Draft: Please do not cite or circulate without permission. Criticisms and comments most welcome! Abstract

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Draft: Please do not cite or circulate without permission. Criticisms and comments most welcome! Abstract"

Transcription

1 Political representation in semi-direct democracy: The impact of the facultative referendum Alice el-wakil, PhD Candidate, University of Zurich / Centre for Democracy Studies Aarau International Political Science Association World Congress Poznan, July 23-28, 2016 Panel RC34.04, Democracy: Representation, Participation, Contestation Draft: Please do not cite or circulate without permission. Criticisms and comments most welcome! Abstract Most normative and empirical defenses of direct democratic procedures emphasize the way in which they supplement the representative institutions. They are framed as some sort of add-ons to representative institutions, which are themselves taken as an unchanged, and unchangeable background. This approach might have caused research to overlook the potential changes that direct institutions bring to representative ones; as Simon Hug notes, little research has addressed the issue of how referendums affect the representative governments that prevail in all democratic states around the world (Hug 2008, 252). In this paper, I propose to contribute to filling this gap by looking at what the presence of direct democratic institutions in a representative system changes, at the theoretical level, in the latter rather than at what it brings to it. I do this by clarifying the impact of one specific bottom-up direct institution, the facultative referendum, on the conception of representation and of the role of representatives. I first present the additional authorization and accountability mechanisms this institution introduces, and how it enables the emergence of democratic unelected representatives. I then argue that its presence makes it impossible for representatives to act as trustees. This doesn t mean that trust is eliminated from the semi-direct political system altogether: The presence of the facultative referendum rather seems to be able to promote a view of selective trust in representative institution on an issue-by-issue basis, which encourages citizens to actively engage in judging their representatives work. Keywords: Contestation, popular vote, selective trust, unelected representation 1. Introduction While contemporary theorists of democracy have mostly favored representative political systems over more direct ones to implement their various democratic ideals, some researchers have recommended the introduction of certain bottom-up direct democratic procedures within representative systems in order to enhance the quality of existing democracies (see e.g., Setälä 2006; Steenbergen 2009; Parkinson 2009). Direct democratic procedures could be considered to play a valuable role in terms of encouraging public deliberation on specific issues (Setälä 2006, 703), of countering the alienation emanating from more conventional electoral processes that citizens might experience (Gastil, Richards, and Knobloch 2014, 80), of bringing the preferences of the representatives closer to the ones of the citizens (Leemann and Wasserfallen tbp; Sager and Bühlmann 2009, 201), of raising the level of trust in authorities (Bauer and Fatke 2014), or of increasing the legitimacy of adopted policies (Hug 2008, 256;

2 Chambers 1998) once we take on board the need for electoral chambers of representatives, and an array of administrative and enabling bodies for it to oversee (Saward 2001, 371; see also Qvortrup 2015, 44). These defenses of direct democratic procedures emphasize the way in which they supplement the representative institutions. They are framed as some sort of add-ons to representative institutions, which are themselves taken as an unchanged, and unchangeable background (Setälä and Schiller 2009, 6). 1 This approach might have caused research to overlook the potential changes that direct institutions bring to representative ones; as Simon Hug notes, little research has addressed the issue of how referendums affect the representative governments that prevail in all democratic states around the world (Hug 2008, 252). 2 In this paper, I want to contribute to filling this gap by changing outlook, namely by looking at what the introduction of direct democratic institutions in a representative system changes, at the theoretical level, in the latter rather than at what it brings to it. More precisely, I aim at clarifying the impact of one specific bottom-up direct institution, the facultative referendum, on the conception of representation and of the role of representatives. Clarifying these changes in the representative, background institutions and evaluating them is an essential step towards offering a convincing defense of semi-direct (or mixed) systems. As such, it could inform the fundamental choice [ ] between a pure representative system and a similar system combined with referendums (Hug 2008, 252; see also Cheneval 2015, 169) as well as open up the possibility for new reflections about representation. Before starting with the argument, let me clarify what is the facultative referendum, and why I focus on this specific institution. The facultative referendum is a bottom-up direct democratic institution, which is implemented in Switzerland at the national level, that enables citizens to contest almost any law adopted by their representatives. In its first, referendum launching phase, they have to gather the required number of signatures in the specified amount of time. In a second step, a popular vote is organized and the majority of citizens decides, in a binding way, on the adoption or the rejection of that law. Focusing on this direct democratic mechanism only benefits the present paper in three ways. First, the facultative referendum institution corresponds to the kind of add-ons recommended by most proponents 1 The question guiding their research is often in what way can referendums supplement or undermine representative democracy? a question to which many answer that the direct democratic institutions could play the role of democratic correctives (Leemann and Wasserfallen tbp; see also Sager and Bühlmann 2009, 201) to be used as supplements to the existing institutions of representative democracy (Setälä 2006, ). 2 In his view, proponents of referendums fail to address convincingly the interactions referendums create between the representative system and the elements of direct citizen participation (Hug 2008, 252). 2

