Losing to Win. How Partisan Candidates Help Parties Win in the Future. Kai Steverson. April 8, 2012

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Losing to Win. How Partisan Candidates Help Parties Win in the Future. Kai Steverson. April 8, 2012"

Transcription

1 Losing to Win How Partisan Candidates Help Parties Win in the Future Kai Steverson April 8, 2012 Abstract In the U.S. presidential election of 1964 the republicans nominated a candidate, Barry Goldwater, who was seen as too ideological extreme to be viable. And as predicted, Goldwater lost in a landslide. Yet conservatives in America argue that the election in 1964 played a crucial role in securing future victories by energizing and building the political base. This paper formalizes this logic in an in nite horizon model of two party competition. In the unique subgame perfect equilibrium parties concede elections by picking a partisan candidate in order to help them win in future periods. The key mechanism is motivated by two pieces of empirical evidence: 1) that partisan candidates increase turnout from the base, and 2) that voting is a persistent behavior. Thus a partisan candidate running today can raise future turnout from the base. The model also generates three testable empirical predictions. 1) Parties newly out of power nominate more partisan candidates. 2) The longer a party is in power the more likely they are to lose. 3) Parties converge in terms of policies but not in terms of candidates nominated. 1 Introduction In the U.S. presidential election of 1964 the Republican party nominated a candidate, named Barry Goldwater, who was considered too ideologically extreme to have any chance of winning. In a editorial written the day after the nomination the New York Times called Goldwater "a disaster for the Republican party" who threatened to turn the GOP into a "right-wing splinter group" and who had "minimal" chance of winning ("The Goldwater Nomination", July 16, 1964, p. 30). During the campaign, the Democrats successfully played o Goldwater s extremism with the slogan "in your guts, you know he s nuts". As predicted, Goldwater lost in a landslide. He got less than 40% of the vote and only won six states. 1

2 Given this large loss, and its predictable nature, how can Goldwater s nomination be explained? Conservatives now argue that Goldwater s nomination energized the conservative movement, which played a crucial role in future victories. William Middendorf, who worked on the Goldwater campaign and later served as Secretary of the Navy, argued that the campaign of 1964 "left behind a cadre of millions of true believers" without which "there would have been no Reagan or Bush administrations" (Middendorf (2006), p. xii). Conservative columnist George Will wrote that "[Goldwater] lost 44 states but won the future...he catalyzed conservatism s breakthrough" ("A Man Who Won the Future", May 27, 1994, p. C7). Segal (1968) reports evidence that in 1964 the republican base turned out a higher rate than the democratic base, supporting the idea that Goldwater energized the base. Goldwater himself viewed the primary purpose of his candidacy as energizing the base. Goldwater didn t really believe he could win, yet decided it was important to rally the base, to give voice to the conservative cause. In his autobiography (Goldwater (1988)) he re ects on a conversation he had in December of 1963 with his wife: I told Peggy something I ve never to this moment told anyone else in my life. I said I didn t want to run. In my gut, there was never a burning desire to be President. I just wanted the conservatives to have a real voice in the country. Many of us were damn tired of the Democrats. They d eventually wreck the economy and bring the whole country down with them. Someone had to rally the conservatives, take over the Republican Party and turn the direction of the GOP around. There was no one to do it but me. We d lose the election but win the party. (p. 154) The case of Goldwater exempli es the thesis of this work, which can be stated as follows. Partisan candidates energize the base, but are less electorally viable. Energizing the base is valuable for future elections. This creates a trade-o between winning today and winning tomorrow. The goal of this paper is to formalize this argument. To do so I develop an in nite horizon model of political competition in which parties nominate candidates to compete in an election. In the unique subgame perfect equilibrium a moderate candidate wins in every period and yet partisan candidates are chosen in order to invest in the future. In particular parties choose partisan candidates when they face electoral adversity, which in the model will be created through an incumbency advantage. Out of power parties, that did not recently energize their base, face a less than 50% chance of winning even with a moderate candidate. Given this situation they decide it is better to concede the current election and build a stronger future with a partisan candidate. 2

3 The key mechanism where partisan candidates help the party win in the future has two ingredients: that partisan candidate energize the base and that this lasts at least until the next election. Energizing the base has potentially many dimensions, for the purposes of this work I speci cally mean increasing turnout. That partisan candidates increase turnout among their base nds empirical support in the literature on "abstention due to alienation". The idea that increasing turnout today impacts turnout tomorrow is founded in the literature on "habitual voting". Section 2 discusses these two ingredients and uses them to motivate the key mechanism of the model. The formal literature on candidate selection has largely centered around reconciling the following two facts: that moderate candidate perform better in elections and yet partisan candidates are still chosen. This literature has only employed models that take place in period, and in a one period parties are restricted to care only about two things: winning today and policy today. Thus a one period cannot explain nominating a sure loser, such as Goldwater. Because my model is multi period parties can care about something new: winning and policy in the future. This allows for a new reason to nominate partisans, that they help parties win future elections. The model developed also delivers three testable predictions. 1) The longer a party is in power the more likely they are to lose. 2) Parties converge in terms of policies but not in terms of candidates nominated. 3) Parties newly out of power nominate more partisan candidates. All three predictions arise from the tension that parties face between winning today and winning tomorrow and di erentiate my model from previous models of candidate selection. These predictions as well as evidence supporting them will be discussed in section 6. Original empirical work is beyond the scope of this paper, but evidence taken from the literature will be presented. The rest of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 motivates and discusses the mechanism whereby partisan candidates help parties win in the future. Section 3 gives a brief review of previous formal models of candidate selection, and compares those models with this work. Section 4 gives the formal description of the model. Section 5 characterizes the equilibrium and gives a sketch of the proof. Section 6 discusses the three testable predictions of the model. Sections 7 and 8 relax the main assumptions of the model by looking at purely o ce motivated and impatient parties respectively. Section 9 concludes. 2 Motivating the Model: Evidence and Theory In this section I discuss and motivate the two key ingredients of the model: that partisan candidates increase the turnout of the base and that this e ect lasts until the next election. 3

4 The rst ingredient links to the literature on "abstention due to alienation" and the second to "habitual voting". These are discussed in 2.1 and 2.2 respectively. Crucially these literatures connect in that people who did not vote previously are more likely to have their turnout decision a ected by the ideology of the candidate. In other words "habitual voters" are less likely to "abstain due to alienation". This connection leads to the key mechanism of the model: that partisan candidates can in uence whether voters from their base acquire the habit of voting. This mechanism is fully discussed in Abstention due to Alienation Zipp (1985) examined how the ideological position of the candidates relative to the voter in uences turnout. Zipp scored the ideological of position of each individual and each candidate on a range of policy issues. He found that individuals who were far from either candidate voted less, an e ect referred to as "abstention due to alienation". Of course the ip side of this e ect is that people who are ideologically close to at least one candidate vote more. This captures the idea that a partisan candidate is capable of energizing the base. More recently Plane and Gershtenson (2004) and Adams et al. (2006) have conducted similar studies and also found a signi cant "abstention due to alienation" e ect. Adams et. al. assumes the e ect works through a threshold, that is an individual votes only if the closest candidate is close enough. Using maximum likelihood they estimated the determinants of this threshold. They nd that having voted in the past election signi cantly reduces how close the candidate has to be. In other words non-voters are more likely to require a candidate with similar ideology to decide to vote. 2.2 Habitual Voting Plutzer (2002) notes: "[v]irtually all major works on turnout have concluded that voting behavior is, in part, a gradually acquired habit". The observation that underlies this conclusion is that voting is a highly stable behavior. This can be observed from both cross sectional and panel data. Miller and Shanks (1996) look at cross sectional cohort data and nds cohort turnout rises for the rst two or three election before hitting a long "turnout plateau" and then tailing o at old age. Similarly Plutzer (2002) looks at panel data from U.S. presidential elections and notes that of the 516 respondents who voted in both 1968 and % voted again in More generally numerous studies show previous voting is a robust predicator of current voting in multivariate analysis (e.g. Franklin (2004); Brody (1977)).The interpretation given to these results is that the population can be divided into two groups: voters and non-voters. During young adulthood individual citizen 4

