympathetic neighbors in a close Muslim community. In these circumstances, the court refused to grant specific performance and limited the Patels remedy to damages for loss of bargain (to be financed by helpful friends). As in the case of Mr. Panco, it seems unlikely that the plaintiffs would choose to press a claim for damages or that, if they did, the jury would award substantial damages. So in effect, the judge made an exception to the normal rules of contract obligation.28 The ambivalence he felt in doing so is evident in his opening remarks: The circumstances of [this] case are unusual and it has caused me some anxiety. The argument for the defendant... necessarily arouses so much sympathy that I felt for a long time that any exercise of discretionary jurisdiction in her favour would probably be unfair to her opponents, just because of the force of such sympathy.29 In the end, however, sympathy in light of Mrs. Ali s circumstances prevailed over fidelity to the rules. In each of these cases, it might be better from the authority s point of view to enforce the rule, both to preserve its value as a guide to contracting parties and to contain judicial error over 28 The court stated that subsequent personal hardship is not normally a defense to contract obligation; the seller takes the risk of unexpected events. It reasoned that in the case of Ms. Ali, she never bargained for a situation in which years would pass before closing. Arguably, however, delay can also be a risk the buyer assumes by signing a contract. Id., Id.,

21 the long run. But this approach is unsatisfying from the vantage point of the particular case. The two viewpoints at work are fundamentally different: they cannot be reconciled or averaged, because they pit long-term practical rationality against epistemic rationality, human sympathy, and human error. Both viewpoints are important to a legal system that depends in part on the loyalty of both actors and judges. Corrective equity gives recognition to the second, particularized point of view. C. Equity and Legal Realism Modern American law has been much influenced by the Legal Realist movement that began in the first half of the twentieth century. Although the American Legal Realists took various views on judicial decisionmaking, they converged on several general ideas. First, most were skeptical about the value of general, determinate rules. They argued that judges typically have a choice among eligible but conflicting rules and that in any event, rules are subject to conflicting interpretations. Consequently, rules exert no real force on judicial decisions Even Karl Llewellyn, principal drafter of the Uniform Commercial Code, took this view, saying that every single precedent, according to what may be the attitude of future judges, is ambiguous, is wide or narrow at will ) Karl N. Llewellyn, The Bramble Bush: Some Lectures on the Law and Its Study 2-4 (New York: Oceana, 1930), (emphasis omitted); see also Karl N. Llewellyn, A Realistic Jurisprudence - The Next Step, 30 Colu. L. Rev. 431(1930), (discussing the difference between paper rules and the real rules that govern decisions). See generally Brian Leiter, American Legal Realism, in The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, Dennis Patterson ed., 2d ed. 2010) 21

22 A closely related idea was that judicial decisions respond primarily to the facts of particular cases. Judges may be moved by the impact of their decisions on the parties involved, or by the social and economic consequences of their decisions, or simply by their own hunches about the dispute before them.31 It follows that operative law is located not in rules but in the facts and outcomes of individual disputes or empirical judgments about the impact of decisions , (discussing Realist endorsement of rational indeterminacy). 31 See, e.g., Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind (New York: Brentano s 1930), 111 ( The peculiar traits, dispositions, biases and habits of the particular judge will, then, often determine what he decides to be the law); Joseph C. Hutcheson, The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the Hunch in Judicial Decision, 14 Cornell L.Q. 274 (1929), 278 ( I, after canvassing all the available material... wait for the feeling, the hunch - that intuitive flash of understanding that makes the jump-spark connection between question and decision... ); Llewellyn, Bramble Bush, 69 (advocates must build an inductive case for their desired result); Herman Oliphant, A Return to Stare Decisis, Pt. 2, 14 A.B.A J. 159 (1928) 159( we see that courts are dominantly coerced not by the essays of their predecessors but by a surer thing, - by the intuition of fitness of solution to problem, - and a renewed faith in judicial government is engendered. ). 32 Frank, Law and the Modern Mind, 276 ( Law is what happened or will happen in concrete cases ); Llewellyn, Bramble Bush, 2-4 ( to my mind the main thing is seeing what officials do...; and seeing that there is a certain regularity in their doing - a regularity which makes possible prediction ). See generally Leiter, American Legal Realism, 257 ( the Core 22