3 of direct democratic institutions. 3 Second, limiting my argument to one specific direct democratic institution prevents me from the risk of blurring the relevant differences between different direct democratic political institutions, 4 and represents a way to gain in argumentative precision and clarity. 5 Third, this analysis can open the way to a more general claim about the impact of other direct democratic mechanisms on representative institutions. If even the facultative referendum, an institution that presupposes a representative institutional context, modifies the conception of representation in relevant ways, other more controversial direct democratic institutions (such as the popular initiative) might also have an impact on these background institutions that would deserve to be made explicit and evaluated. The paper is divided into three parts. In the first one, I propose a translation of the facultative referendum procedure in the terms used by theories of representation. I offer a table that highlights the different mechanisms of authorization and accountability, but also the different kinds of democratic representatives present in a representative democracy with facultative referendum procedures. In the second part, I argue that the presence of this institution makes it impossible for representatives to act as trustees. However, I try to show in the third part that, instead of transforming representatives in mere delegates, the facultative referendum seems to contain a notion of trust that corresponds to a more recent view of trust in representatives a view that answers the radical worry of disengagement of the citizens in the process of politics, which undermines the accountability of democratic representatives (Cohen and Fung 2004; Barber 1984). By providing an institutional tool for citizens to actually check the decisions made by representatives, and giving them an incentive to continuously judge their actions and make the decision to trust their representatives or not (Warren and Gastil 2015, 564), the facultative referendum right encourages elected representatives to be prepared to justify their decisions to a wide audience and to act in an responsive and anticipatory way. I conclude by summarizing what this reversed approach tells us about the impact of the facultative referendum on the representative institutions and by highlighting the valuable character of the semi-direct political system created. 3 Maija Setälä, who calls this process rejective referendum (Setälä and Schiller 2009, 5) or decisioncontrolling referendum (Setälä 2006, 714), for instance strongly supports it (Setälä and Schiller 2009, ). 4 For instance, while John Gastil and Robert Richards claim to highlight the weaknesses of direct democratic mechanisms, i.e. referenda and initiatives, two of their main criticisms to it are actually only directed to the popular initiative (Gastil and Richards 2013, 255); in the same way, their proposal for introducing random assemblies in the direct democratic process appears to only focus on initiative procedures (Gastil and Richards 2013, 266). 5 Even more so after the recent and almost unanimously criticised BREXIT referendum in Great Britain, which differs from the facultative referendum procedure in important and normatively relevant ways. 3

4 1. The facultative referendum in representative terms Direct democratic institutions are rarely accounted for in the same terminology as representative ones. However, this vocabulary appears to be to a certain extent appropriate to highlight unexplored aspects of the facultative referendum is about, and better understand how it impacts the elected representatives. In all representative democracies, including the ones with provisions for direct mechanisms, representatives are selected by the citizens in order to make binding political decisions for the society on the entire bundle of issues upon which they can legislate (Besley and Coate 2008). The democratic theory literature mentions two conditions for representatives to be democratic ones (Pitkin 1967; Urbinati and Warren 2008, 396). On the one hand, they must be authorized by the citizens to take action in a certain domain. This authorization moment is a process of gaining power for representatives-to-be. On the other hand, citizens must have ways to hold them accountable for their actions in this domain. This second feature is said to guarantee some level of responsiveness on the part of the representative (Urbinati and Warren 2008, 402). Fair elections are the main institution recommended to fulfill these two criteria of democratic representation. 6 It is through elections that citizens, by casting their votes, select representatives and authorize them to make decisions for their constituency for a determined period of time. And it is through elections that they can hold representatives accountable for their actions during their entire term and, eventually, sanction them by not re-electing them (Hug 2008, 260). In this sense, regular elections are the main check to avoid gross abuses of power (Urbinati and Warren 2008, 402). The introduction of the facultative referendum in a representative democracy adds an authorization and an accountability mechanism, which can be used during the electoral term. By collecting the required number of signature within the allocated time, a dissatisfied minority 7 can temporarily de-authorize the representatives to make decisions for the constituency on the specific law subjected to the referendum. When a facultative referendum is launched, representatives loose their competence to represent the constituency on that issue. This withdrawal of authorization lasts until the popular vote takes place; right after it, and 6 That is, fair elections in a democratic context. As Nadia Urbinati insists, elections take place in a context with robust local autonomy and freedom of speech and association as well as some basic equality of material conditions to enable democratic representation (Urbinati 2006, 39). 7 In Switzerland, 50'000 signatures must be collected within 100 days to launch a referendum. 4

