Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? A Non-Essentialist Socio-Legal Positivist Analysis of the Concept of Law

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? A Non-Essentialist Socio-Legal Positivist Analysis of the Concept of Law"

Transcription

1 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 24, No. 4 (2004), pp Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? A Non-Essentialist Socio-Legal Positivist Analysis of the Concept of Law KENNETH EINAR HIMMA In A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society, Brian Z. Tamanaha articulates and defends a socio-legal positivism that recognizes the myriad ways in which the concept of law is conventionally used. As he describes it, socio-legal positivism holds that a legal system exists whenever there are legal actors (conventionally identi- Wed as such) engaged in producing and reproducing a legal system through shared secondary rules, regardless of their eycacy in generating widespread conformity to the primary rules, regardless of their evectiveness, or lack thereof, in maintaining social order. 1 Ordinary linguistic usage, then, plays a central role in determining the content of the concept of law. Tamanaha concludes that [l]aw is whatever people identify and treat through their social practices as law (or droit, recht, etc.) (GJ 166; emphasis omitted). Socio-legal positivism is usefully characterized in terms of its relationship to Hartian positivism. Like Hartian positivism, socio-legal positivism accepts the Separability Thesis and the Social Fact Thesis, which, taken together, explain the content of law as manufactured through coordinated social practices of some sort. 2 Unlike Hartian positivism, socio-legal positivism denies the following claims: (1) law has institutional features that are essential to its being characterized as law ; (2) law has something that is plausibly characterized as the function of law; (3) it is a conceptually necessary condition for the existence of a legal system that oycials accept the norms dewning the legality criteria as standards governing their behaviour; and (4) it is a conceptually necessary condition for the existence of law that legal norms are eycacious in guiding citizen behaviour. A Review of Brian Z. Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society (Oxford University Press, 2001). I am indebted to Brian Tamanaha and Julie Dickson for very helpful comments. 1 Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society, 148. Hereinafter GJ. 2 The Separability Thesis asserts that there are no necessary moral constraints on the content of law, while the Social Fact Thesis asserts that the content of law is manufactured according to social processes. Tamanaha seems to accept both: the existence and content of law is determined by some range of facts about human beings in a social setting facts about their behaviour, history, institutions, beliefs, and attitudes (GJ ; quoting David Lyons, Moral Aspects of Legal Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993)), 77. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 24, No. 4, Oxford University Press 2004; all rights reserved

2 718 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 In addition, socio-legal positivism denies the claim, highly inxuential among legal sociologists, that the content of law mirrors the content of prevailing social norms. As is readily evident, socio-legal positivism can fairly be characterized, to use a term coined by Frederick Schauer, as an extremely thin version of Hartian positivism. 3 Tamanaha s project is an ambitious one that criticizes and defends a number of diverent kinds of claim. Some of these claims are, as one would expect from a legal sociologist, contingent, descriptive, and empirical in character; a claim about what law characteristically does is an empirical claim about what most legal systems do. Others are necessary and conceptual in character; claims about essential characteristics or functions purport to be true of every conceptually possible legal system. Indeed, the breadth of Tamanaha s project can be seen in the range of theorists whose views he takes on. Tamanaha s targets include not only conceptual theorists like Joseph Raz, Ronald Dworkin and H.L.A. Hart, but also sociologists like Emile Durkheim. Tamanaha s book overs important conceptual, philosophical, and sociological insights into law; as such, it is an important contribution to both the philosophical and sociological literature a very impressive feat. The writing is clear; and the arguments for both the sociological and philosophical claims are rigorous, detailed, and nuanced. For these reasons, I recommend it, without reservations, to both legal philosophers and sociologists. Nevertheless, I argue below that the book s sociological arguments are more successful than the conceptual arguments. 4 Although Tamanaha s sociological analysis succeeds in refuting the traditional sociological view of the relationship between law and society, his conceptual analysis is somewhat less successful as a challenge to Hartian positivism. In particular, I argue that his view that [l]aw is whatever people identify and treat through their social practices as law is far too thin to be theoretically adequate as an account of the concept of law. 1. The Mirror and Function Theses As the title announces, Tamanaha s aim is to construct what he calls a general jurisprudence of law and society. At least part of this complex idea will be quite familiar to theorists who spend their time attempting to explain the concepts that Wgure centrally in legal practice which, of course, includes the concept of law itself. As Austin and then Hart explained it, a general jurisprudence purports to identify and explain elements central to law in the following sense: any normative system that lacks one of these elements is simply not accurately 3 Frederick Schauer, Positivism through Thick and Thin in Brian Bix (ed), Analyzing Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998). 4 Even so, Tamanaha hits the bull s-eye on at least one critically important positivist doctrine: the Hartian claim that it is a necessary condition for the existence of a legal system that it be minimally eycacious in regulating the behaviour of citizens. See below at 730.

3 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 719 described as law. Thus, it is not just that these elements are present in every conceivable legal system; it is rather that the very presence of such elements in a system, taken together, warrant characterizing it as a system of law. Nevertheless, it is important not to be misled by the reference to conceptual jurisprudence. Tamanaha s goal is not simply, or even principally, to produce an analysis of legal concepts as positivists, constructive interpretivists, and natural law theorists strive to do. Rather, Tamanaha s primary concern is to explain the relations between law and society at a suyciently high level of generality to be applicable to all possible societies and legal systems. The stated goal is to construct a general jurisprudence of law and society and merely explaining the concepts that are central to law and legal practice does not have any obvious connection to the relationship between law and society. Tamanaha s discussion is organized around an evaluation of two theses that, taken together, make up what he takes to be the traditional view of law and society. The Wrst is the Mirror Thesis. As Tamanaha states this thesis, law is a rexection a mirror of society (GJ 1). On this conception of the relationship between law and society, the content of the law rexects the content of various social norms and practices that govern life in the society. The second thesis is the Function Thesis. As Tamanaha describes this thesis, law maintains social order by establishing and enforcing the rules of social intercourse, and by resolving disputes (GJ 2). Thus stated, the idea is that law has some central or essential purpose that is concerned with maintaining social order by enforcing rules that mirror other socially accepted norms. Tamanaha argues that both claims are taken for granted by many legal theorists especially those in working in empirical areas of legal theory like legal sociology. Endorsing the Mirror Thesis, legal sociologist Lawrence Friedman asserts that necessarily, [legal systems] rexect what is happening in their own societies. 5 Endorsing one strong version of the Function Thesis, sociologist David Dudley Field argues Where there is no law there can be no order, since order is but another name for regularity, or conformity to rule. 6 Although we will see that the Mirror and Function Theses can be interpreted in a number of ways, the theorists quoted above interpret them as making very strong claims about the content and purpose of law. Tamanaha believes that each of these theses is problematic and attempts to show both should be rejected. Though most of the discussion in the book is directed at evaluating the Mirror and Function Theses, Tamanaha s principal concern is to articulate his own socio-legal positivist jurisprudence of law and society. He treats the traditional view that consists of these two theses as a foil 5 Lawrence Friedman, Borders: On the Emerging Sociology of Transnational Law, Stanford Journal of International Law, vol 32, no. 1 (1996) 72; quoted at GJ 2. 6 David Dudley Field, Magnitude and Importance of Legal Science in S.B. Presser and J.S. Zainaldin (eds), Law and Jurisprudence (St. Paul, MN: West Publishing, 1995) 713; quoted at GJ 2 3.