23 This understanding of nature of law and legal decisionmaking led to several prescriptions. Pleading and procedures should be oriented toward the fullest possible discovery of facts and legal doctrine should be stated in open terms that lead judges to investigate the facts of cases before them.33 Legal theory should be empirical rather than analytical and legal reform should work from the from the premise that decisionmaking turns on facts.34 Finally, judges should state the grounds of their decisions as forthrightly as possible, so that these can be studied and understood by all actors in the system. Covert tools are never reliable tools. 35 Claim of realism is that judges respond primarily to the stimulus of the underlying facts of the case ). 33 Stephen N. Subrin, How Equity Conquered Common Law: The Federal Rules of Civil Procedure in Historical Perspective, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 909 (1987), (relating the history of Charles Clark and the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure); Llewellyn, Realistic Jurisprudence, 452 (lawmakers must so shape [the rule] as to induce its application ); Oliphant, Stare Decisis, 160 (proposing reclassification of most of law in terms of the human relations affected by it ). 34 See, e.g., Llewellyn, Realistic Jurisprudence, (the focal point of legal thought should be the area of contact between judicial (or official) behavior and the behavior of laymen )(emphasis omitted); Walter Wheeler Cook, The Logical and Legal Bases of the Conflict of Laws, 33 Yale L.J. 457 (1924), 460 (proposing to observe concrete phenomena first and form generalizations afterwards ). 35 Karl N. Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals (Boston: Little, Brown, 1960), 365, quoting Karl N. Llewellyn, Book Review, 52 Harv. L. Rev. 700 (1939), 703. See Oliphant, Stare Decisis, 159 ( With eyes cleared of the old and broad abstractions which 23

24 Steven Subrin has argued persuasively that in the realm of procedure, Legal Realism brought about a fundamental shift from traditional common law methods to fact-oriented methods associated with equity.36 Subrin does not advocate a return to rigid common law procedures, but he suggests that the Realist-inspired Federal Rules of Civil Procedure may have gone too far in the direction of unstructured and particularized decision-making. Lawsuits often lack focus, costs are high, outcomes are unpredictable, and the system consequently is not as effective as it might be in vindicating rights.37 The Realist program brought about similar changes in the substantive law, favoring factspecific equitable doctrines over the more technical rules of the common law. A leading example is Karl Llewellyn s Uniform Commercial Code, which makes liberal use of equitable terms such as unconscionability and good faith that are virtually impossible to define outside the setting of a particular dispute.38 Broad defenses of this kind are no longer confined to curtain our vision, we come to recognize more and more the eminent good sense in what courts are wont to do about disputes before them. ) 36 See Subrin, Equity, 973 ( the major theme [of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure] was that procedures should step aside and not interfere with substance ), 1000 (in this way, equity procedures have swallowed those of common law ). 37 Id., See U.C.C (good faith in performance and enforcement), (2-302)(unconscionability). Arthur Alan Leff was highly critical of the unconscionability provisions of the UCC and also distinguished Code unconscionability from the more modest unconscionability defense previously recognized in equity. See Arthur Allen Leff, 24

25 equitable relief, but applied to legal remedies as well.39 Thus, in many places, Mr. Panco could now rescind his contract with the Rogers, based on a unilateral mistake with unconscionable consequences.40 Mrs. Ali s defense of subsequent hardship remains unusual. When allowed, however, it is likely to be a full defen to contractual obligation, rather than a special defense to equitable relief. Thus, in the post-realist legal system, equity no longer operates in the background as way for judges to act on their best judgment that a rule has misfired. Instead, corrective equity functions as part of the primary law governing legal obligations. D. Clarity About Equity Legal Realism not only pushed law in the direction of particularistic decisionmaking, but also made the equitable component of legal decisionmaking more open and explicit. Traditionally, the main vehicles for corrective equity were equitable defenses of the type applied Unconscionability and the Code: The Emperor s New Clause, 115 U. Pa. L. Rev. 485 (1967). Unconscionability and similar terms were also incorporated into Realist-inspired Restatements. See, e.g., Restatement (Second) of Contracts 153 (unilateral mistake), 205 (good faith and fair dealing) (American Law Institute, 1979). 39 For example, the UCC s provision on unconscionability provides judges with a broad array of remedies in response to unconscionability, including refusal to enforce the contract by any means, legal or equitable. UCC 302; see also Restatement (Second) of Contracts 208 (1981). 40 Restatement (Second) of Contracts 153(a) (1981). 25

26 in Panco v. Rogers and Patel v. Ali, which may not be immediately evident at the planning stage of actions and transactions. Although the existence of equitable defenses has long been publically accessible in judicial reports, parties - even those acting with professional legal advice - may not comprehend the importance of equitable relief or the special defense that may apply if an equitable remedy is needed. As a result, the effect of traditional equitable defenses on the level of public confidence in the rules governing legal obligation is considerably muted. Judges deciding cases after the fact may understand that allowing an equitable defense creates an exception to the governing rules, but parties acting under rules may not fully grasp this point. In this way, the comparative obscurity of equitable defenses provides a partial solution to the dilemma of general rules and equitable correction: judges perceive the effects of their decisions but actors may not fully comprehend the unreliability of the rules.41 In addition to widening the scope of equitable correction, Realist reforms placed equitable correction in a more visible role. The role of equity in modifying the outcome of rules has been codified, restated, and extended beyond the traditional, less visible realm of defenses to equitable relief. Whatever cover the features of subordination and obscurity may once have provided to equitable correction is now largely gone. D. Conclusion: The Place of Equity in Modern Law Corrective equity is inevitable in a legal system. Even given a set of rules such that the sum of outcomes over time would be better if all people followed the rules in all cases, it will 41 See generally Meir Dan-Cohen, Conduct Rules and Decision Rules: On Acoustic Separation in Criminal Law, 97 Harv. L. Rev. 625 (1984). 26