5 sorts themselves into these groups and, once settled, are high unlikely to shift from one to the other. For the purposes of this work what matters is that there is a causal like between voting today and voting tomorrow. That such a link exists has been con rmed by both the instrumental variable and experimental approach. Green and Shachar (2000) instrumented for past voting using aggregate variables from the past elections known to in uence voting, such as perceived closeness of the election or the ideological gap between candidates. They concluded that past voting causes current voting. Gerber et al. (2003) conducted an experiment where the treatment groups was urged to vote through direct mail or face to face canvassing. The treatment was more likely to vote in the current election and this di erence persisted in subsequent elections. In fact the those who voted in the treatment group became indistinguishable from those who voted in the control group. These two studies point to something intrinsic to voting that makes future voting more likely. 2.3 The Mechanism The common explanation given in the literature for habitual voting is that voting involves a one time xed cost. Plutzer (2002) puts it as follows: As young citizens confront their rst election, all of the costs of voting are magni- ed: they have never gone through the process of registration, may not know the location of their polling place, and may not have yet developed an understanding of party di erences and key issues. Moreover, their peer group consists almost entirely of other nonvoters: their friends cannot assure them that voting has been easy, enjoyable, or satisfying. Of course there is variation, some people enjoy engaging in the political process, even in their rst election. The crucial point is, all else equal, having experience with voting makes it easier, and hence more likely. This explanation of habitual voting connects in a crucial way with the evidence mentioned above that non-voters have a much higher "abstention due to alienation" threshold. In other words those who still face the xed cost to voting are more likely to require a candidate with a similar ideology to be convinced to vote. This evidence isn t perfect in that nonvoters are de ned as someone who didn t vote last period, not someone who has never voted. Nevertheless this highly suggests that a partisan candidate brings rst time voters from the political base to the polls, overcoming the initial cost to voting, and pushing them onto the path of habitual voting. More habitual voters in the base leads to higher turnout in the 5

6 future, enhancing the party s future election prospects. This is the key mechanism of this paper by which partisan candidates help parties win in the future. 3 Previous Models of Candidate Selection The formal literature on candidate selection began with the insights of the median voter theorem, which goes back at least far as Downs (1957). In that model whichever party is closer to the position of the median voter wins with certainty, which causes both parties converge to the median voter in equilibrium. This creates two testable implications: that moderate candidates perform better in election and that both parties should converge to the same position. The empirical evidence strongly supports the rst of these claims and strongly disagrees with the second (see Ansolabehere et al. (2001) and Erikson and Wright (2005)). Much of the subsequent literature has focused on modifying the standard model to explain divergence. To do so it must address the following question: if moderates perform better in elections why are partisans candidates ever nominated? Here I brie y survey some of approaches the literature has taken to this question. The most direct way to explain divergence is assuming that parties have an intrinsic preference for partisan candidates, i.e. a policy motive. This tack was rst taken by Wittman (1983) and later developed by Calvert (1985) and Roemer (1994). This can only work if the basic Downsian model is modi ed to include uncertainty. This makes the candidate closer to the median only more likely to win instead of certain to win. Then policy motivated parties are willing to accept a lower probability of winning in order to get a chance of electing a partisan. This produces divergence in a setting where moderate candidates do better, matching the empirical evidence. Palfrey (1984) took another approach and argued that even if only two parties are observed in an election, the possibility of entry by a third party creates divergence. To see this suppose that both parties have converged to the median position. Then a third party could enter slightly to the right (or left) of the median and capture close to half of the votes, while the original two parties would be forced to split the remaining half. The third party gets a plurality of the votes, making its entry pro table, and so convergence to the median cannot be an equilibrium. This explains candidate divergence even when parties care only about winning. Another approach to generate divergence has been taken by Adams and Merrill III (2003). Their model is similar to mine in that they assume partisan candidates energize the base, increasing turnout. They also motive this with the evidence on "abstention due to alienation". The key di erence is in their model partisan candidates do better in elections than 6

7 moderate candidates. This happen because the votes a candidate gains from moving to the center is outweighed by the number of citizen in their base who would then abstain. This models generates candidate divergence in equilibrium, but only at the cost of contradicting the strong evidence that moderate candidate perform better in elections. One feature that all of the above models have in common is they are one period. Intuitively in a one period model parties can only care about two things: winning today and policy today. And indeed each of the above models gives one of these two reason as to why partisan candidates are nominated. Because my model is multi-period parties can care about something new: winning and policy in the future. This allows for a new reason why partisan are nominated, that is partisans energize the base and helps parties win in the future. This innovation can explain the nomination of sure losers, such as Goldwater in My model also produces three other testable implications that di erentiate it from the previous literature discussed above. These will be fully discussed and evidence presented in section 6. 4 The Model 4.1 Basics The model is an overlapping generation model with measure 1 of citizen who each live for 2 periods. The two generations are equally sized with measure :5 each. Everyone discounts the future at 2 (0; 1). Each period there is an election in which each citizen has the right, but not the obligation, to vote. Citizens are split into three equally sized groups based on ideology fl; m; rg 1. The l and r groups are called partisan citizens, and are associated with in nitely lived parties L and R. Type m citizens don t have a party and are referred to as moderate citizens. Each period the parties nominate a citizen candidate from one of the three groups to represent them in the election. For simplicity I suppose the parties will not choose a candidate from the other party s base. Thus parties make a binary choice between a moderate candidate or a partisan candidate from their own base. In order to avoid mixed strategy equilibrium the party that won last period has to choose their candidate rst. The candidate with the larger measure of votes wins the election. If the party that won last period decides to keep the same candidate, that candidates is known as an incumbent. In the event of a tie incumbent candidates win with probability p 2 (:5; 1). If there is no incumbent then ties are decided by a coin ip. 1 The assumption that all three groups are the same size is not essential. It is important that the l and r groups are the same size. 7

8 To summarize, within each period the timing of the game proceeds as follows: 1. The party that won last period chooses a candidate 2. The party that lost chooses a candidate. 3. Each citizen chooses whether to vote, and who to vote for. 4. The candidate with the most votes win. Next I address when citizens vote and who they vote for. 4.2 The Choice to Vote In this model I follow Riker and Ordeshook (1968) and assume people vote because they gain a consumption value for voting. This could take many forms: voters could enjoy expressing their opinion, ful lling their moral or civic duty (as in Feddersen and Sandroni (2006)) or feel social pressure to vote. The alternative approach would be to assume people vote because they might change the outcome. This view is implausible in a large election, and becomes even more implausible if there is a cost to voting. And since the motivation of this model discussed in section 2 involves a xed cost the pivotal voter view is an unpalatable choice. Formally, voting in each period yields utility of D > 0. This payo is net of cost that a voter faces every time they vote such as time spent driving to the polling place, waiting in line etc. On top of this, rst time voters face an additional cost of i in order to vote. A citizen is energized when a candidate from his own ideological group is running, and has his xed cost from voting reduced by > 0 2. It can be easily veri ed that a citizen votes in their rst period of life if and only if they vote in their second period of life. In other words the citizens can be divided into habitual voters who always vote and non-voters who never vote. I restrict i to two values L and H where H > L. The two types are evenly distributed throughout the three ideological groups. The only restriction on how many of each type is that there is strictly positive mass of both. L types nd engaging with the political relatively painless (or even enjoyable) and always vote in both periods of their life. For simplicity I set L = 0. On the other hand H types need to be energized or else they will "abstain due to alienation". Speci cally if there is a candidate from the same ideological 2 Alternatively the citizen utility s from voting could increase by when energized and nothing would change. 8

9 group in their rst period of life they decide to become habitual voters and vote in both period of life. In all other cases they never vote. Formally this is given by: (1 + )D < H < + (1 + )D 4.3 Preferences over Outcomes The parties are in nitely lived with discount rate and are both policy and o ce motivated. In any period t let w t ; y t be the party and ideology respectively of the winning candidate. Thus w t 2 fl; Rg and y t 2 fl; m; rg. Party L maximizes: 1X t (v L (w t ) + u L (y t )) t=0 Where v L (L) = > 0; v L (R) = 0 and u L (l) = 0; u L (m) = :25; u L (r) = 1. The policy motive is consistent with quadratic loss in a spatial model and represents the degree of o ce motivation. R has symmetric preferences. The citizen s preferences on the ideology of the winning candidate are straightforward. Every citizen s rst choice is a candidate with the same ideology as them. A partisan citizens (l and r types) prefers a moderate to win over a candidate with the opposite ideology. And moderate citizens are indi erent between l and r candidates. Formally let u i (x) be the utility of a citizen with ideology i when a candidate with ideology x wins and then: u l (l) > u l (m) > u l (r) u m (m) > u m (l) = u m (r) u r (r) > u r (m) > u r (l) Citizen are non-pivotal and realize it, and so always vote sincerely according to these preferences. Partisan citizens break indi erence in ideology by siding with their own party, moderate citizens break indi erence by randomizing Given this model I can establish the following results about who wins elections. Lemma 1 In every election the following statements hold: 1. A moderate candidate will always defeat a partisan candidate. 2. Suppose both parties choose moderate candidates. Then if party i chose a partisan candidate last period and party j chose a moderate last period than party i s candidate 9