5 independently of whether the majority of citizens has supported or rejected the law, the representatives are automatically authorized to make decisions on this issue again. The popular vote thus constitutes the additional accountability mechanism introduced by the facultative referendum. At this stage, citizens choose to support either the representatives by accepting the law proposal, or the referendum committee, by favoring the status quo. In the latter case, the majority of citizens sanction the representatives in a soft way, as Alexandre Trechsel argues, since the accountor keeps the quality of accountor, i.e. remains in office (or keeps the right to vote) but their politics are potentially affected by the sanction and they might change a political decision or express a different political opinion (Trechsel 2010, 1059). These authorization and accountability mechanisms only concern a single issue, one among the many law projects adopted by representatives. Representatives are de-authorized and held accountable only for this specific issue; they keep their competence to make democratic decisions about all the other ones. In this sense, the facultative referendum makes it possible to unbundle the issues upon which representatives can take action (Besley and Coate 2008, 2). 8 While the election only makes it possible to punish representatives for their overall action on all issues during an entire term, the facultative referendum enables citizens to hold their representative accountable on single issues (Trechsel 2010, 1055). 9 The facultative referendum introduces an additional specificity: It enables the emergence of representatives outside electoral cycles (Saward 2009, 4). The launchers of a specific facultative referendum procedure actually become some sort of unelected representatives. According to institutional definitions of representation, the referendum launchers are representatives in the sense that they are able to influence the political decision-making procedure directly and for the entire society by asking that the last word on a specific law be given to the citizens instead of the representatives. The facultative referendum procedure also provides them with visibility to argue and campaign for this law s rejection before the popular vote. According to broader definitions of representation, such as the one Michael Saward offers, the referendum launchers are representatives to the extent that they make claims to be representatives (Saward 2006, 298). By launching a referendum, simple citizens appear to make two kinds of claims: A general one, about minorities or majorities whose interests are not served by the contested law, and a more specific one, deriving from the signature 8 Timothy Besley and Stephen Coate direct this claim to the popular initiative process. 9 Soft as opposed to hard sanctioning mechanisms, auch as elections or recall procedures, where the accountor (the rulers) may be chased from office (Trechsel 2010, 1059). 5

6 gathering as Saward puts it, I represent these people because they have explicitly supported my view on this issue (Saward 2009, 12). They are thus, in this definition, representatives. In Saward s view, non-elected representation can be beneficial to representative systems (Saward 2009, 9). Contrary to elected representatives, non-elected ones can, among other things, be explicitly partial, are not influenced by electoral cycles, and must put more effort to make their representative claims convincing and create an audience (Saward 2009, 8). Their presence can correct failures of representation by elected representatives, uncover ignored interests, or make new constituencies emerge. Unelected forms of representation serve as a reminder that democracy is not just about deliberation within established forums and provide a solution to avoid that those forums [ ] become sclerotic if they are not subject to pressure and renewal through outsider activism and dissent (Saward 2009, 20). Yet unelected representatives act, precisely, without the citizens control provided by elections. They are neither authorized nor accountable, which raises the question of the democratic legitimacy of their claims and actions. For Saward, the lack of institutional mechanisms can be compensated. He proposes three alternative ways to test the legitimacy of non-elected representatives claims of representation. The first way is to make sure that the claim-makers are in a structure of accountability that can potentially constrain them in ways similar to elections. For Saward, the fact that they operate in a democratic system and context already limits their claims. The second way is to wait for constituencies to emerge and to approve of the claims made by the non-elected representative a solution that requires time and deliberation. And the third way is to make sure that the claim-makers have absolutely no link with elected institution in a way that guarantees their untaintedness and the disinterested character of their claims (Saward 2009, 15 17). In sum, we shouldn t be too focused on the two traditional criteria of democratic representation, authorization and accountability, to identify democratic representatives. According to Saward, we should rather concentrate on the authenticity of the claims made; this criterion would better preserve the positive, complementing and corrective role of nonelectoral representation in democracies (Saward 2009, 21). However, Saward admits that these alternative legitimacy tests are less strong than elections, whose strength comes from the underlying values of authorization it implements (Saward 2009, 21). Moreover, considering his insistence on the fact that representative claims should be accepted by an audience (Saward 2006, 302), Saward s proposals seem to be also weak in terms of accountability: If, as he argues, representative claims participate in the construction of identity of certain constituencies and impacts the way they can act politically 6