27 sometimes appear wrong, irrational, and unfair to enforce a rule. Corrective equity, however, impairs the reliability of, and so decreases the benefits of, determinate rules. As a consequence of Realist reforms, the effect of corrective equity on rules is no longer limited by the obscurity of equitable doctrines and defenses and their seemingly secondary role in the system. Nor can this type of obscurity be reinstated. In a public system of law, obscurity cannot be engineered; it can only arise by an accident such as the separation of common law courts and chancery courts in much of Anglo-American legal history. Any proposal for deliberate obfuscation of corrective equity would surely be rejected as a form of manipulation practiced on judges and citizens. In the current legal world, the only available answer is that judges must do their best to understand the effects that relief from the errors of rules may have on the value of rules. This is not an ideal answer. It requires that judges, in making their decisions, must bear in mind the coordination benefits and other advantages of regularly enforced rules, try to calculate at least roughly the cumulative effects that exceptions in the current case and other similar cases will have on those benefits, and take account of the possibility that their own reasoning will be mistaken. In requires, in other words, that they must not take too seriously the Realist faith in the accuracy of judicial hunches and particularistic situation sense. 27

Ducking Dred Scott: A Response to Alexander and Schauer.

Ducking Dred Scott: A Response to Alexander and Schauer. University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 1998 Ducking Dred Scott: A Response to Alexander and Schauer. Emily Sherwin Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm

More information

Strategic Speech in the Law *

Strategic Speech in the Law * Strategic Speech in the Law * Andrei MARMOR University of Southern California Let us take the example of legislation as a paradigmatic case of legal speech. The enactment of a law is not a cooperative

More information

MISTAKE. (1) the other party to the contract knew or should have known of the mistake; or

MISTAKE. (1) the other party to the contract knew or should have known of the mistake; or MISTAKE Mistake of Fact: The parties entered into a contract with different understandings of one or more material facts relating to the contract s performance. Mutual Mistake: A mistake by both contracting

More information

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism Introduction In his incisive paper, Positivism and the

More information

Reality of Consent. Reality of Consent. Reality of Consent. Chapter 13

Reality of Consent. Reality of Consent. Reality of Consent. Chapter 13 Reality of Consent Chapter 13 Reality of Consent It is crucial to the economy and commerce that the law be counted on to enforce contracts. However, in some cases there are compelling reasons to permit

More information

RECOMMENDED FRAMEWORK FOR BEST PRACTICES IN INTERNATIONAL COMPETITION LAW ENFORCEMENT PROCEEDINGS

RECOMMENDED FRAMEWORK FOR BEST PRACTICES IN INTERNATIONAL COMPETITION LAW ENFORCEMENT PROCEEDINGS RECOMMENDED FRAMEWORK FOR BEST PRACTICES IN INTERNATIONAL COMPETITION LAW ENFORCEMENT PROCEEDINGS 1. INTRODUCTION 1.1. Preliminary Statement 1.1.1. This draft proposal has been prepared by the Due Process

More information

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization" By MICHAEL AMBROSIO We have been given a wonderful example by Professor Gordley of a cogent, yet straightforward

More information

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG SYMPOSIUM POLITICAL LIBERALISM VS. LIBERAL PERFECTIONISM POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG JOSEPH CHAN 2012 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 2, No. 1 (2012): pp.

More information

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process TED VAGGALIS University of Kansas The tragic truth about philosophy is that misunderstanding occurs more frequently than understanding. Nowhere

More information

Judgment of Conviction, Effect in a Civil Case as Res Judicata or as Evidence

Judgment of Conviction, Effect in a Civil Case as Res Judicata or as Evidence University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1932 Judgment of Conviction, Effect in a Civil Case as Res Judicata or as Evidence Edward W. Hinton Follow this and

More information

ORIGINALISM AND PRECEDENT

ORIGINALISM AND PRECEDENT ORIGINALISM AND PRECEDENT JOHN O. MCGINNIS * & MICHAEL B. RAPPAPORT ** Although originalism has grown in popularity in recent years, the theory continues to face major criticisms. One such criticism is

More information

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague E-LOGOS ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN 1211-0442 1/2010 University of Economics Prague Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals e Alexandra Dobra

More information

Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Spring Course Introduction

Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Spring Course Introduction Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Course Introduction I. What is a Contract? A. Epstein, Markell & Ponoroff (p. 1): [A] promise or set of

More information

Uniform Arbitration Act

Uniform Arbitration Act 2-1 Uniform Law Conference of Canada Uniform Act 2-2 Table of Contents INTRODUCTORY MATTERS 1 Definitions 2 Application of Act 3 Contracting out 4 Waiver of right to object 5 agreements COURT INTERVENTION

More information

NJLRC. June Appendix B c:\rpts\ucc5.doc

NJLRC. June Appendix B c:\rpts\ucc5.doc NJLRC New Jersey Law Revision Commission FINAL REPORT UNIFORM COMMERCIAL CODE REVISED ARTICLE 5. - LETTERS OF CREDIT 15 Washington Street, Room 1302 Newark, New Jersey 07102 201-648-4575 (Fax) 648-3123

More information

Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal

Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal 1 The Sources of American Law Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal order must deal with a variety of different, although related, matters. Historical roots and derivations need explanation.