4 720 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 for the development of his own positive views on law, society, and the relationship between them. 2. The Plan of the Book In Chapter 1, Tamanaha sets out the general framework for the discussion. The Wrst component requires an elaboration of the Mirror and Function Theses. The second outlines traditional views on the relationship between law and society in terms of the relationships between three basic elements: Custom/Consent; Morality/Reason; and Positive Law, which Tamanaha describes as the rules articulated and enforced by an institutionalized authority (GJ 4). As Tamanaha describes the traditional views: [A]s characterized by Western legal and social theory, the relations among these three elements are complex and far-ranging. They are thought to have a shared origin; they are thought to rexect one another, to feed or inxuence one another, and to determine the eycacy of one another. The relations between custom/consent and positive law, and between morality/reason and positive law, are parallel in many respects, especially with regard to the issue of legitimation. Coinciding with this general intimacy and with their mutually supporting relations, these three elements also exist in tension as competing sources of power and authority, overlapping one another in their reach (GJ 9). Chapter 2 shows the inxuence of the traditional view in Western legal theory. Tamanaha begins by showing that the principal elements of the view, including the Mirror and Function Theses as well as the analytic framework described above, are all present in Plato s and Aristotle s work. Further, he argues that the principal elements of this view are present in both neo-classical natural law and legal positivism. 7 Natural law theory is sometimes interpreted as claiming that it is conceptually impossible for there to be unjust law, suggesting that the content of the law, though universal and based in reason, is not necessarily responsive to the contingent customs of any particular society. But a more modest interpretation holds only that unjust laws are inconsistent with certain moral ideals of legitimacy; the more modest interpretation, then, recognizes that diverent legal systems contain diverent legal norms that mirror the accepted customs. Positivist theories, on Tamanaha s view, are more explicit in emphasizing the connection between the content of law and the content of the accepted social morality. As Hart put it in The Concept of Law, The law of every modern state shows at a thousand points the inxuence of both the accepted morality and wider moral ideas. 8 Tamanaha Wnishes the chapter by arguing that the traditional view is 7 Tamanaha does not address the issue of whether these elements are present in Dworkin s third theory of law. It is worth noting that Dworkin argues that the law of a community includes those principles of law that, as an objective moral matter, show the pre-existing legal materials and institutional history in the best moral light (i.e. come nearest to, as an objective moral matter, justifying the coercive enforcement of the law). See Ronald Dworkin, Law s Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). 8 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Rev. edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 199. Hereinafter CL.

5 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 721 presupposed, to a greater or lesser extent, by comparative law theories, legalsociological theories, and even Marxian theories. In Chapter 3, Tamanaha argues against two myths that explain the origin of legal systems in ways that suggest the content of the law will rexect the prevailing social norms and customs. According to the evolutionary myth, systems of law evolve naturally out of simpler forms of social organization grounded in the acceptance of customary norms; when these simpler forms of social organization can no longer evectively regulate behaviour, formal centralized structures arise to ensure the continuing obedience of citizens to the customary norms. According to the social contract myth, systems of law originate as the outcome of an agreement that takes place at some particular moment (or moments) in time. Tamanaha rejects these theories on historical grounds in favour of a theory that explains the origin of law as the outcome of conxicts in which one group seeks to impose its will on another. While Tamanaha concedes that some legal systems might have originated in the ways described by the two myths, he argues that [t]he majority of state legal systems in existence today originated through imposition from outside or were created by imitation by local authorities to meet the threat posed by conquest from outside powers (GJ 69). Chapter 4 describes a number of important changes in the way legal theorists and practitioners conceive the proper relationships between law and social norms. According to Tamanaha, scepticism about the objectivity of morality and the ability of reason to discern ultimate goods has contributed to the decreasing relevance of morality in the decisions of legal practitioners, such as judges and legislators. In addition, he argues that the growth of bodies of law that, at best, connect only tenuously with community standards and customs has diminished the role of these norms in shaping the content of the law; business law, administrative law, and law constraining legislative activity lack any substantial foundation in social customs, which are contrived to deal with radically diverent problems. Reliance on the content of custom has increasingly been supplanted by democratic procedures; subject consent is increasingly inferred from democratic participation instead of from the incorporation of widely accepted social norms into the law. Indeed, according to Tamanaha, the formal ideal of the rule of law which is consistent with considerable immorality in the content of law has replaced substantive moral constraints on lawmaking activities as law s chief legitimizing rationale. Chapter 5 consists largely of empirical arguments against the Mirror Thesis. First, Tamanaha points out that many existing legal systems have imported bodies of law from other legal systems. In particular, many colonized nations, such as India, have retained the legal systems and bodies of law that were imposed upon them by colonizing nations, despite the lack of social continuity between them. Second, non-state systems of law tend in many nations to be more evective in regulating behaviour than the oycially sanctioned legal system precisely because the content of state law does not suyciently rexect the content

6 722 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 of prevailing social norms. Finally, the trend towards increasing social, political, and economic globalization has resulted in a trend towards increasing homogeneity in the content of the law of participating nations. In many instances, the desire to reap the benewts of a global economy has led many nations to enact laws rexecting economic and social realities of radically diverent cultures. Local customs and mores, on Tamanaha s view, do not play even a minimal role in shaping these bodies of law. In Chapter 6, Tamanaha develops his socio-legal positivist approach to law that he believes avoids problems that plague Hartian positivism. The discussion in this chapter is organized around a sustained critique of Hartian positivism that focuses on tensions among four central elements: (1) the meta-conventionalist 9 claim that ordinary linguistic usage determines the social phenomena to which the term law is correctly applied; (2) the conventionalist claim that the content of the legality criteria is determined by a conventional rule of recognition; 10 (3) the essentialist claim that certain features of law (such as the existence of a conventional rule of recognition) are essential to law; and (4) the functionalist claim that the function of law, as Hart put it, is to provid[e] guides to human conduct and standards of criticism of such conduct (CL 249). The most important elements of Tamanaha s critique are as follows. First, on his view, the functionalist claim clashes with the essentialist claim because institutional systems lacking the essential features of law can perform law s function and because institutional systems with the essential features of law can fail to perform law s function. Second, the conventionalist claim is in tension with the functionalist claim because [a] given function can be satiswed by any number of conceivable practices (GJ 149). Third, the meta-conventionalist claim is in tension with the essentialist claim because the claim that ordinary usage determines the content of the concept law seems inconsistent with there being any essential features of law (i.e., features that are necessary to law and legal systems). Tamanaha concludes that [law] has no essence (193). Tamanaha s view that law is whatever people call law is an attempt to incorporate the insights of Hart s conventionalist claims while rejecting his functionalist and essentialist claims. As Tamanaha points out, people may conventionally designate as law an institutional system of norms that fails to perform the function of guiding behaviour because people look to other systems of norms for supreme guidance; people in Yap, Micronesia, have very little idea of what the law requires or prohibits. Likewise, people may conventionally identify systems as systems of law despite the fact that they lack certain features thought to be 9 The terminology here is mine. 10 The terms legality criteria and rule of recognition refer to diverent abstract propositional entities though they are obviously related in important ways. For a discussion of the distinction between the two, see Kenneth Einar Himma, Final Authority to Bind with Moral Mistakes: On the Explanatory Potential of Inclusive Legal Positivism forthcoming in Law and Philosophy; and Kenneth Einar Himma, Making Sense of Constitutional Disagreement: Legal Positivism, the Bill of Rights, and the Conventional Rule of Recognition in the United States, Journal of Law in Society, vol. 4, no. 2 (Winter 2003),