7 (Saward 2006, 313), it seems that some institutionalized or facilitated possibility to contest some claims and punish some claim-makers would be justified. But Saward seems to have given up on the possibility to authorize and hold unelected representatives accountable and he might be right to do so for a number of claim-making actors in democratic societies. Yet the unelected representatives emerging through the facultative referendum procedure can still be formally authorized and held accountable and hence, I argue, be considered to be democratic representatives. 10 Fellow-citizens actually authorize the referendum launchers to become representatives and thus to influence policy-making on a specific issue by signing their petition. And the entirety of the citizenry can later hold them accountable by voting to support or to punish them at the stage of the popular vote. These two mechanisms are only valid for representation and action about the contested law, and for a limited period of time, namely until the popular vote has taken place. Table 1. Kinds of authorization and accountability mechanisms in a semi-direct system with facultative referendum (FR) Authorization Accountability Scope Time-frame Representative institutions (Candidates VS. Candidates) FR (Elected representatives VS. FR launchers) Regular and fair elections Gathering of signatures (Deauthorization of the representatives) (Strong); Regular and fair elections (Soft); Popular vote (Sanctioning either the representatives or the FR launchers) Competence on a bundle of issues Competence on a specific, unbundled issue Entire electoral term From the moment the FR is accepted until the popular vote Table 1 highlights the different mechanisms present in a representative democracy with a facultative referendum institution. While the representative institution only need the election to be considered democratic, i.e. to guarantee authorization and accountability, the facultative referendum adds two different mechanisms, i.e. the gathering of signatures and the popular vote, which can be used at any time during the electoral term. These two mechanisms have a simultaneous impact on the representatives and the facultative referendum launchers: The signature collection un-authorizes the elected representatives and authorizes the referendum launchers; and the popular vote sanctions either the former or the latter. 10 I would like here to thank Jean Terrier for pushing me on this point. 7

8 Compared to a pure representative political system, the one including facultative referendum procedures thus adds (1) two new mechanisms of authorization and accountability, (2) the possibility to unbundle the issues upon which representatives can act, and (3) the opportunity for unelected democratic representatives to influence policy-making. 2. No Trustees no More The additional authorization and accountability mechanisms provided by the presence of the facultative referendum have been shown to have an impact on the behavior of elected representatives. A number of empirical research on the Swiss semi-direct democracy have suggested that, because representatives want to avoid the veto of the facultative referendum, it gives them incentives to for instance include the opposition in the governing coalitions, adopt a strategy of co-operation, find compromises 11 that are acceptable to all representatives (Papadopoulos 2001, 39), or negotiate ex ante with parts of the civil society. The point I would like to make here is that the facultative referendum also impacts the way we conceive of the role of representatives in a system with facultative referendum compared to a pure representative system. As mentioned, in representative political systems, elected officials should represent their constituency during their entire term. Since Hanna Pitkin s foundational book on representation (Pitkin 1967), theorists of representation have debated about what representing exactly mean. In order to stay focused on the claim I want to make here, I take as granted the widely shared view that what democratic representatives should represent are the interests of their constituency, thus acting as substantive representatives. Their actions as representatives are thus considered valuable if they serve the interests of the (plurality of) represented (Dovi 2014). Democracy theorists have developed different conceptual models of democratic representation that representatives can adopt to act in a legitimate way. The most traditional model, which Mansbridge names promissory representation, focuses on the need for voters to keep legal or moral control over their distant representatives (Mansbridge 2003, 516). Its basic logic is the following: During the electoral campaign, candidates make promises to the voters. Once elected, they have to realize these promises during their term. If they fail to do so, the citizens can sanction them at the next election by not reelecting them. On the opposite, if they succeed, the voters can support them further by reelecting them. 11 Often referred to as consensus in the Swiss empirical literature (see e.g., Sciarini and Trechsel 1996, 30), although the term compromise seems more appropriate considering the large minorities in parliamentary votes. 8