10 will win. If both parties chose a partisan candidate last period, or neither did, then the election is a tie. Proof: See appendix: Lemma 1 formalizes the central logic of this work: that partisan candidate aren t as electorally viable as moderate candidate but help parties win in the future. Part 1 says a partisan can never defeat a moderate, which makes speci c how they are electorally unviable. Part 2 shows how partisan candidates help parties win in the future. Speci cally if both parties decide to win today and pick moderates then the election is decided by who energized their base last period. A result identical to part 2 would attain in the case when both parties picked a partisan candidate today. The next step is to see how these forces play out in equilibrium, which is the topic of the next section. 5 Equilibrium In this section I analyze the game described above using the solution concept of subgame perfect equilibrium. The model above will have a unique subgame perfect equilibrium, which allows for sharp predictions. This section is split into three parts. 5.1 discusses two key assumptions and introduces some useful notation. 5.2 presents the unique equilibrium in detail and gives a discussion of its important features. 5.3 provides a sketch of the proof. 5.1 Assumptions and Notation Throughout this section the following two assumptions are maintained Assumption 1 : < (1 ) ; Assumption 2 : > 1 p p The rst assumption says the parties can t be too highly o ce motivated and the second that they can t be too impatient. If the parties are patient enough (! 1), both conditions are always satis ed. Assumption 1 gives the allowed level of o ce motivation as a function of the patience of the parties. Assumption 1 is satis ed for any level of if is close enough to 1 or close enough to 0. Moreover less than 2:4 works for any. Assumption 2 says the parties have to be patient compared to the advantage incumbents get in the case of ties. As p! 1 any level of works, as p! :5 then needs to approach 1. Assumption 1 is not essential, in section 7 I show purely o ce motivated parties still retain the central behavior of conceding current elections to win later. The main di erence is with purely o ce motivated parties partisan candidates do win in equilibrium. Counterintuitively 10

11 this implies a policy motive makes it less likely for partisan policies to get enacted. On the other hand, assumption 2 is essential. In section 8 I show if the parties are too impatient then in the unique equilibrium only moderate candidates are ever chosen. It is intuitive that short sighted parties won t invest in future elections. And without this forward looking behavior my model largely resembles a standard one shot spatial model, and the logic of the median voter theorem applies. 5.2 Characterization and Discussion Here I characterize and discuss the unique subgame perfect equilibrium, which I denote by? = (? L ;? R ). The equilibrium ends up being Markovian, so it can be described using a state that includes the party that won and the positions taken in the previous period. To denote these states I will use the notation (I; x; y) where I is the party that won last period, x is that party s last period position, and y is the losing party s previous position. For example (R; m; l) means the R party won last period with a moderate candidate, and the L party lost with a partisan candidate. actions each party takes in each state. In the equilibrium the parties will use symmetric strategies, so only the states where the L party is the incumbent need to be described. This is done in the following table: State L s Position R s Position R s Position if L deviates (L; m; m) m r m (L; m; r) m m r (L; l; r) m m m Note the table doesn t include state (L; l; m) because it is impossible since the moderate candidate picked by party R can t lose to the partisan candidates picked by L. Proposition 1 Both parties employing strategy? is the unique subgame perfect equilibrium. Proof. In appendix By examining the table it can be seen that this equilibrium has the property that after any history the cyclical pattern displayed in gure 1 below results within two periods. Each box in the gure represents a period. The rst line in the box is the state, and the second line describes what happens. The rst thing to notice is a moderate candidate wins in every period, and yet partisan candidates are regularly chosen. To see why consider the lower left hand box with state (R; m; m) which means L is out of power and neither party has the advantage of an energized base. R goes rst and picks a moderate candidate. L could pick a moderate candidate which would result in a tie and give L probability 1 p < 1 2 of winning. Instead L decides to 11

12 Figure 1: Cycle in Equilibrium (R,m,l) L-m Beats R-m - (L,m,m) L-m Beats R-r 6 (R,m,m) R-m Beats L-l? (L,m,r) R-m Beats L-m concede the current election and pick a partisan. This leads to the upper left hand box (state (R; m; l)) where both parties pick moderates, but L wins for certain because they energized their base last period. Hence L trades o a chance of victory (at state (R; m; m)) for certain victory in the next period (at state (R; m; l)). Notice that 1 p represents how much L is giving up by picking a partisan. This makes clear the role of assumption 2, the parties have to be su ciently patient relative to what they are giving up by conceding the election. In the remaining two boxes, (L; m; m) and (L; m; r), the same story occurs with the role of the two parties switched. One feature that might seem puzzling is that R chooses a moderate candidate in the upper left box in state (R; m; l). R knows L s base is energized, and can foresee defeat, so why doesn t he choose a partisan candidate to build a stronger future? Well if R chooses a partisan then party L can also choose a partisan and win for sure (recall R has to go rst). And since R has a policy motive he prefers to lose to a moderate than lose to a partisan. That R acts in this way is the content of assumption 1. Thus the policy motive of the parties acts to prevent partisan candidates from winning, which is a counterintuitive result. This point is exactly how the equilibrium with purely o ce motivated di ers from the above cycle, and will be discussed in more detail in section 7. Another feature of this cycle is that parties alternate in power in a predictable fashion. This is a result of the fundamental tension between winning today and tomorrow. In equilibrium, only moderates ever win, but they fail to energize the base, and leave the winning party with a weakened future. This creates a testable prediction: that the longer a party is in power the more likely it is to lose the next election. This prediction, as well as two others, will be more fully discussed in section 6. That the model has a unique subgame perfect equilibrium is a striking feature. Uniqueness allows for sharp predictions, which is uncommon for in nite horizon games which are 12

13 usually plagued by multiplicity as is allowed to go to 1. Dutta (1995) provides a folk theorem that applies to a wide class of games with state dependent payo s, including my model. He shows that, under some regularity conditions, any feasible payo that is above the min max can be achieved with su ciently patient players. As will be discussed in more detail in 5.3, uniqueness holds because the equilibrium is both strongly e cient and pushes both players to their min max payo. Thus the equilibrium is the only arrangement of strategies that is individually rational for both players. The intuition for why? is unique is the model is almost a zero sum game. To see this note that if a moderate always wins then the only variation in payo s comes from who get the o ce motivated payo, which is zero sum. And as seen in Lemma 1 a moderate always defeats a partisan, so a partisan can only win if the other party allows it. And the parties won t allow it as long as they are su ciently policy motivated, which is guaranteed by assumption Sketch of Proof Verifying that? is an equilibrium is simply an application of the one shot deviation principle; see appendix for calculations. The calculations are made manageable by the fact the equilibrium is Markovian. Additionally the strict inequalities in the assumptions implies the one shot deviation principle holds strictly at every history, which will be used to prove the equilibrium is unique. To see why? is unique consider any history h that begins a period, so that it is the party in power s turn to move. Let V i? (h) be the continuation payo party i receives at history h if both parties are employing strategy?. The proof starts by establishing the following three statements: 1. At history h, each party can achieve at least V i? (h), no matter the strategy of the other party. 2.? is strongly e cient in the sense that the sum of continuations payo s at history h can never exceed V? L (h) + V? R (h) 3. 1 and 2 imply that in any equilibrium the continuation payo of both parties at history h must be V i? (h). That statement 3 follows from 1 and 2 is obvious. Statement 2 can be seen by noting that if a partisan candidate wins the parties combined payo is candidate wins it is 1 and if a moderate :5 and these are the only two possibilities. Thus combined payo is 13