7 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 723 essential to law; people might, for example, identify a system as law despite the fact that it lacks a centralized mechanism for coercive enforcement or despite the fact that it lacks a monopoly on such enforcement. Socio-legal positivism is consistent with characterizing such practices, norms, and systems as legal in character precisely because it rejects Hart s functionalist and essentialist claims. 11 Chapter 7 attempts to reconcile socio-legal positivism with the legal pluralist view, nearly unquestioned among legal sociologists, that there can be, and frequently are, many legal systems operating within one society. Such systems include the legal system that gives rise to the state, of course, but they can also include systems of indigenous customary norms accepted as, and designated by, theoretically signiwcant portions of the population as law. Tamanaha believes that essentialist concepts of law are diycult to reconcile with legal pluralism because they limit the application of law to only systems that satisfy a laundry list of essential features, which may exclude systems that are recognized, accepted, and treated within a society as legal systems. In contrast, Tamanaha s non-essentialist, conventionalist analysis of law is clearly compatible with legal pluralism because it recognizes as law whatever people attach the label law to. To the extent that law is applied to a plurality of systems within a society, Tamanaha s analysis entails that there is a plurality of legal systems within that society. 12 The last chapter sets out the elements of a general jurisprudence that is broad enough to accommodate the diversity of both legal institutions and social living. To this end, Tamanaha rejects the concept of society in favor of a more general concept of social arena; the boundaries of the concept can be drawn in any way desired [and] as determined by the purposes of the study (GJ 207). Additionally, Tamanaha describes a number of diverent sources of social order: (1) an unarticulated and unrexective substrate of shared habits, modes of action, and practices; (2) shared norms; (3) self-interested instrumental behaviour that leads to mutually benewcial voluntary exchanges; (4) agreements; (5) feelings of social identiwcation and attachment (including love, altruism, and group identiwcation); and (6) coercion. Finally, Tamanaha lists a typology of various kinds of law, which include state law, customary law, religious law, international law, and transnational law. Tamanaha concludes the book by articulating what he takes to be the core questions for sociological investigation about law. As Tamanaha puts it, [f]or any given social arena, the core questions posed will be: (1) to what extent is 11 It is worth reiterating that socio-legal positivism shares with legal positivism its commitment to the ideas (1) that there are no necessary moral constraints on the content of law (the Separability Thesis) and (2) that the content of law is ultimately manufactured according to social processes (the Social Fact Thesis). 12 For an interesting attempt to reconcile legal pluralism with Hartian positivism, see Detlef von Daniels, Is Positivism a State-Centered Theory? in Kenneth Einar Himma (ed), Law, Morality, and Legal Positivism (Proceedings of the 21st World Congress of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy), Franz Steiner Verlag, forthcoming 2004.

8 724 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 (state, customary, international, religious, natural, indigenous, etc.) law a mirror of prevailing customs and morals? and (2) to what extent does... law contribute to the maintenance of the social order (GJ 231)? The underlying idea is that the extent to which law mirrors society to maintain social order will diver from one society to the next. In some social arenas, the norms of law will closely rexect other norms; in others, there will be little resemblance between legal and other social norms. 3. The Critique of the Mirror Thesis To get a sense for whether Tamanaha s critique of the Mirror Thesis succeeds, we need a clear sense of what this claim amounts to. The claim is stated in a number of diverent ways throughout the book: (1) law is a rexection a mirror of society (GJ 1); (2) a society s law will rexect its patterns of life and morality (GJ 2) 13 ; (3) the law of every modern state shows at a thousand points the inxuence of both the accepted social morality and wider moral ideas (GJ 2; quoting Hart, CL 199); and (4) law rexects/mirrors society (GJ 51). As it turns out, there are a number of very diverent interpretations of this claim. For his part, Tamanaha observes that the Mirror Thesis is ambiguous between a number of interpretations: William Ewald observed that there are strong versions of the mirror thesis Law is nothing but X, Law is wholly explicable in terms of X and there are weaker versions Law and X are closely related. And he noted that there are diverent dimensions of mirroring, whereby X can be Wlled in with economics, culture, politics, climate, and geography, or some combination thereof (GJ 51). As it turns out, there are considerably more interpretations than are suggested in this passage. In addition to the determining which set of norms are being mirrored, there are at least three more important areas of ambiguity in the statements of the Mirror Thesis quoted in the Wrst paragraph of this section, leading to a very large number of interpretations. First, it is not clear exactly what kind of modality is being expressed. On one construction, the Mirror Thesis expresses a necessary truth of some kind and there are three possibilities here: logical, conceptual, or causal. 14 On this construction, it is a logically/conceptually/ nomologically necessary truth that the content of the law in any given society rexects the content of its social norms and customs. On another construction, the Mirror Thesis expresses a contingent truth that is grounded in empirical 13 Tamanaha is quoting Kent Greenawalt, Law and Objectivity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992) A proposition is a logically necessary truth if it is not possible for it to be false no matter what the world might otherwise have been like; e.g. the proposition expressed by either Sam is in the room or Sam is not in the room is logically necessary. A proposition is a conceptually necessary truth if it is logically implied by propositions that express the content of some concept; e.g. the proposition expressed by laws are norms is conceptually necessary. A proposition is a nomologically necessary truth if it is logically implied by the causal laws that are true of this world; e.g. the proposition that expresses some general truth about gravitational force is nomologically necessary.

9 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 725 observations: in most/all observed legal systems, the content of the law rexects the content of the prevailing social norms and customs. Since, strictly speaking, the empirical construction applies only to existing legal systems, a third construction can be distinguished that states a probabilistic thesis about future legal systems: it is likely that the content of the law in future legal systems will also rexect the content of the prevailing social norms and customs. Second, it is not clear exactly how much of the law must rexect or mirror prevailing social norms to satisfy the Mirror Thesis. On one construction, the content of every single law rexects/mirrors the content of prevailing social norms. Though this interpretation is obviously quite strong, the use of the term mirror suggests such a construction. My image in a looking glass mirrors my appearance in the following sense: the appearance of every feature of my rexection in the looking glass closely resembles the appearance of some feature of me, and the appearance of every feature of me closely resembles the appearance of some feature of my rexection in the looking glass. On another construction, the content of most laws rexects/mirrors the content of the prevailing social norms. On the weakest construction, the content of a theoretically signiwcant number (large enough to warrant the supposition, at the very least, that it is not an accident or chance occurrence) of laws rexects/mirrors the content of prevailing social norms. Third, it is not clear what is meant by the terms rexect and mirror. On one construction, a law rexects/mirrors prevailing social norms if and only if the content of the law reproduces the content of some prevailing social norm or norms. On another construction, a law rexects/mirrors prevailing social norms if and only if the content of the law is logically consistent with the content of the set of prevailing social norms. A law that reproduces the content of some social norm is consistent with prevailing social norms (assuming the social norms themselves are consistent), but a law need not reproduce the content of some norm to be consistent with the set of social norms (assuming the set of social norms is not complete in the sense that there is a norm that governs every pair of alternative behaviours). Much, of course, turns on how we interpret the Mirror Thesis. On the one hand, the very strongest interpretation is wildly implausible. On this interpretation, it is a logically necessary truth that every law in every legal system reproduces the content of some prevailing social norm or norms; that is, the claim that some law does not reproduce the content of some prevailing social norm or norms is selfcontradictory. Such an interpretation, of course, cannot be reconciled with ordinary intuitions and practices regarding law and use of the associated concepts. Whether the US federal statute prohibiting unauthorized computer intrusions is a law has absolutely nothing to do with whether its content reproduces the content of a social norm in force among some segment of the population; it counts as law regardless of whether there is a corresponding social norm being practiced in the US.

10 726 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 It is true that Hart seems to endorse a modal version of the Mirror Thesis, but this version is much weaker than the strongest version and is not really part of his core views about law. H.L.A. Hart suggested more as a working hypothesis than as some sort of Wrm conviction about an immutable truth that there are certain rules that had, as a matter of natural necessity, to be part of the law in order to do what law normally does. He called such norms (which include, e.g. norms prohibiting violence and theft) the minimum content of the natural law. But this version is much weaker than the strongest version described above in two respects. First, the character of the modality, as Tamanaha is careful to observe, is causal rather than conceptual or logical; Hart hypothesized that the law could not be causally eycacious in regulating human behaviour if it did not contain certain rules protecting human survival. Second, there was nothing in Hart s view that implied even that the content of many, much less most, laws had to incorporate the content of some pre-existing social norms; as far as Hart s view was concerned, the minimum content of the natural law could represent a very small portion say 1% of the content of the law in some municipal legal system. On the other end of the interpretive spectrum, the weakest claim is simply too modest to be of theoretical interest. The claim that many laws in many legal systems are consistent with some set of prevailing social norms is too weak at least on ordinary understandings of what many amounts to to be worth theoretical investigation. The claim that, as an empirical matter, there are many such societies seems too obvious to be worth an expenditure of theoretical resources. Such thoroughgoing ambiguities make it diycult for the reader to determine Tamanaha s targets and fully evaluate his arguments; but it seems to me that his arguments are strong enough to refute a more modest version that asserts that the content of most laws in most existing legal systems reproduce (or directly incorporate) the content of some social norms. The bulk of his case is empirical. As noted in the last section, Tamanaha argues that the standards of business law, administrative law, and law constraining legislative activity do not have counterparts in social norms because social norms generally govern the interaction of individuals in their personal capacities. Further, he argues that many nations have simply carried over bodies of law that were imposed upon them by colonizing nations and lacked any sort of substantive foundation in prevailing social norms. In addition, the trend toward social and economic globalization assures the increasing homogeneity of law around the world. It is hard to Wnd fault with Tamanaha s critique of even this more modest version of the Mirror Thesis. If anything, the case against this interpretation of the thesis is so strong that it is tempting to wonder why so many sociologists (and this interpretation states a sociological thesis) would have accepted this to begin with much less the stronger modal versions. After reading Tamanaha s analysis, it is hard to fathom how legal sociologists would have missed, for example, the fact that very important bodies of law governing governmental