9 Mansbridge distinguishes between different kinds of promises that candidates can make. The nature of the promise made places the representatives on the mandate-independence continuum presented at large by Pitkin (Pitkin 1967, ). If they promise to follow the constituents instructions or expressed desires (Mansbridge 2003, 516), they commit to acting as mandate, or delegate representatives. The most extreme version of the mandate conception demands that the representative acts on explicit instructions from his constituents without any exercise of discretion (Pitkin 1967, 146). A less extreme view allows the representative to act as he thinks his constituents would want, unless or until he receives instructions from them, and then he must obey (Pitkin 1967, 146). This view assumes that the represented have a rather good idea of what is good for them, and that they should be the ones deciding at least in cases of conflict between the representatives and their constituency. Other candidates can promise to further the constituency s long-run interests and the interests of the nation as a whole (Mansbridge 2003, 516). These are the kind of promises made by trustee representatives. Situated on the other side of the mandate-independence continuum, the extreme trustee must be completely free to use his own judgment without any interference from the citizens (Pitkin 1967, 146). In this view, representatives are considered to know what is in the interest of their constituency and of the national interests (Pitkin 1967, 147) better than the citizens: A good trustee is a wise judge of his or her constituents needs and how to meet them (Plotke 1997, 34, note 15). They thus can legitimately make decisions that conflict with the preferences of the citizens. Acting contrary to [the constituents ] wishes is not necessarily wrong, not necessarily bad representation or a violation of a representative s duty (Pitkin 1967, 164) in this view. The only duty for representatives in such cases is, according to Pitkin, to explain and justify their decision to go against the citizens preferences in a satisfactory way (i.e. not for private interest reasons) (Pitkin 1967, 164). All the promissory models that are found between the two extreme positions of this mandate-independence continuum are considered as defensible models of representation. Theorists then tend to favor some over others once they include additional considerations (Pitkin 1967, ). As such, deliberative democracy theorists tend to favor a model close to that of the trustee: The category of trust has proved more fruitful than that of delegate, reconfigured so it is clear that, as a trustee, the representative is obligated to keep his or her constituents in view (Urbinati and Warren 2008, 401; see also Arneson 2003, 216). One of the main deliberative democracy arguments for representative systems is indeed that representatives are more competent than citizens in making binding decisions for the 9

10 society. Some argue in this direction for rather elitist reasons: Representatives would be more competent independently of whether citizens have had an opportunity to deliberate in an appropriate, deliberative setting or not. Mansbridge expresses such a view when she argues that if citizens assemblies did binding decisions, it would probably generate costs in the legislators having less ability, expertise, and possibly even commitment to the common good than legislators chosen through election (Mansbridge 2015, 267). But most deliberative theorists argue that representatives know better precisely because of the deliberative setting in which they operate, which enables them to take various perspectives into account, to gain knowledge and information on a specific issue, and to develop considered, reasonable opinions on which to ground new legislation (Manin 1987; Cohen 1997; see also e.g., Warren and Gastil 2015, 568). Good deliberation is in their view necessary for binding decisions to have political legitimacy; yet it can only happen at the small-scale, with a limited number of participants as is the case in parliament. For deliberative democracy theorists, there are thus good reasons for citizens to trust their representatives, and to a priori accept that they do what is best for them (Pitkin 1967, 163). After all, if citizens could deliberate in the same conditions, they would arrive to similar conclusions. They can thus assume that they can approve what the representative has done (Pitkin 1967, 163; see also Hug 2008, 257), even if they themselves have neither access to all the information on an issue, nor taken part in the deliberation process. The facultative referendum institution makes the opposite assumption with regard to trust in representatives. It rejects the trustee view s fundamental assumption according to which the representatives know better : The institutionalization of a way for citizens to contest decisions made by the representatives can actually only be explained if we assume that the latter can sometimes be wrong namely, make choices that citizens judge contrary to their interests. In such cases of disagreement, it is not enough that representatives give acceptable reasons for their decision, as in the trustee model. As mentioned above, when there is a conflict about a specific law between the representatives and a minority of the population, having managed to launch a referendum, the representatives lose their authorization to make decisions about this law. Their mistake on a specific issue constitutes a good-enough reason to enable the represented to reclaim, and obtain the power to have the last word over a policy (Trechsel 2010, 1056) in order to correct the situation (Bauer and Fatke 2014, 53). This doesn t mean that unpopular policies can never be adopted; but for them to have a chance, the representatives must be able to give good reasons why they propose to undertake such a 10