14 maximized when a moderate always win, which happens in equilibrium? starting from any history that begins a period. To see statement 1 suppose that party L commits to playing strategy? L, look for the the strategy of R that minimizes L s payo. Notice that, no matter what R does,? L ensures an r type will never win. Thus it is intuitive the worst case for L will have a moderate winning in every period 3. But when a moderate always wins the game is zero sum, and so the strategy that minimizes L s payo is the strategy that maximizes R s payo, which is? R. Thus L s worst case is V L? (h) and hence he can always achieve this payo by playing? L. Given statement 3 the rest of the proof proceed as follows. Take any history h that doesn t start a period, i.e. where it is the out of power party s turn to move. WLOG let it be L s turn to move. Once L moves the next history will be one that starts a period. Using statement 3, for any action a, L 0 s continuation payo must be V L? ((h; a)). This, plus the fact that the one shot deviation principle holds strictly for? L, means that in any equilibrium L must take the same action? L at history h. And this can be used to show the continuation payo s for both parties at h must be V i? (h). And then this same argument can be applied again on histories that start a period, which completes the proof. 6 Three Testable Predictions The model delivers three testable predictions, each of which derives from the central tension between winning today and winning tomorrow. In this section I will discuss these predictions and present some empirical support for them found in the literature. Additionally I will argue that these predictions sharply distinguish my model from the previous models discussed in section 3. Prediction 1: The longer a party is in power the more likely they are to lose the next election The most fundamental consequence of the trade-o parties face between winning today or tomorrow is that the winning party sets itself up for a weaker future. In equilibrium only moderates win, and hence the winning party never energizes its base. A base that isn t energized hurts the party s future turnout leading to its eventual defeat. This dynamic gives rise to prediction 1. In the equilibrium presented this takes the sharp form that a party that has been in power for two periods loses the next election with certainty. This prediction is inter-temporal in nature which means it cannot be generated in a one period model, such as 3 The proof of this requires assumption 1. See Lemma A in the appendix for full details. 14

15 the previous models of candidate selection discussed in section 3. This make this prediction a novel one in the context of that literature. There is evidence supporting this prediction. Looking at U.S. presidential elections Abramowitz (1988) nds what he calls a "time for a change" e ect. He estimates that a party which holds the Presidency for two terms su ers a four percentage point penalty in the popular vote in the next election. This e ect is robust to including a number of controls including an incumbency e ect. The incumbency control is particularly important because of the two term limit for U.S. Presidents. Along similar lines Lewis-Beck and Nadeau (2004) looks at data from the United Kingdom and nds a 3 percentage penalty for each term a party holds power. Prediction 2: Parties diverge in the ideology of the candidates chosen, but not in policies implemented A key feature of the equilibrium presented above is that moderates always win and yet partisans are still chosen. This runs in sharp contrast to the models in section 3 which had partisans winning in equilibrium. Indeed I argue this prediction cannot be generated in a one period model without contradicting the strong empirical fact (discussed in section 3) that moderate candidates perform better in elections. Intuitively parties should care only about two things: winning and policy. So in a one period model only winning today and policy today can matter. But prediction 2 speci es convergence in policy between the parties, so policy can t be the reason for choosing a partisan. And, as already stated, moderates are better at winning. Thus it becomes impossible to explain why partisan candidates are ever chosen in a one period model. My model solves this by adding something new for parties to care about: winning and policy in future periods. There is moderate evidence to support this prediction. The evidence is limited in that it focuses almost exclusively on the relationship between the ideology of the government in power and government spending as percentage of GDP. Imbeau (2001) surveys 43 such studies of which 29 nd no signi cant relationship. Additionally, many of the studies that found a signi cant relationship found a very small one. For example Blais et al. (1996) nds that a government controlled entirely by the left only spends 0.4% of GDP more than an entirely right controlled government. Prediction 3: Parties newly out of power nominate more partisan candidates Another consequence of parties making inter-temporal choices about who to nominate is there can be predictable time series pattern in that choice. In the equilibrium presented 15

16 above the parties always (and only) nominate a partisan candidate in the period after losing power. The logic behind this is while in power a party tends to neglect its base, so it needs to reenergize it before being able to reclaim power. Again the inter-temporal nature of this prediction means it could not be generated in any of the one period models of candidate selection discussed in section 3. There is evidence to support this prediction. Cohen et al. (2008) looked at the relationship between the ideology of the candidate of the out of power party and the number of years the party has been out of power. They focus on U.S. presidential elections and rate the ideology of the candidates using the National Election Survey. They nd the longer the party has been out of power the more moderate the candidate. This directly matches up with prediction 3. Their result can be seen graphically in gure 2 below, which is taken directly from their book. Figure 2: Taken from Cohen et al. (2008) pg

17 7 O ce Motivated Candidates In this section I consider the case where parties are purely o ce motivated. I nd and discuss the unique subgame perfect equilibrium. The key feature of the original equilibrium, that parties concede election to invest in the future, is preserved. The main di erence from section 5 is that partisan candidates win in equilibrium. This gives the counterintuitive result that a policy motive enforces a median voter result in the outcomes of elections. The only change to the model is to the parties payo. Party L now maximizes: 1X t (v L (w t )) t=0 Where w t 2 fl; Rg is the party of the winning candidate and v L (L) = 1 and v L (R) = 0. Party R s preferences are symmetric. impatient, so I impose assumption 3: It is still important that the parties are not too Assumption 3 : p > This is more complicated than assumption 2 but serves much the same role, and gives the required level of patience as a function of the incumbency advantage. I describe the strategy pair? o ce =? L;o ce ;? R,o ce in the following matrix. Just as in? the equilibrium is symmetric so I only describe the states where L is in power. State L s Action R s Action R s Action if L deviates (L; m; m) m r m (L; m; r) l r m (L; l; r) m m m Proposition 2? o ce is the unique sub game perfect equilibrium. Proof: In Appendix. By examining? o ce it can be seen that after any history, within 2 periods, the following cycle results. Unlike the previous cycle this one involve ties. Where the ties occur the party in power did not keep their incumbent candidate, so the election is decided by a fair coin ip. The boxes where the ties occur have two arrows coming out to indicate the two possibilities, each of which occur with probability 1. Conceding the current election to invest in the future still 2 occurs at states (R; m; m) and (L; m; m) (the two center boxes), which is the same states where it happened in the original equilibrium. Thus purely o ce motived parties maintain the central feature of the original equilibrium. 17

18 Figure 3: Cycle in Equilibrium (R,r,l) R-m ties L-m 6 (L,m,r) R-r Beats L-l 1 * 2 H HHj 1 2 (R,m,m) R-m Beats L-l (L,m,m) L-m Beats R-r * 1 2 HY H H 1 2 (R,m,l) L-l Beats R-r? (L,l,r) L-m ties R-m The main di erence from the original equilibrium occurs at states (R; m; l) and (L; m; r), lower left and upper right boxes respectively. Under?, in these states both parties move to the middle and the side with the energized base wins with certainty. In? o ce the side with the energized base still wins, but both parties choose partisan candidates. The reason for this is the party without the energized base knows they are going to lose no matter what. Their only motive for taking a moderate position is to keep a partisan from the other side out of power. Since there is no policy motive they don t care about that and choose instead to pick a partisan candidate to build a stronger future. This provides the counterintuitive result that a policy motive prevents partisan candidates from winning. 8 Short Sighted Parties In this section I consider parties who are short sighted. Formally I take the opposite inequality of assumption 2 and suppose < 1 p p. For simplicity I take the case that parties are completely o ce motivated as in section 7, but the results would generalize to any level of o ce motive. Consider the strategy pair? short =? L;short ; R,short?, which is described in the following matrix. 18