More information

Foundations of the Economic Approach to Law. Edited by AVERY WIENER KATZ

Foundations of the Economic Approach to Law. Edited by AVERY WIENER KATZ Foundations of the Economic Approach to Law Edited by AVERY WIENER KATZ New York Oxford Oxford University Press 1998 Contents 1 Methodology of the Economic Approach, 3 1.1 Behavioral Premises The Economic

More information

Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, Volume 5, Issue 1, 2008, pp. 1-4 (Article) DOI: /epi

Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, Volume 5, Issue 1, 2008, pp. 1-4 (Article) DOI: /epi ntr d t n: p t ppr h t D r David Estlund Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, Volume 5, Issue 1, 2008, pp. 1-4 (Article) P bl h d b d nb r h n v r t Pr DOI: 10.1353/epi.0.0028 For additional information

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Spring Contract Terms (Expanded)

Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Spring Contract Terms (Expanded) Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Contract Terms (Expanded) I. Construing and Interpreting Contracts A. Purpose: A court s primary concern

More information

This page intentionally left blank

This page intentionally left blank This page intentionally left blank Demystifying Legal Reasoning Demystifying Legal Reasoning defends the proposition that there are no special forms of reasoning peculiar to law. Legal decision makers

More information

Illegality. Illegality. Meaning of Illegality. Irwin/McGraw-Hill 2001 The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All Rights Reserved.

Illegality. Illegality. Meaning of Illegality. Irwin/McGraw-Hill 2001 The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All Rights Reserved. Illegality Chapter 15 (8) Slide 1 Illegality When an agreement involves an act or a promise that violates some legislative or court-made rule, agreement will not be enforceable on ground of illegality

More information

REVIEW QUESTIONS TRUE/FALSE QUESTIONS (CIRCLE THE CORRECT ANSWER)

REVIEW QUESTIONS TRUE/FALSE QUESTIONS (CIRCLE THE CORRECT ANSWER) REVIEW QUESTIONS TRUE/FALSE QUESTIONS (CIRCLE THE CORRECT ANSWER) 1. T F When a court or legislature protects a class, this protection extends to all members of that class in every contractual transaction.

More information

Comments and observations received from Governments

Comments and observations received from Governments Extract from the Yearbook of the International Law Commission:- 1997,vol. II(1) Document:- A/CN.4/481 and Add.1 Comments and observations received from Governments Topic: International liability for injurious

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

What is equity? Equity as a body of law

What is equity? Equity as a body of law What is equity? Purpose of equity: to work alongside/supplements the common law, rather than overwhelm it. Equity and justice Principle: Equity ameliorates the harshness of the common law by proposing

More information

The Expectation Remedy Revisited

The Expectation Remedy Revisited Yale Law School Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship Series Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship 2012 The Expectation Remedy Revisited Alan Schwartz Yale Law School Follow this

More information

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the United States and other developed economies in recent

More information

A COMMENTARY ON PUBLIC FUNDS OR PUBLICLY FUNDED BENEFITS AND THE REGULATION OF JUDICIAL CAMPAIGNS

A COMMENTARY ON PUBLIC FUNDS OR PUBLICLY FUNDED BENEFITS AND THE REGULATION OF JUDICIAL CAMPAIGNS A COMMENTARY ON PUBLIC FUNDS OR PUBLICLY FUNDED BENEFITS AND THE REGULATION OF JUDICIAL CAMPAIGNS LILLIAN R. BEVIER * 1 Professor Briffault s paper is an elegant and virtually unassailable analysis of

More information

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon PHILIP PETTIT The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon In The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy, Christopher McMahon challenges my claim that the republican goal of promoting or maximizing

More information

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia AUSTRALIAN JOURNAL OF LAW AND SOCIETY (1993) 9 REVIEW Statutory Interpretation in Australia P C Pearce and R S Geddes Butterworths, 1988, Sydney (3rd edition) John Gava Book reviews are normally written

More information

Contracts of Insane Persons in New York

Contracts of Insane Persons in New York Fordham Law Review Volume 2 Issue 3 Article 3 1916 Contracts of Insane Persons in New York Frederick L. Kane Recommended Citation Frederick L. Kane, Contracts of Insane Persons in New York, 2 Fordham L.