11 seemingly unpopular policy (Frey and Stutzer 2013, 508) that the citizens actually accept. If they fail to convince the majority of citizens, the representatives have to see their decision rejected and they law project called an error (Sager and Bühlmann 2009, 201). In this sense, the facultative referendum changes the conception of the role of representatives by making it impossible (and undesirable) for the latter to act as trustees. The citizens are the ones who know better what their interests are: Each person is the only reliable measure of his own interest; no one else can know what it is as well as he does (Pitkin 1967, 159). The facultative referendum does not exclude that representatives might also know what the interests of the represented are. But in case they would misunderstand them, citizens must be able to signal and correct this error to control the trustee, as Paul Bauer and Matthias Fatke innocently put it (Bauer and Fatke 2014, 53) at any time. Only in this way can we avoid implementing decisions of the representatives that are not supported by the majority of the citizens, a situation deemed undesirable in the logic of the facultative referendum. This discussion thus highlights a fourth difference in the representative institutions between a pure representative system and a semi-direct one including the facultative referendum: Contrary to a system where only an elected political elite has both deliberative and decision-making power, unlike the citizens, whose formal freedom to discuss and criticize proposals and policies does not ensure that their opinions will affect legislation and policy making (Urbinati and Warren 2008, 407), the presence of the facultative referendum limits the possibility for representatives to act as trustees and enables citizens to get the last word on a specific, controversial issue. This limitation (which has, to my knowledge, never been theorized in this way) seems to induce certain questionable behaviors among representatives that have been highlighted by empirical findings about the Swiss semi-direct democracy. The presence of bottom-up direct institutions has for instance been shown to have the effect of demobilizing the representatives (Jaggi 2016 (my translation from French)). Hug argues that increasing the possibilities of sanctioning the agents reduces obviously the latter s incentives to get informed and specialized, because the efforts put into designing a law project could be annihilated by a facultative referendum (Hug 2008, 261, 260). 12 Moreover, a frequent use of facultative 12 Another explanation that I haven t so far found in the literature could be that representatives don t feel the need to specialize so much because they rely on the facultative referendum check; if this was the case, could it indicate a sense of shared responsibility of the representatives with the citizens, the latter being responsible for checking, and indeed correcting the potentially bad laws adopted by representatives? Such a view could indeed correspond to the empirical findings from Switzerland according to which the facultative referendum, despite its 11

12 referendum procedures would encourage representatives to act in a less trustworthy way (Bauer and Fatke 2014, 54). These findings seem to offer support to Philip Pettit s claim that the trust of citizens in their authorities which puts them in a vulnerable situation, as any act of trust gives an incentive to those in power to do their best (here in terms of gaining knowledge or of acting in a reliable way): In a very act whereby the trustor is put at risk, the trustee is given a motive not to let that risk materialize (Pettit 1999, 269). It also raises normative questionings: Does the facultative referendum, by excluding the possibility for representatives to act as trustees and by letting citizens reclaiming the last word on policies, impose a conception of representatives as mandates? As mentioned, in this view, the representative was sent to pursue his constituents will and not his own and loses his independence (Pitkin 1967, 146). Adrian Vatter and Deniz Danaci claim that this view indeed dominates when they write that the Swiss concept of sovereignty is that of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (Vatter and Danaci 2010, 217), namely an ideal of general will that cannot be represented (Urbinati 2006, 60), because in their view, the facultative referendum on laws demands that every law receives the confirmation of the people (Vatter and Danaci 2010, 217 (my translation from German)). This confirmation can be explicit when a facultative referendum is organized. Or it can be implicit, if we assume that laws that are not contested through a facultative referendum procedure are de facto supported by the citizens. However, the extreme mandate representative is a very objectionable conception of the representative: Representation as a contract (delegation) is in itself a denial of political representation (Urbinati 2006, 57). This model actually leaves no autonomy to representatives (Pitkin 1967, 152); insisting that the representative cannot be persistently at odds with the desires of his constituency, it goes too far in removing all his discretion to act (Pitkin 1967, 153). Representatives indeed need to have some level of independence, be it only to act upon issues on which the represented has no will (Pitkin 1967, 163). Does the facultative referendum institution thus contains this undesirable view of representation? 3. Or another kind of judged trustee? fundamental assumption that representatives can t be trusted, actually increases trust in them. In Bauer and Fatke s view, this is due to the possibility to keep their agents on a much shorter leash than in pure representative systems (Bauer and Fatke 2014, 52 53). In this sense, it could indicate that Swiss citizens consider themselves as responsible to be the watchdogs of representatives? And that the lower engagement of representatives could be compensated for by a higher engagement of the citizens? Bruno Frey and Alois Stutzer seem to suggest something similar when they write that direct democratic institutions provide incentives to voters to inform themselves about political issues, and changes their relationship to authorities and fellow citizens (Frey and Stutzer 2013, (emphasis added)). 12