19 State L s Action R s Action R s Action if L deviates (L; m; m) m m m (L; m; r) l r m (L; l; r) m m m Proposition 3 Suppose < 1 p p is the unique subgame perfect equilibrium. and the parties are completely o ce motivated. Then? short Proof: In appendix. The only di erence between the equilibrium here and the one in section 7 is that at states (L; m; m) and (R; m; m) both parties pick a moderate candidates and the election is a tie. So with probability p the state remains same and with probability 1 p the state switches to either (L; m; m) or (R; m; m), whichever is not the current state. This means once one of these two states are reached the equilibrium will stochastically alternate between them forever. And it can be veri ed that any of the other states will lead to either (L; m; m) or (R; m; m) within two periods. This result could be generalized to policy motivated parties as well. The only change would that at state (L; m; r) the L party would take action m and similarly for the state (R; m; l). So with short sighted parties the equilibrium is one in which both parties converge to the center in every period. This occurs because when parties ignore the future my model strongly resembles the standard one period model with no uncertainty. Myopic parties are not willing to lose today to invest in the future, and thus lose their only incentive to pick partisan candidates. 9 Conclusion In this work I argued that partisan candidates are less electorally viable, but energize the base which is valuable for future elections. I motivated this mechanism with empirical evidence on habitual voting and abstention due to alienation. Previous formal models of candidate selection have largely been one period in which parties can only care about who wins today and what policy gets enacted today. By introducing parties that are forward looking I allow for a new reason to pick partisan candidates: winning in the future. The model also generates three novel testable predictions, which match evidence found in the literature. The core innovation of this work is that parties also care about winning and policy in the future. That is parties are patient enough to consider the rami cation of their actions on future elections. This work has focused speci cally on the mechanism of partisan candidates energizing the base. But this is just one example of a larger principle; exploring other ways 19

20 forward looking behavior can impact political strategies presents an important direction for future work. References Abramowitz, A. (1988). An improved model for predicting presidential election outcomes. PS: Political science and politics, 21(4): Adams, J., Dow, J., and Merrill, S. (2006). The political consequences of alienation-based and indi erence-based voter abstention: Applications to Presidential Elections. Political Behavior, 28(1): Adams, J. and Merrill III, S. (2003). Voter turnout and candidate strategies in American elections. Journal of Politics, 65(1): Ansolabehere, S., Snyder Jr, J., and Stewart III, C. (2001). Candidate positioning in US House elections. American Journal of Political Science, 45(1): Blais, A., Blake, D., and Dion, S. (1996). Do Parties Make a Di erence? A Reappraisal. American Journal of Political Science, 40(2):514. Brody, R. (1977). From life space to polling place: The relevance of personal concerns for voting behavior. British Journal of Political, 7(03):337. Calvert, R. (1985). Robustness of the multidimensional voting model: Candidate motivations, uncertainty, and convergence. American Journal of Political Science, 29(1): Cohen, M., Karol, D., Noel, H., and Zaller, J. (2008). The Party Decides. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of political action in a democracy. The Journal of Political Economy, 65(2): Dutta, P. (1995). A folk theorem for stochastic games. Journal of Economic Theory. Erikson, R. and Wright, G. (2005). Voters, Candidates, and Issues in Congressional Elections. In Dodd, L. and Oppenheimer, B., editors, Congress Reconsidered, pages CQ Press, 8th edition. Feddersen, T. J. and Sandroni, A. (2006). A Theory of Participation in Elections. American Economic Review, 96(4):

21 Franklin, M. (2004). Voter turnout and the dynamics of electoral competition in established democracies since Cambridge Univ Pr. Gerber, A. S., Green, D. P., and Shachar, R. (2003). Voting May Be Habit-Forming: Evidence from a Randomized Field Experiment. American Journal of Political Science, 47(3): Goldwater, B. (1988). Goldwater. Doubleday, New York. Green, D. and Shachar, R. (2000). Habit formation and political behaviour: Evidence of consuetude in voter turnout. British Journal of Political Science, 72(1978): Imbeau, L. (2001). Left-right party ideology and government policies: A meta-analysis. European Journal of Political Research, pages Lewis-Beck, M. and Nadeau, R. (2004). General election forecasts in the United Kingdom: a political economy model. Electoral Studies, 23: Middendorf, J. (2006). A Glorious Disaster: Barry Goldwater s Presidential Campaign and the Origins of the Conservative Movement. Basic Books, New York. Miller, W. and Shanks, J. (1996). The new American voter. Harvard University Press Cambridge, Cambridge. Palfrey, T. R. (1984). Spatial Equilibrium with Entry. The Review of Economic Studies, 51(1):139. Plane, D. and Gershtenson, J. (2004). Candidates ideological locations, abstention, and turnout in US midterm senate elections. Political Behavior, 26(1): Plutzer, E. (2002). Becoming a habitual voter: Inertia, resources, and growth in young adulthood. American Political Science Review, 96(01): Riker, W. and Ordeshook, P. (1968). A Theory of the Calculus of Voting. The American Political Science Review, 62(1): Roemer, J. (1994). A theory of policy di erentiation in single issue electoral politics. Social Choice and Welfare, pages Segal, D. (1968). Partisan realignment in the United States: the lesson of the 1964 election. The Public Opinion Quarterly, 32(3):

22 Wittman, D. (1983). Candidate Motivation: A Synthesis of Alternative Theories. The American Political Science Review, 77(1):142. Zipp, J. (1985). Perceived Representativess and Voting: An Assessment of the Impact of" Choices" vs." Echoes". The American political science review, 79(1):

Polarization and Income Inequality: A Dynamic Model of Unequal Democracy

Polarization and Income Inequality: A Dynamic Model of Unequal Democracy Polarization and Income Inequality: A Dynamic Model of Unequal Democracy Timothy Feddersen and Faruk Gul 1 March 30th 2015 1 We thank Weifeng Zhong for research assistance. Thanks also to John Duggan for

More information

Nomination Processes and Policy Outcomes

Nomination Processes and Policy Outcomes Nomination Processes and Policy Outcomes Matthew O. Jackson, Laurent Mathevet, Kyle Mattes y Forthcoming: Quarterly Journal of Political Science Abstract We provide a set of new models of three di erent

More information

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas?

'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas? 'Wave riding' or 'Owning the issue': How do candidates determine campaign agendas? Mariya Burdina University of Colorado, Boulder Department of Economics October 5th, 008 Abstract In this paper I adress

More information

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study

Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Supporting Information Political Quid Pro Quo Agreements: An Experimental Study Jens Großer Florida State University and IAS, Princeton Ernesto Reuben Columbia University and IZA Agnieszka Tymula New York

More information

Turnout and Strength of Habits

Turnout and Strength of Habits Turnout and Strength of Habits John H. Aldrich Wendy Wood Jacob M. Montgomery Duke University I) Introduction Social scientists are much better at explaining for whom people vote than whether people vote

More information

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES

Political Economics II Spring Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency. Torsten Persson, IIES Lectures 4-5_190213.pdf Political Economics II Spring 2019 Lectures 4-5 Part II Partisan Politics and Political Agency Torsten Persson, IIES 1 Introduction: Partisan Politics Aims continue exploring policy

More information

Policy Reversal. Espen R. Moen and Christian Riis. Abstract. We analyze the existence of policy reversal, the phenomenon sometimes observed

Policy Reversal. Espen R. Moen and Christian Riis. Abstract. We analyze the existence of policy reversal, the phenomenon sometimes observed Policy Reversal Espen R. Moen and Christian Riis Abstract We analyze the existence of policy reversal, the phenomenon sometimes observed that a certain policy (say extreme left-wing) is implemented by

More information

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout Esteban F. Klor y and Eyal Winter z September 2006 We are grateful to Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau, Eric Gould, Dan Levin, Bradley Ru e and Moses Shayo for very helpful

More information

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000

Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania. March 9, 2000 Campaign Rhetoric: a model of reputation Enriqueta Aragones Harvard University and Universitat Pompeu Fabra Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania March 9, 2000 Abstract We develop a model of infinitely

More information

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty

1 Electoral Competition under Certainty 1 Electoral Competition under Certainty We begin with models of electoral competition. This chapter explores electoral competition when voting behavior is deterministic; the following chapter considers

More information

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT

HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT HOTELLING-DOWNS MODEL OF ELECTORAL COMPETITION AND THE OPTION TO QUIT ABHIJIT SENGUPTA AND KUNAL SENGUPTA SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE UNIVERSITY OF SYDNEY SYDNEY, NSW 2006 AUSTRALIA Abstract.