More information

Permanent Editorial Board for the Uniform Commercial Code PEB COMMENTARY NO. 18. July 2014

Permanent Editorial Board for the Uniform Commercial Code PEB COMMENTARY NO. 18. July 2014 Permanent Editorial Board for the Uniform Commercial Code PEB COMMENTARY NO. 18 July 2014 2014 by The American Law Institute and the National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. All rights

More information

Doss v. State 135 OHIO ST. 3D 211, 2012-OHIO-5678, 985 N.E.2D 1229 DECIDED DECEMBER 6, 2012

Doss v. State 135 OHIO ST. 3D 211, 2012-OHIO-5678, 985 N.E.2D 1229 DECIDED DECEMBER 6, 2012 Doss v. State 135 OHIO ST. 3D 211, 2012-OHIO-5678, 985 N.E.2D 1229 DECIDED DECEMBER 6, 2012 I. INTRODUCTION In Doss v. State, 1 the Supreme Court of Ohio decided whether an appellate decision vacating

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules

Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules Chicago-Kent Law Review Volume 65 Issue 1 Symposium on Post-Chicago Law and Economics Article 10 April 1989 Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules Jules L. Coleman Follow this and additional

More information

The Influences of Legal Realism in Plessy, Brown and Parents Involved

The Influences of Legal Realism in Plessy, Brown and Parents Involved The Influences of Legal Realism in Plessy, Brown and Parents Involved Brown is not an example of the Court resisting majoritarian sentiment, but... converting an emerging national consensus into a constitutional

More information

Glossary of Terms for Business Law and Ethics

Glossary of Terms for Business Law and Ethics Glossary of Terms for Business Law and Ethics MBA 625, Patten University Abusive/Intimidating Behavior Physical threats, false accusations, being annoying, profanity, insults, yelling, harshness, ignoring

More information

BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW INSTITUTE

BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW INSTITUTE BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW INSTITUTE 1822 East Mall, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia V6T 1Z1 Voice: (604) 822 0142 Fax: (604) 822 0144 E mail: bcli@bcli.org Website: www.bcli.org UNFAIR

More information

NASH EQUILIBRIUM AS A MEAN FOR DETERMINATION OF RULES OF LAW (FOR SOVEREIGN ACTORS) Taron Simonyan 1

NASH EQUILIBRIUM AS A MEAN FOR DETERMINATION OF RULES OF LAW (FOR SOVEREIGN ACTORS) Taron Simonyan 1 NASH EQUILIBRIUM AS A MEAN FOR DETERMINATION OF RULES OF LAW (FOR SOVEREIGN ACTORS) Taron Simonyan 1 Social behavior and relations, as well as relations of states in international area, are regulated by

More information

Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Spring Contract Terms

Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Spring Contract Terms Contracts Professor Keith A. Rowley William S. Boyd School of Law University of Nevada Las Vegas Contract Terms I. Construing and Interpreting Contracts A. Purpose: A court s primary concern is to ascertain

More information

COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL THE LEGAL CONTEXT OF CONSTRUCTION 1.1 INTRODUCTION

COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL THE LEGAL CONTEXT OF CONSTRUCTION 1.1 INTRODUCTION 1 1.1 INTRODUCTION THE LEGAL CONTEXT OF CONSTRUCTION Construction projects are complex and multifaceted. Likewise, the law governing construction is complex and multifaceted. Aside from questions of what

More information

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions

Socio-Legal Course Descriptions Socio-Legal Course Descriptions Updated 12/19/2013 Required Courses for Socio-Legal Studies Major: PLSC 1810: Introduction to Law and Society This course addresses justifications and explanations for regulation

More information

Observations on The Sedona Principles

Observations on The Sedona Principles Observations on The Sedona Principles John L. Carroll Dean, Cumberland School of Law, Samford Univerity, Birmingham AL Kenneth J. Withers Research Associate, Federal Judicial Center, Washington DC The

More information

The Scope of the Rule of Law and the Prosecutor some general principles and challenges

The Scope of the Rule of Law and the Prosecutor some general principles and challenges The Scope of the Rule of Law and the Prosecutor some general principles and challenges It gives me great pleasure to speak today at the 18 th Annual Conference and General Meeting of the International

More information

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED David Brink Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER David Brink examines the views of legal positivism and natural law theory

More information

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. Political Philosophy, Spring 2003, 1 The Terrain of a Global Normative Order 1. Realism and Normative Order Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. According to

More information

IS STARE DECISIS A CONSTRAINT OR A CLOAK?

IS STARE DECISIS A CONSTRAINT OR A CLOAK? Copyright 2007 Ave Maria Law Review IS STARE DECISIS A CONSTRAINT OR A CLOAK? THE POLITICS OF PRECEDENT ON THE U.S. SUPREME COURT. By Thomas G. Hansford & James F. Spriggs II. Princeton University Press.

More information

Impression Products, Inc. v. Lexmark International, Inc.: A Glib Rebuke of the Federal Circuit

Impression Products, Inc. v. Lexmark International, Inc.: A Glib Rebuke of the Federal Circuit GW Law Faculty Publications & Other Works Faculty Scholarship 2017 Impression Products, Inc. v. Lexmark International, Inc.: A Glib Rebuke of the Federal Circuit Andrew Michaels The George Washington University

More information

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously Yale Law School Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship Series Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1978 The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously Jules L. Coleman Yale

More information

PHIL 168: Philosophy of Law UCSD; Fall 2015 Prof. David O. Brink Handout #2: Hart's Model of Rules and Legal Realism