13 In this still in development part, I suggest that the conception of representatives promoted by the facultative referendum does not correspond to that of the extreme mandate. Rather, it could contain a view of representation that implements a kind of trust in the political system that requires judgment on the part of citizens, and that thus answers the objection of radical democrats according to which representative governments pushes citizens to disengage from politics (Cohen and Fung 2004, 171). Several democracy theorists have recently called for enlarging our focus beyond electoral processes to think about political representation, and emphasized the need for citizens to remain active even after the election (Saward 2006; Urbinati 2006; Warren and Gastil 2015). Deliberative and participatory critiques to pure representative systems have highlighted that these systems can only be considered democratic if the citizens stay active. Joshua Cohen and Archon Fung present three of these objections to pure representative systems. First, focusing on the election moment alone would encourage citizens to excessively rely on their representatives and to renounce to act in a responsible way. Capacities of citizens may in turn atrophy, on the one hand, and on the other hand they may refrain from judging public business except under dire circumstances and then judge poorly (Cohen and Fung 2004, 171). Second, representative systems legitimized by the universal suffrage might violate equality, because it conceives of it without taking social inequalities into account. Yet deliberative and participatory democrats consider that these inequalities have an impact on the use of political power, and that they should be fought back by expanding and deepening citizen participation so that the concentration of power can be challenged (Cohen and Fung 2004, 171). Third, pure representative democracies pull the political power away from citizens. Instead of reflecting the ideal of self-government, at its best, the process reflects fair bargaining among competitive interests (Cohen and Fung 2004, 172). In Cohen and Fung s view, it should rather ensure that political arguments and appeals to interests are framed by considerations such as fairness, equality, and common advantage so that every citizen whose views do not win out can see that the decisions are supported by good reasons (Cohen and Fung 2004, 172). These objections dismiss the traditional trustee view of representation, detrimental to democracy for it conceptualizes the citizens as inactive between the elections: Once they have selected their representatives, they can rely on them to make the decisions for them, and only have to judge at the next election whether they support the decisions taken during the term. The extreme, Burkean model of trustee depends on deferential citizens who suspend judgment so that representatives might exercise their own (Warren and Gastil 2015, 564). 13

14 Although less extreme, the deliberative model of trustee mentioned in the second subsection of this paper also limits the incentives for citizens to judge the work of representatives. Because it insists that only those who took part in the deliberative process, namely the representatives, have all the information necessary to make a considered and legitimate decision, it appears to exclude the possibility for citizens who didn t take part in the deliberation to judge their representatives action. The deliberative and participatory critiques however make clear that these notions of trust should be rejected, and that the citizenry must be continuously active for elections to guarantee that representatives will act in a responsive way (Pitkin 1967, 153). Recent literature on representation has thus shifted the focus from electoral mechanisms to ongoing interactions between representatives and represented during electoral terms. As Nadia Urbinati puts it, it is desirable that the relationship between representatives and represented does not end at the moment of electoral authorization (Urbinati 2006, 58). Empowered citizens in a democracy should make ongoing judgments as voters, petitioners, advocates, deliberators, and jurors, and political institutions should be responsive to citizens judgments (Warren and Gastil 2015, 563). This is not to say that citizens should be continuously watching their representatives. On the one hand, this task would be impossible: even the most attentive citizen cannot knowledgably engage with most of the collective decisions that affect them (Warren and Gastil 2015, 562). And on the other hand, generalized distrust would undermine the citizens capacities for democratic self-government because it causes them to often withdraw from participation altogether (Warren and Gastil 2015, 563, 566). For Mark Warren and John Gastil, a certain level of trust is needed to enable citizens to play their role, namely to focus their activity on participation in specific areas or on overseeing the institutions or representatives they don t trust. Democracy thus still requires some sort of trust in (parts of) the elected and the institutions. Yet Warren and Gastil insist that this trust cannot have the desirable effect if it is a priori given to any institution or any representative. 13 Trust should, in their view, be the result of a 13 Their view here differs from that of Philipp Pettit, who, despite his insistence on citizens vigilance, promotes a view of impersonal trust according to which institutions make it possible to have an assumption of trust towards all members of the society: When we rely confidently on someone to behave in a certain way because they are independent sanctions available that support that form of behavior, then we trust that person in an impersonal fashion (Pettit 1999, 261). In Pettit s view, vigilance (a necessary aspect of the republic and a necessity for freedom as non-domination) does not contradict an attitude of confidant reliance on the powerful (Pettit 1999, 263). Individuals can at the same time trust the authorities and keep an attitude of distrust by insisting on keeping the checks and restrictions that limit their power (Pettit 1999, 264). 14