More information

The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting 1

The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting 1 The E ects of Identities, Incentives, and Information on Voting Anna Bassi 2 Rebecca Morton 3 Kenneth Williams 4 July 2, 28 We thank Ted Brader, Jens Grosser, Gabe Lenz, Tom Palfrey, Brian Rogers, Josh

More information

Nominations for Sale. Silvia Console-Battilana and Kenneth A. Shepsle y. 1 Introduction

Nominations for Sale. Silvia Console-Battilana and Kenneth A. Shepsle y. 1 Introduction Nominations for Sale Silvia Console-Battilana and Kenneth A. Shepsle y Abstract Models of nomination politics in the US often nd "gridlock" in equilibrium because of the super-majority requirement in the

More information

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts. The call for more transparency is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits Decision Making Procedures for Committees of Careerist Experts Gilat Levy; Department of Economics, London School of Economics. The call for "more transparency" is voiced nowadays by politicians and pundits

More information

Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership

Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership Party Platforms with Endogenous Party Membership Panu Poutvaara 1 Harvard University, Department of Economics poutvaar@fas.harvard.edu Abstract In representative democracies, the development of party platforms

More information

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout

On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout On Public Opinion Polls and Voters Turnout Esteban F. Klor y and Eyal Winter z March 2014 We are grateful to Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau, Eric Gould, Dan Levin, Rebecca Morton, Bradley Ru e and Moses Shayo

More information

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability

Policy Reputation and Political Accountability Policy Reputation and Political Accountability Tapas Kundu October 9, 2016 Abstract We develop a model of electoral competition where both economic policy and politician s e ort a ect voters payo. When

More information

Notes on Strategic and Sincere Voting

Notes on Strategic and Sincere Voting Notes on Strategic and Sincere Voting Francesco Trebbi March 8, 2019 Idea Kawai and Watanabe (AER 2013): Inferring Strategic Voting. They structurally estimate a model of strategic voting and quantify

More information

Answers to Practice Problems. Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism.

Answers to Practice Problems. Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism. Answers to Practice Problems Median voter theorem, supermajority rule, & bicameralism. Median Voter Theorem Questions: 2.1-2.4, and 2.8. Located at the end of Hinich and Munger, chapter 2, The Spatial

More information

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002.

Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002. Sampling Equilibrium, with an Application to Strategic Voting Martin J. Osborne 1 and Ariel Rubinstein 2 September 12th, 2002 Abstract We suggest an equilibrium concept for a strategic model with a large

More information

Voting Criteria April

Voting Criteria April Voting Criteria 21-301 2018 30 April 1 Evaluating voting methods In the last session, we learned about different voting methods. In this session, we will focus on the criteria we use to evaluate whether

More information

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation

The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation The Robustness of Herrera, Levine and Martinelli s Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation Alexander Chun June 8, 009 Abstract In this paper, I look at potential weaknesses in the electoral

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 4 and 5: Voting and Political Decisions in Practice

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 4 and 5: Voting and Political Decisions in Practice 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 4 and 5: Voting and Political Decisions in Practice Daron Acemoglu MIT September 18 and 20, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 4 and

More information

Voting and Electoral Competition

Voting and Electoral Competition Voting and Electoral Competition Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute On the organization of the course Lectures, exam at the end Articles to read. In more technical articles, it

More information

Reputation E ects and Incumbency (Dis)Advantage. November 2017

Reputation E ects and Incumbency (Dis)Advantage. November 2017 Reputation E ects and Incumbency (Dis)Advantage Navin Kartik Richard Van Weelden November 2017 Motivation 1 How to discipline elected policymakers? main instrument: re-election decision; electoral accountability

More information

A MODEL OF POLITICAL COMPETITION WITH CITIZEN-CANDIDATES. Martin J. Osborne and Al Slivinski. Abstract

A MODEL OF POLITICAL COMPETITION WITH CITIZEN-CANDIDATES. Martin J. Osborne and Al Slivinski. Abstract Published in Quarterly Journal of Economics 111 (1996), 65 96. Copyright c 1996 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. A MODEL OF POLITICAL COMPETITION

More information

Ambiguity and Extremism in Elections

Ambiguity and Extremism in Elections Ambiguity and Extremism in Elections Alberto Alesina Harvard University Richard Holden Massachusetts Institute of Technology June 008 Abstract We analyze a model in which voters are uncertain about the

More information

The Case of the Disappearing Bias: A 2014 Update to the Gerrymandering or Geography Debate

The Case of the Disappearing Bias: A 2014 Update to the Gerrymandering or Geography Debate The Case of the Disappearing Bias: A 2014 Update to the Gerrymandering or Geography Debate Nicholas Goedert Lafayette College goedertn@lafayette.edu May, 2015 ABSTRACT: This note observes that the pro-republican

More information

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits Voluntary Voting: Costs and Benefits Vijay Krishna and John Morgan May 21, 2012 Abstract We compare voluntary and compulsory voting in a Condorcet-type model in which voters have identical preferences

More information

Lobbying and Elections

Lobbying and Elections Lobbying and Elections Jan Klingelhöfer RWTH Aachen University April 15, 2013 Abstract analyze the interaction between post-election lobbying and the voting decisions of forward-looking voters. The existing

More information

Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1

Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1 Let the Experts Decide? Asymmetric Information, Abstention, and Coordination in Standing Committees 1 Rebecca Morton 2 Jean-Robert Tyran 3 November 2, 2008 1 We appreciate greatly the work of Michael Rudy

More information

Decentralization via Federal and Unitary Referenda

Decentralization via Federal and Unitary Referenda Decentralization via Federal and Unitary Referenda First Version: January 1997 This version: May 22 Ben Lockwood 1 Department of Economics, University of Warwick, Coventry CV4 7AL UK. email: b.lockwood@warwick.ac.uk

More information

Public and Private Welfare State Institutions

Public and Private Welfare State Institutions Public and Private Welfare State Institutions A Formal Theory of American Exceptionalism Kaj Thomsson, Yale University and RIIE y November 15, 2008 Abstract I develop a formal model of di erential welfare

More information

Part I: Univariate Spatial Model (20%)

Part I: Univariate Spatial Model (20%) 17.251 Fall 2012 Midterm Exam answers Directions: Do the following problem. Part I: Univariate Spatial Model (20%) The nation is faced with a situation in which, if legislation isn t passed, the level

More information

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997)

Classical papers: Osborbe and Slivinski (1996) and Besley and Coate (1997) The identity of politicians is endogenized Typical approach: any citizen may enter electoral competition at a cost. There is no pre-commitment on the platforms, and winner implements his or her ideal policy.

More information

Supplementary Materials for Strategic Abstention in Proportional Representation Systems (Evidence from Multiple Countries)

Supplementary Materials for Strategic Abstention in Proportional Representation Systems (Evidence from Multiple Countries) Supplementary Materials for Strategic Abstention in Proportional Representation Systems (Evidence from Multiple Countries) Guillem Riambau July 15, 2018 1 1 Construction of variables and descriptive statistics.

More information

Problems with Group Decision Making

Problems with Group Decision Making Problems with Group Decision Making There are two ways of evaluating political systems: 1. Consequentialist ethics evaluate actions, policies, or institutions in regard to the outcomes they produce. 2.

More information

Case Study: Get out the Vote

Case Study: Get out the Vote Case Study: Get out the Vote Do Phone Calls to Encourage Voting Work? Why Randomize? This case study is based on Comparing Experimental and Matching Methods Using a Large-Scale Field Experiment on Voter

More information

Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute for Economic Research

Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute for Economic Research Prof. Panu Poutvaara University of Munich and Ifo Institute for Economic Research Lectures, exam at the end Articles to read. In more technical articles, it suffices to read introduction and conclusion

More information

Amy Tenhouse. Incumbency Surge: Examining the 1996 Margin of Victory for U.S. House Incumbents

Amy Tenhouse. Incumbency Surge: Examining the 1996 Margin of Victory for U.S. House Incumbents Amy Tenhouse Incumbency Surge: Examining the 1996 Margin of Victory for U.S. House Incumbents In 1996, the American public reelected 357 members to the United States House of Representatives; of those

More information

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association

Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association Published in Canadian Journal of Economics 27 (1995), 261 301. Copyright c 1995 by Canadian Economics Association Spatial Models of Political Competition Under Plurality Rule: A Survey of Some Explanations

More information

Developing Political Preferences: Citizen Self-Interest

Developing Political Preferences: Citizen Self-Interest Developing Political Preferences: Citizen Self-Interest Carlos Algara calgara@ucdavis.edu October 12, 2017 Agenda 1 Revising the Paradox 2 Abstention Incentive: Opinion Instability 3 Heuristics as Short-Cuts:

More information

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 1 VOTING ON INCOME REDISTRIBUTION: HOW A LITTLE BIT OF ALTRUISM CREATES TRANSITIVITY DONALD WITTMAN ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ wittman@ucsc.edu ABSTRACT We consider an election

More information

Quorum Rules and Shareholder Power

Quorum Rules and Shareholder Power Quorum Rules and Shareholder Power Patricia Charléty y, Marie-Cécile Fagart z and Saïd Souam x February 15, 2016 Abstract This paper completely characterizes the equilibria of a costly voting game where

More information

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE N. R. Miller 05/01/97 5 th rev. 8/22/06 VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE This discussion focuses on single-winner elections, in which a single candidate is elected from a field of two or more candidates.