PHIL 168: Philosophy of Law UCSD; Fall 2015 Prof. David O. Brink Handout #2: Hart's Model of Rules and Legal Realism Draft of 9-23- 15 PHIL 168: Philosophy of Law UCSD; Fall 2015 Prof. David O. Brink Handout #2: Hart's Model of Rules and Legal Realism Hart develops his own conception of the nature of law in the wake

More information

Bounded Rationality and Behavioralism: A Clarification and Critique

Bounded Rationality and Behavioralism: A Clarification and Critique Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics (JITE) 146 (1990). 691 6 95 Zeitschrift fiir die gesamte Staatswissenschaft Bounded Rationality and Behavioralism: A Clarification and Critique Viewed

More information

CONSUMER ARBITRATION AGREEMENTS AND COLLECTIVE ACTION WAIVERS: WHY THE SUPREME COURT S DEFENSE OF ARBITRATION HAS GONE TOO FAR

CONSUMER ARBITRATION AGREEMENTS AND COLLECTIVE ACTION WAIVERS: WHY THE SUPREME COURT S DEFENSE OF ARBITRATION HAS GONE TOO FAR CONSUMER ARBITRATION AGREEMENTS AND COLLECTIVE ACTION WAIVERS: WHY THE SUPREME COURT S DEFENSE OF ARBITRATION HAS GONE TOO FAR Alexander C. Hyder * ARBITRATION AGREEMENTS COLLECTIVE ACTION WAIVERS FEDERAL

More information

Inverse Condemnation and the Law of Waters

Inverse Condemnation and the Law of Waters Inverse Condemnation and the Law of Waters DANIEL R. MANDELKER School of Law, Washington University, St. Louis, Mo. This paper deals with research on recent trends of legislation and court decisions pertaining

More information

How Italian Colors Guts Private Antitrust Enforcement by Replacing It With Ineffective Forms Of Arbitration

How Italian Colors Guts Private Antitrust Enforcement by Replacing It With Ineffective Forms Of Arbitration How Italian Colors Guts Private Antitrust Enforcement by Replacing It With Ineffective Forms Of Arbitration The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits

More information

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Politics (2000) 20(1) pp. 19 24 Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Colin Farrelly 1 In this paper I explore a possible response to G.A. Cohen s critique of the Rawlsian defence of inequality-generating

More information

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory The problem with the argument for stability: In his discussion

More information

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Cite as: 560 U. S. (2010) 1 SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES No. 08 1151 STOP THE BEACH RENOURISHMENT, INC., PETITIONER v. FLORIDA DEPARTMENT OF ENVIRONMENTAL PROTECTION ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI

More information

Steve Subrin 30 Birch Hill Rd. Newton, MA U.S.A. Office: Fax: Home:

Steve Subrin 30 Birch Hill Rd. Newton, MA U.S.A. Office: Fax: Home: 30 Birch Hill Rd. Newton, MA 02465 U.S.A. Office: 617 373 3923 Fax: 617 373 5056 Home: 617 527 5926 E-mail: s.subrin@neu.edu MAJOR PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE Professor of Law, Northeastern University School

More information

Trusts Law 463 Fall Term 2013 INTRODUCTORY NOTES

Trusts Law 463 Fall Term 2013 INTRODUCTORY NOTES Trusts Law 463 Fall Term 2013 INTRODUCTORY NOTES LAW & EQUITY Trusts are a part of the law known as Equity. Equity in this context does not mean social fairness, its contemporary meaning. Rather, equity

More information

Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review

Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review Fordham Law Review Volume 69 Issue 6 Article 3 2001 Response to Robert P. George, Natural Law, the Constitution, and the Theory and Practice of Judicial Review Joseph W. Koterski Recommended Citation Joseph

More information

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS ROBERT ANOSHKA, Personal Representative of the Estate of GARY ANOSHKA, UNPUBLISHED April 19, 2011 Plaintiff-Appellant, v No. 296595 Oakland Circuit Court Family Division

More information

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall

Lahore University of Management Sciences. Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall Phil 323/Pol 305 Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy Fall 2013-14 Instructor Anwar ul Haq Room No. 219, new SS wing Office Hours TBA Email anwarul.haq@lums.edu.pk Telephone Ext. 8221 Secretary/TA

More information

Legal Change: Integrating Selective Litigation, Judicial Preferences, and Precedent

Legal Change: Integrating Selective Litigation, Judicial Preferences, and Precedent University of Connecticut DigitalCommons@UConn Economics Working Papers Department of Economics 6-1-2004 Legal Change: Integrating Selective Litigation, Judicial Preferences, and Precedent Thomas J. Miceli

More information

Premise. The social mission and objectives

Premise. The social mission and objectives Premise The Code of Ethics is a charter of moral rights and duties that defines the ethical and social responsibility of all those who maintain relationships with Coopsalute. This document clearly explains

More information

CLIENT-LAWYER RELATIONSHIP MODEL RULE 1.2

CLIENT-LAWYER RELATIONSHIP MODEL RULE 1.2 CLIENT-LAWYER RELATIONSHIP MODEL RULE 1.2 1 RULE 1.2 SCOPE OF REPRESENTATION AND ALLOCATION OF AUTHORITY BETWEEN CLIENT AND LAWYER (a) Subject to paragraphs (c) and (d), a lawyer shall abide by a client's

More information

Chapter 2 Treaty Interpretation as Opposed to Statutory, Constitutional and Contractual Interpretations

Chapter 2 Treaty Interpretation as Opposed to Statutory, Constitutional and Contractual Interpretations Chapter 2 Treaty Interpretation as Opposed to Statutory, Constitutional and Contractual Interpretations Contents 2.1 Interpretation of Different Legal Texts... 17 2.1.1 Different Legal Texts Needed Interpretation...