11 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 727 functions do not have mirror images in social norms. It is likewise hard to fathom how they would have overlooked the signiwcance of the fact that social norms have failed to keep pace with the rapid changes in information and medical technologies or the signiwcance of the increasing inxuence around the world of business models developed in the US and Western Europe. Tamanaha s critique of this version of the Mirror Thesis seems devastating. Nevertheless, a somewhat more plausible interpretation of the thesis holds that the content of most laws in most systems is consistent with the content of moral norms that are generally accepted and practiced by the bulk of the population. While it might be true, as Hart believed, that citizens need not take the internal point of view towards the primary or secondary norms for a stable legal system to exist and function, it is reasonable to think that a stable legal system cannot exist in a society where citizens vehemently reject the content of signiwcant areas of law as would likely be the case where the law conxicts with important moral norms accepted as legitimate standards by citizens. Citizens would likely have a very strong reaction to a body of administrative rules that allowed oycials to behave dishonestly with citizens that would likely impair the smooth functioning of the legal system. Still, Tamanaha s larger point remains correct: as he would surely point out, this kind of claim is simply not something that can be taken for granted as some sort of bedrock sociological principle. Rather, it is an empirical claim that rests on assumptions about how people are likely to react to certain kinds of behaviour by oycials and hence must be conwrmed according to exactly the same methodological principles that govern any other sociological study. Indeed, on Tamanaha s view, sociological study of any particular legal system should begin with the core question of whether the content of the relevant kind of law mirrors (in the appropriate sense) prevailing customs and morality. 4. The Critique of the Function Thesis While the Function Thesis is less ambiguous than the Mirror Thesis, there are several ways to interpret it. 15 To begin, there are at least a couple of diverent empirical interpretations. According to one, the Function Thesis asserts that, in most societies with a legal system, the law plays a primary role in maintaining social order among citizens. According to another, the Function Thesis asserts that, in most societies with a legal system, the law is intended (by some appropriate class of persons) to maintain social order. Further, the Function Thesis can be construed as asserting a conceptual claim about the nature of law. On this construction, the conceptual function of law the point of law as such is to maintain social order by providing rules that guide the behaviour of citizens. 15 As will be recalled, the Function Thesis asserts that law maintains social order by establishing and enforcing the rules of social intercourse, and by resolving disputes (2).

12 728 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 Though Tamanaha is concerned to address a number of these claims, his principal target is the conceptual interpretation of the Function Thesis. The claim that law has a conceptual function seems to be a core thesis of most analyses of the concept of law. H.L.A. Hart, for example, somewhat reluctantly took the position that the point of law is to guide behaviour; as he put it, I think it quite vain to seek any more speciwc purpose which law as such serves beyond providing guides to human conduct and standards of criticism of such conduct (CL ). 16 Ronald Dworkin argues that the conceptual function of law is to justify the state in using coercive measures to maintain social order. 17 Lon L. Fuller argues that the point of a legal system to achiev[e]... [social] order... through subjecting people s conduct to the guidance of general rules by which they may themselves orient their behaviour. 18 Though these theorists disagree on the precise formulation of the Function Thesis, all seem to take the position that the conceptual function of law is to maintain social order by guiding citizen behaviour. Tamanaha rejects the claim that law has a conceptual function. For starters, Tamanaha points out that there is no function performed by only law or legal systems; for any proposed function f, it is not a suycient condition for a system of norms S to be a system of law that S performs f. Indeed, all systems of norms purport at least to maintain social order by guiding behaviour which is the function that is most commonly attributed by positivists to the law. Morality, for example, purports to do exactly that; and the scope of its rules are at least as wide as the scope of the legal norms of any developed legal systems with which we are familiar. There is, of course, nothing in the claim that the conceptual function of law is to maintain social order by guiding behaviour, as traditionally understood by those who endorse it, that implies that it is a suycient condition for S to be a legal system that S maintains social order by guiding behaviour. Indeed, being able to guide behaviour was just one of a number of properties that a normative system must satisfy in order to count as a legal system on Hart s view. In addition, the oycials must accept and follow a rule of recognition that provides standards for creating, changing, and adjudicating laws, while citizens must generally obey the rules valid under the legality criteria dewned by the rule of recognition. Tamanaha realizes this, but argues that the additional features that Hart posits are insuycient to distinguish state legal systems from sets and systems of norms that are not, on Hart s view, legal systems: 16 Although the view that law has a conceptual function is commonly attributed to Hart, he nonetheless seems to reject the view in the same passage that contains the remark that is typically thought to justify the attribution: Like other forms of positivism my theory makes no claim to identify the point or purpose of law and legal practices as such; so there is nothing in my theory to support Dworkin s view, which I certainly do not share that the purpose of law is to justify the use of coercion. In fact, I think it quite vain to seek any more speciwc purpose which law as such serves beyond providing guides to human conduct and standards of criticism of such conduct (CL ; emphasis added). 17 See Dworkin, Law s Empire, n Lon L. Fuller A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin, 10 Villanova Law Review 655 (1965), 657.

13 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 729 Hart s resort to secondary rules was not as evective in distinguishing legal from nonlegal systems of social control as he apparently believed. Hart s concept of law has been adopted by many legal pluralists, who assert that society consists of a multitude of legal institutions with rule-making and rule-enforcing power, from corporations to universities, to community associations, to sports leagues... All these institutions exert social control through administering a system of secondary and primary rules (GJ 138). Tamanaha concludes that Hart s analysis fails because social life is thick with phenomena that he would not have wanted to call law (GJ 138). 19 Tamanaha makes a convincing case that the existence conditions Hart posited fail to distinguish systems of law that give rise to a state from other institutional normative systems, but this does not, strictly speaking, refute the claim that law has a conceptual function. Assuming that legal pluralism is false, Tamanaha s observation, at best, refutes the claim that the existence conditions that Hart identiwes exhaust the content of the relevant concept of law; and this criticism can be answered by specifying additional existence conditions that only the state systems satisfy. 20 But assuming that legal pluralism is true as Tamanaha believes, his observations do not even constitute a criticism. If pluralism is true, then it is a virtue, rather than a vice, that Hart s theory does not pick out only state systems of law. Tamanaha, however, has a second objection to the conceptual interpretation of the Function Thesis. He argues that there is no function that is performed by every law or legal system; thus, for any proposed function f, it is not a necessary condition for a system of norms S to be a system of law that S performs f. In particular, there are institutional normative systems that are clearly legal systems despite the fact that the law in those systems does not succeed in guiding behaviour: Yap [Micronesia] had a legal system, with a legislature, a handful of judges and attorneys, a small police department, and a complete legal code based in its entirety on laws transplanted from the United States. But vast portions of the Code had never been applied, few lay people had any knowledge of the content of the laws or of the operation of the legal system, a large proportion of social problems were dealt with through traditional means without participation of the state legal system, and indeed on most islands there was no legal presence at all. The day-to-day behaviour of the people was not governed by state law, but by their own cultural norms... They did not identify with the legal system in any way. For most Yapese, when confronted with the law, it was like being confronted with the command of an alien sovereign, despite the fact that they were an independent country and this was their own legal system. While they did not routinely act in conxict with the law... it could not be said that they were obeying or complying with the primary rules in Hart s terms, since they were ignorant of these rules and paid them almost no heed (GJ ). 19 Tamanaha, however, criticizes liberal versions of legal pluralism that characterize entities like corporations and sports leagues as legal systems (GJ ). 20 Tamanaha acknowledges this and suggests that a conventional identiwcation of legal oycials might solve the problem (GJ 142).