More information

Font Size: A A. Eric Maskin and Amartya Sen JANUARY 19, 2017 ISSUE. 1 of 7 2/21/ :01 AM

Font Size: A A. Eric Maskin and Amartya Sen JANUARY 19, 2017 ISSUE. 1 of 7 2/21/ :01 AM 1 of 7 2/21/2017 10:01 AM Font Size: A A Eric Maskin and Amartya Sen JANUARY 19, 2017 ISSUE Americans have been using essentially the same rules to elect presidents since the beginning of the Republic.

More information

Many Social Choice Rules

Many Social Choice Rules Many Social Choice Rules 1 Introduction So far, I have mentioned several of the most commonly used social choice rules : pairwise majority rule, plurality, plurality with a single run off, the Borda count.

More information

Candidate Citizen Models

Candidate Citizen Models Candidate Citizen Models General setup Number of candidates is endogenous Candidates are unable to make binding campaign promises whoever wins office implements her ideal policy Citizens preferences are

More information

A Vote Equation and the 2004 Election

A Vote Equation and the 2004 Election A Vote Equation and the 2004 Election Ray C. Fair November 22, 2004 1 Introduction My presidential vote equation is a great teaching example for introductory econometrics. 1 The theory is straightforward,

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lecture 11: Economic Policy under Representative Democracy Daron Acemoglu MIT October 16, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lecture 11 October 16, 2017.

More information

Coalition Governments and Political Rents

Coalition Governments and Political Rents Coalition Governments and Political Rents Dr. Refik Emre Aytimur Georg-August-Universität Göttingen January 01 Abstract We analyze the impact of coalition governments on the ability of political competition

More information

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete

International Cooperation, Parties and. Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete International Cooperation, Parties and Ideology - Very preliminary and incomplete Jan Klingelhöfer RWTH Aachen University February 15, 2015 Abstract I combine a model of international cooperation with

More information

Distributive Politics and Economic Ideology

Distributive Politics and Economic Ideology MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Distributive Politics and Economic Ideology David Lopez-Rodriguez Columbia University, Department of Economics 2011 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/44145/ MPRA

More information

Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention

Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention Excerpts from Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row, 1957. (pp. 260-274) Introduction Chapter 14. The Causes and Effects of Rational Abstention Citizens who are eligible

More information

Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States. Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley

Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States. Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley Authoritarianism and Democracy in Rentier States Thad Dunning Department of Political Science University of California, Berkeley CHAPTER THREE FORMAL MODEL 1 CHAPTER THREE 1 Introduction In Chapters One

More information

Political Parties and Network Formation

Political Parties and Network Formation ömmföäflsäafaäsflassflassflas ffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffffff Discussion Papers Political Parties and Network Formation Topi Miettinen University of Helsinki, RUESG and HECER and University College

More information

Diversity and Redistribution

Diversity and Redistribution Diversity and Redistribution Raquel Fernández y NYU, CEPR, NBER Gilat Levy z LSE and CEPR Revised: October 2007 Abstract In this paper we analyze the interaction of income and preference heterogeneity

More information

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures Mathematics and Social Choice Theory Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives 4.1 Social choice procedures 4.2 Analysis of voting methods 4.3 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem 4.4 Cumulative voting

More information

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections

Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections Reputation and Rhetoric in Elections Enriqueta Aragonès Institut d Anàlisi Econòmica, CSIC Andrew Postlewaite University of Pennsylvania April 11, 2005 Thomas R. Palfrey Princeton University Earlier versions

More information

Bipartisan Gerrymandering

Bipartisan Gerrymandering Bipartisan Gerrymandering Hideo Konishi y Chen-Yu Pan z February 15, 2016 Abstract In this paper we propose a tractable model of partisan gerrymandering followed by electoral competitions in policy positions

More information

External Validation of Voter Turnout Models by Concealed Parameter Recovery 1

External Validation of Voter Turnout Models by Concealed Parameter Recovery 1 External Validation of Voter Turnout odels by Concealed Parameter Recovery 1 Antonio erlo 2 Thomas R. Palfrey 3 October 2017 1 We gratefully acknowledge the nancial support of the National Science Foundation

More information

Should the Democrats move to the left on economic policy?

Should the Democrats move to the left on economic policy? Should the Democrats move to the left on economic policy? Andrew Gelman Cexun Jeffrey Cai November 9, 2007 Abstract Could John Kerry have gained votes in the recent Presidential election by more clearly

More information

E ciency, Equity, and Timing of Voting Mechanisms 1

E ciency, Equity, and Timing of Voting Mechanisms 1 E ciency, Equity, and Timing of Voting Mechanisms 1 Marco Battaglini Princeton University Rebecca Morton New York University Thomas Palfrey California Institute of Technology This version November 29,

More information

Media Bias and Electoral Competition

Media Bias and Electoral Competition Media Bias and Electoral Competition Archishman Chakraborty y Parikshit Ghosh z November 010 Abstract We introduce mass media in a one-dimensional Downsian model of electoral competition in order to address

More information

Should rational voters rely only on candidates characteristics?

Should rational voters rely only on candidates characteristics? Should rational voters rely only on candidates characteristics? Sergio Vicente. IDEA, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona. February 006. Abstract This paper analyzes the role of information in elections

More information

The Idealized Electoral College Voting Mechanism and. Shareholder Power

The Idealized Electoral College Voting Mechanism and. Shareholder Power The Idealied Electoral College Voting Mechanism and Shareholder Power Edward Dickersin Van Wesep September 17, 2012 Abstract Increasing concern over corporate governance has led to calls for more shareholder

More information

Weak States And Steady States: The Dynamics of Fiscal Capacity

Weak States And Steady States: The Dynamics of Fiscal Capacity Weak States And Steady States: The Dynamics of Fiscal Capacity Timothy Besley London School of Economics and CIFAR Ethan Ilzetzki London School of Economics Torsten Persson IIES, Stockholm University and

More information

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory 3.1 Social choice procedures Plurality voting Borda count Elimination procedures Sequential pairwise

More information

Following the Leader: The Impact of Presidential Campaign Visits on Legislative Support for the President's Policy Preferences

Following the Leader: The Impact of Presidential Campaign Visits on Legislative Support for the President's Policy Preferences University of Colorado, Boulder CU Scholar Undergraduate Honors Theses Honors Program Spring 2011 Following the Leader: The Impact of Presidential Campaign Visits on Legislative Support for the President's

More information

The 2010 Midterm Election for the US House of Representatives

The 2010 Midterm Election for the US House of Representatives Douglas A. Hibbs, Jr. www.douglas-hibbs.com/house2010election22september2010.pdf Center for Public Sector Research (CEFOS), Gothenburg University 22 September 2010 (to be updated at BEA s next data release

More information

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing

Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing Information Aggregation in Voting with Endogenous Timing Konstantinos N. Rokas & Vinayak Tripathi Princeton University June 17, 2007 Abstract We study information aggregation in an election where agents

More information

WORKING PAPER NO. 256 INFORMATION ACQUISITION AND DECISION MAKING IN COMMITTEES: A SURVEY

WORKING PAPER NO. 256 INFORMATION ACQUISITION AND DECISION MAKING IN COMMITTEES: A SURVEY EUROPEAN CENTRAL BANK WORKING PAPER SERIES E C B E Z B E K T B C E E K P WORKING PAPER NO. 256 INFORMATION ACQUISITION AND DECISION MAKING IN COMMITTEES: A SURVEY BY KERSTIN GERLING, HANS PETER GRÜNER,

More information

3 Electoral Competition

3 Electoral Competition 3 Electoral Competition We now turn to a discussion of two-party electoral competition in representative democracy. The underlying policy question addressed in this chapter, as well as the remaining chapters

More information

The California Primary and Redistricting

The California Primary and Redistricting The California Primary and Redistricting This study analyzes what is the important impact of changes in the primary voting rules after a Congressional and Legislative Redistricting. Under a citizen s committee,

More information

14.11: Experiments in Political Science

14.11: Experiments in Political Science 14.11: Experiments in Political Science Prof. Esther Duflo May 9, 2006 Voting is a paradoxical behavior: the chance of being the pivotal voter in an election is close to zero, and yet people do vote...