More information

TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER

TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER TUSHNET-----Introduction THE IDEA OF A CONSTITUTIONAL ORDER President Bill Clinton announced in his 1996 State of the Union Address that [t]he age of big government is over. 1 Many Republicans thought

More information

DISSENTING OPINIONS. Yale Law Journal. Volume 14 Issue 4 Yale Law Journal. Article 1

DISSENTING OPINIONS. Yale Law Journal. Volume 14 Issue 4 Yale Law Journal. Article 1 Yale Law Journal Volume 14 Issue 4 Yale Law Journal Article 1 1905 DISSENTING OPINIONS Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/ylj Recommended Citation DISSENTING OPINIONS,

More information

NAPD Formal Ethics Opinion 16-1

NAPD Formal Ethics Opinion 16-1 NAPD Formal Ethics Opinion 16-1 Question: The Ethics Counselors of the National Association for Public Defense (NAPD) have been asked to address the following scenario: An investigator working for Defense

More information

COPYRIGHT 2009 THE LAW PROFESSOR

COPYRIGHT 2009 THE LAW PROFESSOR CIVIL PROCEDURE SHOPPING LIST OF ISSUES FOR CIVIL PROCEDURE Professor Gould s Shopping List for Civil Procedure. 1. Pleadings. 2. Personal Jurisdiction. 3. Subject Matter Jurisdiction. 4. Amended Pleadings.

More information

WHAT IS HEARSAY AND WHY DO WE CARE?

WHAT IS HEARSAY AND WHY DO WE CARE? WHAT IS HEARSAY AND WHY DO WE CARE? I. WHAT IS HEARSAY? The definition of hearsay is set forth in Rule 801(c ) of the North Carolina Rules of Evidence as follows: HEARSAY IS A STATEMENT, OTHER THAN ONE

More information

No Free Lunch: How Settlement can Reduce the Legal System's Ability to Induce Efficient Behavior

No Free Lunch: How Settlement can Reduce the Legal System's Ability to Induce Efficient Behavior SMU Law Review Volume 61 Issue 4 Article 2 2008 No Free Lunch: How Settlement can Reduce the Legal System's Ability to Induce Efficient Behavior Ezra Freidman Abraham L. Wickelgren Follow this and additional

More information

C. Sources of Law: Common Law, Stare Decisis and the System of Precedent

C. Sources of Law: Common Law, Stare Decisis and the System of Precedent C. Sources of Law: Common Law, Stare Decisis and the System of Precedent The United States legal system is rooted in English common law which began to develop in the eleventh century. The common law was

More information

Italy Orsingher-Avvocati Associati

Italy Orsingher-Avvocati Associati Orsingher-Avvocati Associati This text first appeared in the IAM magazine supplement Patents in Europe 2008 April 2008 Italy By Matteo Orsingher and Fabrizio Sanna, Orsingher-Avvocati Associati, Milan

More information

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt *

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt * ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE Steven Walt * D ISTRIBUTIVE justice describes the morally required distribution of shares of resources and liberty among people. Corrective justice describes the moral obligation

More information

Code of Administrative Justice 2003

Code of Administrative Justice 2003 Public Report No. 42 March 2003 to the Legislative Assembly of British Columbia Code of Administrative Justice 2003 National Library of Canada Cataloguing in Publication Data British Columbia. Office of

More information

The Aggregation Problem for Deliberative Democracy. Philip Pettit

The Aggregation Problem for Deliberative Democracy. Philip Pettit 1 The Aggregation Problem for Deliberative Democracy Philip Pettit Introduction Deliberating about what to do is often cast as an alternative to aggregating people s preferences or opinions over what to

More information

Management prerogatives, plant closings, and the NLRA: A response

Management prerogatives, plant closings, and the NLRA: A response NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository School of Law Faculty Publications Northeastern University School of Law 1-1-1983 Management prerogatives, plant closings, and the NLRA: A response Karl E. Klare

More information

UNITED STATES V. MATTHEWS ET AL. [2 Betts, C. C. MS. 49.] Circuit Court, S. D. New York. Dec. 18, 1843.