14 730 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 Tamanaha believes that this refutes the claim that the conceptual function of law is to guide behaviour because it shows that it is not a conceptually necessary condition for law to exist that it succeed in guiding citizen behaviour. Yap has a legal system, despite the fact that the citizens are largely unaware of its existence and operations and hence cannot be said to be guided by it. Tamanaha s claims about the institutional normative system in Yap and the role it plays in the lives of citizens seem correct. On the one hand, Yap is accurately characterized as having a legal system since all of the distinguishing furniture is there: courts, legislatures, attorneys, and coercive mechanisms for enforcing the law. On the other, the citizens of Yap are not accurately characterized as being guided by the law since they have little knowledge of its content. Although their behaviour happens to conform to the content of the law, this is because the relevant content of the law largely conforms to the content of social norms generally obeyed by citizens something that is unbeknownst to the citizens. Since the citizens are unaware of the law s content, it would badly misdescribe the situation to characterize the citizens as being guided by the law. Tamanaha s insightful analysis of Yap s system has at least two very important theoretical implications. First, it suggests a very plausible hypothesis that, if true, would refute certain empirical interpretations of the Function Thesis. The behaviour of citizens of Yap conforms to the law, not because they are motivated to obey the law, but rather because they are motivated to obey other norms that play a more central role in their lives. This, of course, is hardly unusual. Most people are morally decent and refrain from committing theft, murder, and physical assaults, honour their contracts, etc, because such behaviours are required by moral norms and not because such behaviours are required by law. If this is correct (as seems reasonable to hypothesize), it refutes the empirical claim that the law in most legal systems actually functions to guide citizen behaviour. Second, as Tamanaha points out (GJ 148), it also refutes Hart s eycacy condition, which is largely unquestioned among positivists. Hart argues that it is a conceptually necessary condition for a system S to constitute a legal system that S be generally eycacious in regulating citizen behaviour; as Hart puts the point, those rules of behaviour which are valid according to the system s ultimate criteria of validity must be generally obeyed (CL 116; emphasis added). But Yap has a legal system despite the fact that the citizens of Yap are not fairly characterized as obeying the laws. Again, while their behaviour conforms to the law, it is because they are obeying other social norms and not because they are obeying the law. The importance of this point should not be overlooked: the eycacy condition is almost universally regarded as a core tenet of any plausible analysis of the concept of law. That Tamanaha s analysis provides such a strong challenge to the eycacy condition is a striking achievement. Nevertheless, Tamanaha s argument falls short as a criticism of the conceptual interpretation of the Function Thesis. As it turns out, there is nothing in the

15 WINTER 2004 Do Philosophy and Sociology Mix? 731 view that the conceptual function of law is to maintain social order by guiding behaviour that implies it is a necessary condition for something to count as law that it maintains social order by guiding behaviour. To say that some kind of entity K has a conceptual function f is to say only that something must be capable of performing f to count as a K; it is not to say that something must succeed in performing f to count as a K. Objects that have conceptual functions are capable of malfunctioning; a television in need of repair is still a television despite the fact that it does not succeed in performing its function. But a CD player is not a television, in part, because it is not capable of doing what televisions do. It is nomologically impossible for something that is built the way a CD player is built to do the job that televisions are conceived to do. Such considerations apply to the functional concepts associated with law. Joseph Raz, for example, analyzes the concept of authority as having something like a conceptual function. 21 Roughly put, he argues that the function of an authoritative directive is to substitute the judgments of the authority about what people ought to do according to the reasons that apply to them for the judgments of its subjects; the point is to pre-empt the subjects own judgments about what those reasons require them to do. But, Raz argues, a directive that says Do what the balance of reasons requires you to do is not authoritative because it is incapable of pre-empting the subject s judgment about what to do; the subject must weigh the balance of reasons to determine what the directive requires. Since such a directive cannot as opposed to merely does not perform the conceptual function of authority, it is conceptually disqualiwed from being authoritative. One might think, I suppose, that the conceptual function of a social artefact like law should be unique to that artefact. On this view, conceptual functions operate to distinguish one social artefact from another such that it is a logical or metaphysical truth that no two social artefacts can share the same conceptual function. Thus, the function of maintaining social order by guiding behaviour can be the conceptual function of only one kind of system of norms; it simply cannot be that, say, the rules of law and the rules of social morality share the conceptual function of guiding behaviour. Conceptual functions are distinguishing functions. But even if this were true, it would not follow from the claim that social morality and law are both capable of guiding behaviour that law has no conceptual function; what follows is that it is not the case that the conceptual function of law is to guide behaviour. This latter claim is consistent, of course, with the claim that law has no conceptual function, but it is also consistent with the claim that law has some other presumably more narrowly speciwed conceptual function. For example, one might think that the conceptual function of law is to 21 Joseph Raz, Authority, Morality, and Law in Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994).

16 732 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL. 24 guide behaviour by providing norms that will be enforced by the state. While it might be true that states sometimes enforce norms of social morality, those norms are enforced because they are incorporated into the law and thereby made legally binding. Such norms, then, are enforced qua law and not qua social morality. Though the claim that law has a conceptual function is not accepted by everyone, there is a fairly compelling motivation for the idea. Consider, for example, the concept of scissors. Someone who understands all of the structural features and properties of scissors but does not understand that scissors are capable of cutting certain kinds of objects has not fully grasped the concept. It is true, of course, that scissors can be used for other purposes, such as for wounding people. But one can understand the concept of scissors without realizing that they can be used to wound people. Knowing that scissors are designed to do the job of cutting thin objects like papers is essential to understanding the concept. Legal systems are like scissors in this respect. One can understand the concept of a legal system without understanding that a legal system can be used to oppress people; knowing this requires knowing psychological facts about people that are not relevant with respect to the existence conditions for law. But someone who does not understand that legal systems are capable of guiding behaviour (though they might fail to do so) because they manufacture norms has failed to grasp something that is essential to understanding law. One who does not understand this has simply not fully grasped the concept of a legal system. If this is correct, then being capable of performing this function (or something very like it) is one of the existence conditions for law. 5. The Critique of Legal Essentialism Central to Tamanaha s view that law is whatever people attach law to is the rejection of a view that is at the foundation of each of the most inxuential theories of law. According to this view, there are some features that are essential to law in the following sense: an entity that lacks these features is conceptually disqualiwed from counting as an instance of law regardless of what otherwise might be true of the world. As is readily evident, positivism, classical natural law theory, and Dworkinian constructivism all describe properties of law that are fairly characterized as essential and thus presuppose a legal essentialist view. To his credit, Tamanaha grounds his argument in a methodological constraint on conceptual analysis that is not always appreciated by philosophers who analyze legal concepts. As will be recalled, Tamanaha distinguishes two threads of conventionalism: a conventionalism having to do with the content of concepts and a conventionalism with respect to the content of the rule of recognition. According to the Wrst version of conventionalism, the content of our concepts is largely determined by conventional linguistic practices regarding the use of the

Introduction[1] The obstacle

Introduction[1] The obstacle In his book, The Concept of Law, HLA Hart described the element of authority involved in law as an obstacle in the path of any easy explanation of what law is. In this paper I argue that this is true for

More information

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1. Introduction There are two sets of questions that have featured prominently in recent debates about distributive justice. One of these debates is that between universalism

More information

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Abstract: This paper develops a unique exposition about the relationship between facts and principles in political

More information

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism

Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism Legal Reasoning, the Rule of Law, and Legal Theory: Comments on Gerald Postema, Positivism and the Separation of the Realists from their Skepticism Introduction In his incisive paper, Positivism and the

More information

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory

Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory Phil 115, June 20, 2007 Justice as fairness as a political conception: the fact of reasonable pluralism and recasting the ideas of Theory The problem with the argument for stability: In his discussion

More information

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG SYMPOSIUM POLITICAL LIBERALISM VS. LIBERAL PERFECTIONISM POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG JOSEPH CHAN 2012 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 2, No. 1 (2012): pp.