More information

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma K r Eliaz and Roberto Serrano y February 20, 2013 Abstract Consider the problem of information disclosure for a planner

More information

Political Agency in Democracies and Dictatorships. Georgy Vladimirovich Egorov

Political Agency in Democracies and Dictatorships. Georgy Vladimirovich Egorov Political Agency in Democracies and Dictatorships A dissertation presented by Georgy Vladimirovich Egorov to The Department of Economics in partial ful llment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor

More information

The welfare consequences of strategic behaviour under approval and plurality voting

The welfare consequences of strategic behaviour under approval and plurality voting The welfare consequences of strategic behaviour under approval and plurality voting Aki Lehtinen Department of social and moral philosophy P.O.Box9 00014 University of Helsinki Finland aki.lehtinen@helsinki.

More information

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems

Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems Soc Choice Welf (018) 50:81 303 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1084- ORIGINAL PAPER Preferential votes and minority representation in open list proportional representation systems Margherita Negri

More information

Electing the President. Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling

Electing the President. Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling Electing the President Chapter 12 Mathematical Modeling Phases of the Election 1. State Primaries seeking nomination how to position the candidate to gather momentum in a set of contests 2. Conventions

More information

Political Economy. Pierre Boyer. Master in Economics Fall 2018 Schedule: Every Wednesday 08:30 to 11:45. École Polytechnique - CREST

Political Economy. Pierre Boyer. Master in Economics Fall 2018 Schedule: Every Wednesday 08:30 to 11:45. École Polytechnique - CREST Political Economy Pierre Boyer École Polytechnique - CREST Master in Economics Fall 2018 Schedule: Every Wednesday 08:30 to 11:45 Boyer (École Polytechnique) Political Economy Fall 2018 1 / 18 Outline

More information

Federal Primary Election Runoffs and Voter Turnout Decline,

Federal Primary Election Runoffs and Voter Turnout Decline, Federal Primary Election Runoffs and Voter Turnout Decline, 1994-2010 July 2011 By: Katherine Sicienski, William Hix, and Rob Richie Summary of Facts and Findings Near-Universal Decline in Turnout: Of

More information

Coalition and Party Formation in a Legislative. Voting Game. April 1998, Revision: April Forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Theory.

Coalition and Party Formation in a Legislative. Voting Game. April 1998, Revision: April Forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Theory. Coalition and Party Formation in a Legislative Voting Game Matthew O. Jackson and Boaz Moselle April 1998, Revision: April 2000 Forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Theory Abstract We examine a legislative

More information

The Case of the Disappearing Bias: A 2014 Update to the Gerrymandering or Geography Debate

The Case of the Disappearing Bias: A 2014 Update to the Gerrymandering or Geography Debate The Case of the Disappearing Bias: A 2014 Update to the Gerrymandering or Geography Debate Nicholas Goedert Lafayette College goedertn@lafayette.edu November, 2015 ABSTRACT: This note observes that the

More information

Third Party Voting: Vote One s Heart or One s Mind?

Third Party Voting: Vote One s Heart or One s Mind? Third Party Voting: Vote One s Heart or One s Mind? Emekcan Yucel Job Market Paper This Version: October 30, 2016 Latest Version: Click Here Abstract In this paper, I propose non-instrumental benefits

More information

In Elections, Irrelevant Alternatives Provide Relevant Data

In Elections, Irrelevant Alternatives Provide Relevant Data 1 In Elections, Irrelevant Alternatives Provide Relevant Data Richard B. Darlington Cornell University Abstract The electoral criterion of independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) states that a voting

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PROTECTING MINORITIES IN BINARY ELECTIONS: A TEST OF STORABLE VOTES USING FIELD DATA

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PROTECTING MINORITIES IN BINARY ELECTIONS: A TEST OF STORABLE VOTES USING FIELD DATA NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PROTECTING MINORITIES IN BINARY ELECTIONS: A TEST OF STORABLE VOTES USING FIELD DATA Alessandra Casella Shuky Ehrenberg Andrew Gelman Jie Shen Working Paper 1413 http://www.nber.org/papers/w1413

More information

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness

ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness CeNTRe for APPlieD MACRo - AND PeTRoleuM economics (CAMP) CAMP Working Paper Series No 2/2013 ONLINE APPENDIX: Why Do Voters Dismantle Checks and Balances? Extensions and Robustness Daron Acemoglu, James

More information

Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders

Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders Introduction to the declination function for gerrymanders Gregory S. Warrington Department of Mathematics & Statistics, University of Vermont, 16 Colchester Ave., Burlington, VT 05401, USA November 4,

More information

Campaign Contributions as Valence

Campaign Contributions as Valence Campaign Contributions as Valence Tim Lambie-Hanson Suffolk University June 11, 2011 Tim Lambie-Hanson (Suffolk University) Campaign Contributions as Valence June 11, 2011 1 / 16 Motivation Under what

More information

Patterns of Poll Movement *

Patterns of Poll Movement * Patterns of Poll Movement * Public Perspective, forthcoming Christopher Wlezien is Reader in Comparative Government and Fellow of Nuffield College, University of Oxford Robert S. Erikson is a Professor

More information

What is The Probability Your Vote will Make a Difference?

What is The Probability Your Vote will Make a Difference? Berkeley Law From the SelectedWorks of Aaron Edlin 2009 What is The Probability Your Vote will Make a Difference? Andrew Gelman, Columbia University Nate Silver Aaron S. Edlin, University of California,

More information

Problems with Group Decision Making

Problems with Group Decision Making Problems with Group Decision Making There are two ways of evaluating political systems. 1. Consequentialist ethics evaluate actions, policies, or institutions in regard to the outcomes they produce. 2.

More information

A positive correlation between turnout and plurality does not refute the rational voter model

A positive correlation between turnout and plurality does not refute the rational voter model Quality & Quantity 26: 85-93, 1992. 85 O 1992 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Note A positive correlation between turnout and plurality does not refute the rational voter model

More information

The Macro Polity Updated

The Macro Polity Updated The Macro Polity Updated Robert S Erikson Columbia University rse14@columbiaedu Michael B MacKuen University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill Mackuen@emailuncedu James A Stimson University of North Carolina,

More information

EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS

EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS EFFICIENCY OF COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE : A GAME THEORETIC ANALYSIS TAI-YEONG CHUNG * The widespread shift from contributory negligence to comparative negligence in the twentieth century has spurred scholars

More information

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks

Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks Sequential Voting with Externalities: Herding in Social Networks Noga Alon Moshe Babaioff Ron Karidi Ron Lavi Moshe Tennenholtz February 7, 01 Abstract We study sequential voting with two alternatives,

More information

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees

Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees Social Rankings in Human-Computer Committees Moshe Bitan 1, Ya akov (Kobi) Gal 3 and Elad Dokow 4, and Sarit Kraus 1,2 1 Computer Science Department, Bar Ilan University, Israel 2 Institute for Advanced

More information

DOES GERRYMANDERING VIOLATE THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT?: INSIGHT FROM THE MEDIAN VOTER THEOREM

DOES GERRYMANDERING VIOLATE THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT?: INSIGHT FROM THE MEDIAN VOTER THEOREM DOES GERRYMANDERING VIOLATE THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT?: INSIGHT FROM THE MEDIAN VOTER THEOREM Craig B. McLaren University of California, Riverside Abstract This paper argues that gerrymandering understood

More information

Election Theory. How voters and parties behave strategically in democratic systems. Mark Crowley

Election Theory. How voters and parties behave strategically in democratic systems. Mark Crowley How voters and parties behave strategically in democratic systems Department of Computer Science University of British Columbia January 30, 2006 Sources Voting Theory Jeff Gill and Jason Gainous. "Why

More information