UNITED STATES V. MATTHEWS ET AL. [2 Betts, C. C. MS. 49.] Circuit Court, S. D. New York. Dec. 18, 1843. YesWeScan: The FEDERAL CASES UNITED STATES V. MATTHEWS ET AL. Case No. 15,741b. [2 Betts, C. C. MS. 49.] Circuit Court, S. D. New York. Dec. 18, 1843. CRIMINAL LAW JOINT INDICTMENT SEPARATE TRIALS DRAWING

More information

Spinning the Legislative Veto

Spinning the Legislative Veto Georgetown University Law Center Scholarship @ GEORGETOWN LAW 1984 Spinning the Legislative Veto Girardeau A. Spann Georgetown University Law Center, spann@law.georgetown.edu This paper can be downloaded

More information

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* 219 Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* Laura Valentini London School of Economics and Political Science 1. Introduction Kok-Chor Tan s review essay offers an internal critique of

More information

The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts

The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts Washington University Law Review Volume 73 Issue 3 Northwestern University / Washington University Law and Linguistics Conference 1995 The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts

More information

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS ISSN 1045-6333 A SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF NUISANCE SUITS: THE OPTION TO HAVE THE COURT BAR SETTLEMENT David Rosenberg Steven Shavell Discussion

More information

Warner-Jenkinson Co. v. Hilton-Davis Chemical Co.:

Warner-Jenkinson Co. v. Hilton-Davis Chemical Co.: Warner-Jenkinson Co. v. Hilton-Davis Chemical Co.: Apt Reconciliation of Supreme Court Precedent, and Reasoned Instruction to a Trusted Federal Circuit 1997 by Charles W. Shifley and Lance Johnson On March

More information

RPC RULE 1.5 FEES. (3) the fee customarily charged in the locality for similar legal services;

RPC RULE 1.5 FEES. (3) the fee customarily charged in the locality for similar legal services; RPC RULE 1.5 FEES (a) A lawyer shall not make an agreement for, charge, or collect an unreasonable fee or an unreasonable amount for expenses. The factors to be considered in determining the reasonableness

More information

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle

The Conflict between Notions of Fairness and the Pareto Principle NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository Harvard Law School John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business Discussion Paper Series Harvard Law School 3-7-1999 The Conflict between Notions of Fairness

More information

Unit 03. Ngo Quy Nham Foreign Trade University

Unit 03. Ngo Quy Nham Foreign Trade University Unit 03 Ngo Quy Nham Foreign Trade University The process by which managers identify organisational problems and try to resolve them. Identifying a problem Identifying decision criteria Allocating weight

More information

Debating Deliberative Democracy

Debating Deliberative Democracy Philosophy, Politics and Society 7 Debating Deliberative Democracy Edited by JAMES S. FISHKIN AND PETER LASLETT Debating Deliberative Democracy Dedicated to the memory of Peter Laslett, 1915 2001, who

More information

The One-dimensional View

The One-dimensional View Power in its most generic sense simply means the capacity to bring about significant effects: to effect changes or prevent them. The effects of social and political power will be those that are of significance

More information

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Cite as: 563 U. S. (2011) 1 SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES No. 09 834 KEVIN KASTEN, PETITIONER v. SAINT-GOBAIN PERFORMANCE PLASTICS CORPORATION ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS

More information

The Other State s Interests

The Other State s Interests Cornell International Law Journal Volume 24 Issue 2 Spring 1991 Article 3 The Other State s Interests Lea Brilmayer Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/cilj Part of

More information

Regulatory Coordinating Committee

Regulatory Coordinating Committee Regulatory Coordinating Committee On November 5, 1996, the Section submitted comments to the General Services Administration regarding its proposed rule on procurement integrity. The proposed rule would

More information

OREGON LAW COMMISSION

OREGON LAW COMMISSION OREGON LAW COMMISSION INFORMATION ITEM 2000-1 July, 2000 A Report to the Statutes of Limitations Work Group regarding statutory time limitations on product liability actions From The Office of the Executive

More information

Foreword to Reviews (Books on the Law of Contracts)

Foreword to Reviews (Books on the Law of Contracts) University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 2014 Foreword to Reviews (Books on the Law of Contracts) Lisa E. Bernstein Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles

More information

Introduction to The Revision of Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code Symposium

Introduction to The Revision of Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code Symposium William & Mary Law Review Volume 35 Issue 4 Article 2 Introduction to The Revision of Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code Symposium Peter A. Alces William & Mary Law School, paalce@wm.edu Repository

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Any Frequency of Plaintiff Victory at Trial Is Possible Author(s): Steven Shavell Source: The Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 25, No. 2 (Jun., 1996), pp. 493-501 Published by: The University of Chicago

More information

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak

Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak DOI 10.1007/s11572-008-9046-5 ORIGINAL PAPER Justifying Punishment: A Response to Douglas Husak Kimberley Brownlee Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008 Abstract In Why Criminal Law: A Question of

More information

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Playing Fair and Following the Rules JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY brill.com/jmp Playing Fair and Following the Rules Justin Tosi Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan jtosi@umich.edu Abstract In his paper Fairness, Political Obligation,

More information

Expedited Procedures in the House: Variations Enacted into Law

Expedited Procedures in the House: Variations Enacted into Law Expedited Procedures in the House: Variations Enacted into Law Christopher M. Davis Analyst on Congress and the Legislative Process September 16, 2015 Congressional Research Service 7-5700 www.crs.gov

More information