More information

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED David Brink Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER David Brink examines the views of legal positivism and natural law theory

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

LEGAL THEORY/ JURISPRUDENCE SUMMARY

LEGAL THEORY/ JURISPRUDENCE SUMMARY LEGAL THEORY/ JURISPRUDENCE SUMMARY LAWSKOOL NEW ZEALAND TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 4 POSTIVISM AND THE NATURE OF LAW(S) 5 What is a legal system 5 (i) Obligation 5 (ii) Law as a System of Rules 6

More information

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Do we have a strong case for open borders? Do we have a strong case for open borders? Joseph Carens [1987] challenges the popular view that admission of immigrants by states is only a matter of generosity and not of obligation. He claims that the

More information

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously

The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously Yale Law School Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship Series Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1978 The Rights and Wrongs of Taking Rights Seriously Jules L. Coleman Yale

More information

A political theory of territory

A political theory of territory A political theory of territory Margaret Moore Oxford University Press, New York, 2015, 263pp., ISBN: 978-0190222246 Contemporary Political Theory (2017) 16, 293 298. doi:10.1057/cpt.2016.20; advance online

More information

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization" By MICHAEL AMBROSIO We have been given a wonderful example by Professor Gordley of a cogent, yet straightforward

More information

The Identity of Legal Systems

The Identity of Legal Systems California Law Review Volume 59 Issue 3 Article 11 May 1971 The Identity of Legal Systems Joseph Raz Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/californialawreview Recommended

More information

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society.

Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. Political Philosophy, Spring 2003, 1 The Terrain of a Global Normative Order 1. Realism and Normative Order Last time we discussed a stylized version of the realist view of global society. According to

More information

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Bryan Smyth, University of Memphis 2011 APA Central Division Meeting // Session V-I: Global Justice // 2. April 2011 I am

More information

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague

E-LOGOS. Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals. University of Economics Prague E-LOGOS ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN 1211-0442 1/2010 University of Economics Prague Rawls two principles of justice: their adoption by rational self-interested individuals e Alexandra Dobra

More information

In 1978, Congress established the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Court, which reviews warrants related to national security investigations.

In 1978, Congress established the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Court, which reviews warrants related to national security investigations. (Draft of 21 October 2013) For the Conference, On the Very Idea of Secret Laws: Transparency and Publicity in Deliberative Democracy, University of Pennsylvania School, Center for Ethics and the Rule of

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

AUTHORITY AND NORMATIVITY. Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

AUTHORITY AND NORMATIVITY. Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law AUTHORITY AND NORMATIVITY Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law Joseph Raz (1939) - exclusive positivism concept of authority law claims to be a legitimate authority tax officer claim to pay the tax

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Comment on Steiner's Liberal Theory of Exploitation Author(s): Steven Walt Source: Ethics, Vol. 94, No. 2 (Jan., 1984), pp. 242-247 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2380514.

More information

How to approach legitimacy

How to approach legitimacy How to approach legitimacy for the book project Empirical Perspectives on the Legitimacy of International Investment Tribunals Daniel Behn, 1 Ole Kristian Fauchald 2 and Malcolm Langford 3 January 2015

More information

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* 219 Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* Laura Valentini London School of Economics and Political Science 1. Introduction Kok-Chor Tan s review essay offers an internal critique of

More information

Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy with Aristotle s. Political Philosophy

Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy with Aristotle s. Political Philosophy Original Paper Urban Studies and Public Administration Vol. 1, No. 1, 2018 www.scholink.org/ojs/index.php/uspa ISSN 2576-1986 (Print) ISSN 2576-1994 (Online) Comparison of Plato s Political Philosophy

More information

Comments and observations received from Governments

Comments and observations received from Governments Extract from the Yearbook of the International Law Commission:- 1997,vol. II(1) Document:- A/CN.4/481 and Add.1 Comments and observations received from Governments Topic: International liability for injurious

More information

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D

25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Frankfurt am Main August Paper Series. No. 055 / 2012 Series D 25th IVR World Congress LAW SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY Frankfurt am Main 15 20 August 2011 Paper Series No. 055 / 2012 Series D History of Philosophy; Hart, Kelsen, Radbruch, Habermas, Rawls; Luhmann; General

More information

HART S CRITIQUE OF AUSTIN S THEORY. Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law

HART S CRITIQUE OF AUSTIN S THEORY. Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law HART S CRITIQUE OF AUSTIN S THEORY Literature: A. Marmor, Philosophy of Law imperative theory of law (J. Austin, 1790-1859) 1) law consists of instructions or directives issued by some people in order

More information

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt *

ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE. Steven Walt * ELIMINATING CORRECTIVE JUSTICE Steven Walt * D ISTRIBUTIVE justice describes the morally required distribution of shares of resources and liberty among people. Corrective justice describes the moral obligation

More information

Ekaterina Bogdanov January 18, 2012

Ekaterina Bogdanov January 18, 2012 AP- PHIL 2050 John Austin s and H.L.A. Hart s Legal Positivist Theories of Law: An Assessment of Empirical Consistency Ekaterina Bogdanov 210 374 718 January 18, 2012 For Nathan Harron Tutorial 2 John

More information

PHIL 168: Philosophy of Law UCSD; Fall 2015 Prof. David O. Brink Handout #2: Hart's Model of Rules and Legal Realism

PHIL 168: Philosophy of Law UCSD; Fall 2015 Prof. David O. Brink Handout #2: Hart's Model of Rules and Legal Realism Draft of 9-23- 15 PHIL 168: Philosophy of Law UCSD; Fall 2015 Prof. David O. Brink Handout #2: Hart's Model of Rules and Legal Realism Hart develops his own conception of the nature of law in the wake

More information

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View

Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's View Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 8-7-2018 Civil Disobedience and the Duty to Obey the Law: A Critical Assessment of Lefkowitz's

More information

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION Libertarianism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe L ibertarianism is a moral, social, and political doctrine that considers the liberty of individual citizens the absence of external restraint and coercion

More information

International Law s Relative Authority

International Law s Relative Authority DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5235/20403313.6.1.169 (2015) 6(1) Jurisprudence 169 176 International Law s Relative Authority A review of Nicole Roughan, Authorities. Conflicts, Cooperation, and Transnational

More information

Kenneth Einar Himma Winter 2014 (Tuesday & Thursday, Room 441, 1:30 p.m. 3:20 p.m. Friday, April 12, April 26, 1:30 p.m. 10:20 p.m.

Kenneth Einar Himma Winter 2014 (Tuesday & Thursday, Room 441, 1:30 p.m. 3:20 p.m. Friday, April 12, April 26, 1:30 p.m. 10:20 p.m. PHILOSOPHY OF LAW Law E519 Kenneth Einar Himma Winter 2014 (Tuesday & Thursday, Room 441, 1:30 p.m. 3:20 p.m. Friday, April 12, April 26, 1:30 p.m. 10:20 p.m.) Office Hours and Contact Information Office:

More information

IS LAW DETERMINED BY MORALITY? Dworkin and Inclusive Legal Positivism

IS LAW DETERMINED BY MORALITY? Dworkin and Inclusive Legal Positivism Dworkin and Inclusive Legal Positivism legal positivism conventionality thesis: legal validity can ultimately be explained in terms of criteria that are authoritative in virtue of some kind of social convention

More information

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process

The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process The Justification of Justice as Fairness: A Two Stage Process TED VAGGALIS University of Kansas The tragic truth about philosophy is that misunderstanding occurs more frequently than understanding. Nowhere

More information

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon PHILIP PETTIT The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon In The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy, Christopher McMahon challenges my claim that the republican goal of promoting or maximizing

More information

In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism

In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 5-3-2007 In Defense of Rawlsian Constructivism William St. Michael Allen Follow this and additional

More information

Equity, Legal Pluralism and the Honour of the Crown(s) in Settler State Legal and Political Theory Kirsty Gover

Equity, Legal Pluralism and the Honour of the Crown(s) in Settler State Legal and Political Theory Kirsty Gover Abstracts Session 1 Do Lawyers Need a Theory Of Legal Pluralism? Roger Cotterrell Legal pluralism is a condition in which laws derived from different regulatory regimes or systems interact or compete in

More information

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary

Mehrdad Payandeh, Internationales Gemeinschaftsrecht Summary The age of globalization has brought about significant changes in the substance as well as in the structure of public international law changes that cannot adequately be explained by means of traditional

More information

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic The European Journal of International Law Vol. 20 no. 4 EJIL 2010; all rights reserved... National Courts, Domestic Democracy, and the Evolution of International Law: A Reply to Eyal Benvenisti and George

More information

METHODOLOGY IN JURISPRUDENCE:

METHODOLOGY IN JURISPRUDENCE: Legal Theory, 10 (2004), 117 156. Printed in the United States of America Published by Cambridge University Press 0361-6843/04 $12.00+00 METHODOLOGY IN JURISPRUDENCE: A Critical Survey Julie Dickson Somerville

More information

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of

In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of Global Justice, Spring 2003, 1 Comments on National Self-Determination 1. The Principle of Nationality In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that nationalism is a theory of political legitimacy

More information

The Morality of Conflict

The Morality of Conflict The Morality of Conflict Reasonable Disagreement and the Law Samantha Besson HART- PUBLISHING OXFORD AND PORTLAND, OREGON 2005 '"; : Contents Acknowledgements vii Introduction 1 I. The issue 1 II. The

More information

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp.

On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp. On Human Rights by James Griffin, Oxford University Press, 2008, 339 pp. Mark Hannam This year marks the sixtieth anniversary of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which was adopted and proclaimed

More information

TOPIC: - THE PLACE OF KELSONS PURE THEORY OF LAW IN

TOPIC: - THE PLACE OF KELSONS PURE THEORY OF LAW IN 1 LEGAL THEORY SEMINAR TOPIC: - THE PLACE OF KELSONS PURE THEORY OF LAW IN FUNCTIONAL JURISPRUDENCE NAME: SANKALP BHANGUI CLASS: FIRST YEAR L.L.M 2 INDEX SR.NO. TOPIC PG.NO. THE PLACE OF KELSON S PURE

More information

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi REVIEW Clara Brandi We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Terry Macdonald, Global Stakeholder Democracy. Power and Representation Beyond Liberal States, Oxford, Oxford University

More information

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: 699 708 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI 10.1007/s10982-015-9239-8 ARIE ROSEN (Accepted 31 August 2015) Alon Harel, Why Law Matters. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice?

Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice? Republicanism: Midway to Achieve Global Justice? (Binfan Wang, University of Toronto) (Paper presented to CPSA Annual Conference 2016) Abstract In his recent studies, Philip Pettit develops his theory

More information

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating

Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating Disagreement, Error and Two Senses of Incompatibility The Relational Function of Discursive Updating Tanja Pritzlaff email: t.pritzlaff@zes.uni-bremen.de webpage: http://www.zes.uni-bremen.de/homepages/pritzlaff/index.php

More information

Call for Papers. May 14-16, Nice

Call for Papers. May 14-16, Nice Call for Papers Conference «The Philosophy of Customary Law» May 14-16, Nice Organized by the Centre of Research in History of Ideas Philosophy Department of the University of Nice Sophia Antipolis Member

More information

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.). S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: 0-674-01029-9 (hbk.). In this impressive, tightly argued, but not altogether successful book,

More information

Occasional Paper No 34 - August 1998

Occasional Paper No 34 - August 1998 CHANGING PARADIGMS IN POLICING The Significance of Community Policing for the Governance of Security Clifford Shearing, Community Peace Programme, School of Government, University of the Western Cape,

More information

Meeting Plato s challenge?

Meeting Plato s challenge? Public Choice (2012) 152:433 437 DOI 10.1007/s11127-012-9995-z Meeting Plato s challenge? Michael Baurmann Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2012 We can regard the history of Political Philosophy as

More information

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views Larry Levine Department of Economics, University of New Brunswick Introduction The two views which are agenda

More information

On Interpretivism and International Law

On Interpretivism and International Law The European Journal of International Law Vol. 20 no. 3 EJIL 2009; all rights reserved... On Interpretivism and International Law B a ș ak Ç ali * Abstract This article argues for the relevance of interpretivism

More information

Political Obligation 3

Political Obligation 3 Political Obligation 3 Dr Simon Beard Sjb316@cam.ac.uk Centre for the Study of Existential Risk Summary of this lecture How John Rawls argues that we have an obligation to obey the law, whether or not

More information

Dworkin, selections from Taking Rights Seriously. Dworkin identifies these three propositions as forming the core of the legal positivist position:

Dworkin, selections from Taking Rights Seriously. Dworkin identifies these three propositions as forming the core of the legal positivist position: Session 4 Dworkin, selections from Taking Rights Seriously Dworkin on Hart s Model of Rules Dworkin identifies these three propositions as forming the core of the legal positivist position: (1) The law

More information

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a Justice, Fall 2003 Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair

More information

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS 1. Two Principles of Justice John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. That theory comprises two principles of

More information

Two Sides of the Same Coin

Two Sides of the Same Coin Unpacking Rainer Forst s Basic Right to Justification Stefan Rummens In his forceful paper, Rainer Forst brings together many elements from his previous discourse-theoretical work for the purpose of explaining

More information

Constitutional Self-Government: A Reply to Rubenfeld

Constitutional Self-Government: A Reply to Rubenfeld Fordham Law Review Volume 71 Issue 5 Article 4 2003 Constitutional Self-Government: A Reply to Rubenfeld Christopher L. Eisgruber Recommended Citation Christopher L. Eisgruber, Constitutional Self-Government:

More information

Democracy and Common Valuations

Democracy and Common Valuations Democracy and Common Valuations Philip Pettit Three views of the ideal of democracy dominate contemporary thinking. The first conceptualizes democracy as a system for empowering public will, the second

More information

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017)

MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017) MA International Relations Module Catalogue (September 2017) This document is meant to give students and potential applicants a better insight into the curriculum of the program. Note that where information

More information

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Western University Scholarship@Western 2014 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2014 Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Taylor C. Rodrigues Western University,

More information

SHOULD THE UNITED STATES WORRY ABOUT LARGE, FAST-GROWING ECONOMIES?

SHOULD THE UNITED STATES WORRY ABOUT LARGE, FAST-GROWING ECONOMIES? Chapter Six SHOULD THE UNITED STATES WORRY ABOUT LARGE, FAST-GROWING ECONOMIES? This report represents an initial investigation into the relationship between economic growth and military expenditures for

More information

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES Final draft July 2009 This Book revolves around three broad kinds of questions: $ What kind of society is this? $ How does it really work? Why is it the way

More information

University of Virginia Law School

University of Virginia Law School University of Virginia Law School Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper Series Year 2009 Paper 129 Institutions and the Concept of Law: A Reply to Ronald Dworkin (With Some Help From Neil MacCormick)

More information

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia

REVIEW. Statutory Interpretation in Australia AUSTRALIAN JOURNAL OF LAW AND SOCIETY (1993) 9 REVIEW Statutory Interpretation in Australia P C Pearce and R S Geddes Butterworths, 1988, Sydney (3rd edition) John Gava Book reviews are normally written

More information

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights

Part 1. Understanding Human Rights Part 1 Understanding Human Rights 2 Researching and studying human rights: interdisciplinary insight Damien Short Since 1948, the study of human rights has been dominated by legal scholarship that has

More information

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent? Chapter 1 Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent? Cristina Lafont Introduction In what follows, I would like to contribute to a defense of deliberative democracy by giving an affirmative answer

More information

1. Introduction. Jonathan Verschuuren

1. Introduction. Jonathan Verschuuren 1. Introduction Jonathan Verschuuren In most western societies, the role of the legislature was originally based upon the principle of the separation of powers, as developed by Montesquieu in his De l

More information

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN:

Book Reviews. Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN: Public Reason 6 (1-2): 83-89 2016 by Public Reason Julian Culp, Global Justice and Development, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2014, Pp. xi+215, ISBN: 978-1-137-38992-3 In Global Justice and Development,

More information

Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court *

Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court * INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL TRIBUNALS Interview with Philippe Kirsch, President of the International Criminal Court * Judge Philippe Kirsch (Canada) is president of the International Criminal Court in The Hague

More information

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis

On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis Eastern Economic Journal 2018, 44, (491 495) Ó 2018 EEA 0094-5056/18 www.palgrave.com/journals COLANDER'S ECONOMICS WITH ATTITUDE On the Irrelevance of Formal General Equilibrium Analysis Middlebury College,

More information

Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal

Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal 1 The Sources of American Law Aconsideration of the sources of law in a legal order must deal with a variety of different, although related, matters. Historical roots and derivations need explanation.

More information

A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS

A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS Bachelor Thesis by S.F. Simmelink s1143611 sophiesimmelink@live.nl Internationale Betrekkingen en Organisaties Universiteit Leiden 9 June 2016 Prof. dr. G.A. Irwin Word

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi

THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY. Justin Tosi VC 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd Ratio (new series) XXX 1 March 2017 0034-0006 doi: 10.1111/rati.12114 THE POSSIBILITY OF A FAIR PLAY ACCOUNT OF LEGITIMACY Justin Tosi Abstract The philosophical literature

More information

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008

Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday October 17, 2008 Helena de Bres Wellesley College Department of Philosophy hdebres@wellesley.edu Comments on Justin Weinberg s Is Government Supererogation Possible? Public Reason Political Philosophy Symposium Friday

More information

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

Jürgen Kohl March 2011 Jürgen Kohl March 2011 Comments to Claus Offe: What, if anything, might we mean by progressive politics today? Let me first say that I feel honoured by the opportunity to comment on this thoughtful and

More information

LAWS2249 Legal Theory 2 nd Semester 2009

LAWS2249 Legal Theory 2 nd Semester 2009 LAWS2249 Legal Theory 2 nd Semester 2009 How to Use this Script: These sample exam answers are based on problems done in past years. Since these answers were written, the law has changed and the subject

More information

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at:

ABSTRACT. Electronic copy available at: ABSTRACT By tracing the development and evolvement of certain legal theories over the centuries, as well as consequences emanating from such developments, this paper highlights how and why a shift from

More information

On the Value of Jurisprudence

On the Value of Jurisprudence On the Value of Jurisprudence LEGALITY. By Scott J. Shapiro. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011. 472 pages. $39.95. Reviewed by Ian P. Farrell * Introduction

More information

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts) primarysourcedocument Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical, Excerpts John Rawls 1985 [Rawls, John. Justice As Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14, no. 3.

More information

Book Review: The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century, by Peter Cane (ed)

Book Review: The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century, by Peter Cane (ed) Osgoode Hall Law Journal Volume 48, Number 3/4 (Fall/Winter 2010) Article 11 Book Review: The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century, by Peter Cane (ed) Sean Rehaag Osgoode Hall Law School of York

More information

Political Norms and Moral Values

Political Norms and Moral Values Penultimate version - Forthcoming in Journal of Philosophical Research (2015) Political Norms and Moral Values Robert Jubb University of Leicester rj138@leicester.ac.uk Department of Politics & International

More information

The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts

The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts Washington University Law Review Volume 73 Issue 3 Northwestern University / Washington University Law and Linguistics Conference 1995 The Language of Law and More Probable Than Not : Some Brief Thoughts

More information

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES PAPER NO. 12-03-02 March 2012 WHAT IS GENERAL JURISPRUDENCE? A CRITIQUE OF UNIVERSALISTIC CLAIMS BY PHILOSOPHICAL CONCEPTS OF LAW by Brian Z. Tamanaha William Gardiner

More information

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES

CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES CHAPTER 1 PROLOGUE: VALUES AND PERSPECTIVES Final draft July 2009 This Book revolves around three broad kinds of questions: $ What kind of society is this? $ How does it really work? Why is it the way

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

Book Review: American Constitutionalism: from Theory to Politics. by Stephen M. Griffin.

Book Review: American Constitutionalism: from Theory to Politics. by Stephen M. Griffin. University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 1997 Book Review: American Constitutionalism: from Theory to Politics. by Stephen M. Griffin. Daniel O. Conkle Follow

More information

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract

Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 7 5-1-2005 Utilitarianism, Game Theory and the Social Contract Daniel Burgess Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/philo

More information

INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND COERCION AS A GROUND OF JUSTICE

INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND COERCION AS A GROUND OF JUSTICE INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE AND COERCION AS A GROUND OF JUSTICE Siba Harb * siba.harb@hiw.kuleuven.be In this comment piece, I will pick up on Axel Gosseries s suggestion in his article Nations, Generations

More information

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy

Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy Nanyang Technological University From the SelectedWorks of Chenyang Li 2009 Where does Confucian Virtuous Leadership Stand? A Critique of Daniel Bell s Beyond Liberal Democracy Chenyang Li, Nanyang Technological

More information

MLL110 LEGAL PRINCIPLES & SKILLS EXAM NOTES. problems

MLL110 LEGAL PRINCIPLES & SKILLS EXAM NOTES. problems WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO BE A LAWYER MLL110 LEGAL PRINCIPLES & SKILLS EXAM NOTES MYTH All lawyers earn a lot of money There is a right side and wrong side in a dispute A lawyer needs only to be good at arguing

More information

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1

Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1 András Szigeti Linköping University andras.szigeti@liu.se Review of Michael E. Bratman s Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together (Oxford University Press 2014) 1 If you have ever had to move

More information

The Nebraska Death Penalty Study: An Interdisciplinary Symposium

The Nebraska Death Penalty Study: An Interdisciplinary Symposium Nebraska Law Review Volume 81 Issue 2 Article 2 2002 The Nebraska Death Penalty Study: An Interdisciplinary Symposium Robert F. Schopp University of Nebraska Lincoln Follow this and additional works at:

More information

Part I Introduction. [11:00 7/12/ pierce-ch01.tex] Job No: 5052 Pierce: Research Methods in Politics Page: 1 1 8

Part I Introduction. [11:00 7/12/ pierce-ch01.tex] Job No: 5052 Pierce: Research Methods in Politics Page: 1 1 8 Part I Introduction [11:00 7/12/2007 5052-pierce-ch01.tex] Job No: 5052 Pierce: Research Methods in Politics Page: 1 1 8 [11:00 7/12/2007 5052-pierce-ch01.tex] Job No: 5052 Pierce: Research Methods in

More information

Business Ethics Journal Review

Business Ethics Journal Review Business Ethics Journal Review SCHOLARLY COMMENTS ON ACADEMIC BUSINESS ETHICS businessethicsjournalreview.com Why Justice Matters for Business Ethics 1 Jeffery Smith A COMMENTARY ON Abraham Singer (2016),

More information

INTRODUCTION: SYMPOSIUM ON PAUL GOWDER, THE RULE OF LAW IN THE REAL WORLD MATTHEW LISTER*

INTRODUCTION: SYMPOSIUM ON PAUL GOWDER, THE RULE OF LAW IN THE REAL WORLD MATTHEW LISTER* INTRODUCTION: SYMPOSIUM ON PAUL GOWDER, THE RULE OF LAW IN THE REAL WORLD MATTHEW LISTER* The rule of law is an example of what has been called an essentially contested concept. These are concepts where

More information