15 judgment: A decision to trust is a judgment (not a suspended judgment) (Warren and Gastil 2015, 562). With regards to their representatives, citizens should thus develop a form of selective trust enabling them to decide which representatives they should spend time and energy watching and which ones they can rely on without the extra effort (Warren and Gastil 2015, 565). These judgments are not made once and for all for the entire length of an electoral term: The context of conflicting interests continuously tests the bond between truster and trustee (Warren and Gastil 2015, 566). To offer the necessary checks, citizens trust should be well-founded (Warren and Gastil 2015, 564). For Warren and Gastil, this implies that political institutions should help citizens to make better trust judgments by creating facilitative trustee institutions (Warren and Gastil 2015, 567). Facilitative trustees facilitate, enable, and support citizens capacity for political judgment by lowing their cognitive costs (Warren and Gastil 2015, 566). Warren and Gastil suggest spreading the use of deliberative mini publics such as the British Columbia Citizens Assembly or the Oregon Citizens Initiative Review, which would serve as trusted information proxies (Warren and Gastil 2015, 568). Let s come back to the facultative referendum institution, and to explaining for now in a very sketchy way why, despite its capacity to give virtual control over every decision made by representatives, it actually seems to promote a form of selective trust in them and in the entire political system. 1. As shown in the first part of this paper, the facultative referendum provides additional means to promote interactions between the representatives and the represented during electoral terms. Its presence promotes a view of active citizens whose possibilities of influence are not limited to voting representatives in. On the opposite, citizens have an important, controlling role to play to limit the power of representatives who, as shown in the second part of this paper, may happen to make mistakes and fail to represent the interests of all the represented. This gives them an incentive to keep some minimal level of information about the work of the authorities, especially when they come to legislate on issues upon which these citizens have high stakes Citizens thus develop a form of selective trust similar to the concept offered by Warren and Gastil. However, instead of judging which representative they can 14 However, it goes further than what authors like Urbinati, Fung and Cohen, or Warren and Gastil argue for by enabling citizens to also make binding decisions upon laws (see e.g., Urbinati 2006, 58; Cohen and Fung 2004, 172). This point needs some further considerations. 15

16 trust or not, they judge what issue they have to oversee or not. They don t have to engage with every decision of the parliament, but only with those that affect them. In other words, they can decide to trust the parliament for all the topics in which they have no or low stakes as long as the facultative referendum is not triggered. 3. Yet if representatives happen to adopt a law that goes against the interests of a part of the constituency, the latter can launch a referendum. In this case, the entire citizenry has to make a trust judgment about this specific issue. The fact that a part of the citizens claim to have their interests hurt by a law demands that all the citizens judge the issue for themselves and decide whether to support the elected representatives or the facultative referendum launchers. 4. In this way, the facultative referendum launchers appear to play the role of facilitative trustee. As long as there is no contestation through a facultative referendum, citizens can trust their representative institutions. But when the nonelected representatives launching the referendum highlight the fact that representatives might fail to represent them properly on a specific issue, they indicate to the entire citizenry that they should remove their trust in the representatives on that issue and engage with this topic. They facilitate the trust judgments of citizens by informing them that the quality of representation is questionable, thus functioning as information proxies (Warren and Gastil 2015, 658). Just as members of mini-publics, they can be trusted because they can be assumed to have impartial, in the sense of disinterested, motivations and of being (minimally) competent, because they are sufficiently interested in politics to launch a facultative referendum (Warren and Gastil 2015, 568) (but also, maybe, because it is their interests that are at stake). Moreover, their use of the facultative referendum increases the accessibility to information about the law contested, as both the launcher and the representative campaign before the popular vote in an attempt to justify their position to the entire constituency (Setälä 2006). For these reasons, which still need to be reflected upon, I posit that the semi-direct political system with facultative referendum rights promotes selective trust and an engaged citizenry. Before I close this paper with some remaining challenges and questions, I want to come back to the implications of the facultative referendum for the role of representatives. I actually mentioned earlier the empirical findings according to which representatives in the Swiss semidirect system don t specialize as much as representatives in pure representative systems. Yet I 16

17 would like to suggest that, if they don t get the same level of knowledge about the issues at stake, they might get more of another kind of knowledge about citizens expectations and interests. In a system with the facultative referendum, elected representatives actually have a strong incentive to get to know what are the opinions shared among the citizenry. Just as elected representatives in pure representative systems want to be reelected to keep their prerogatives in the political decision-making process, representatives in mixed-systems actually want to avoid the challenge points of referendums, and so to keep their authorization to act on all the issues of which they are in charge, in addition to being reelected. In a semi-direct democracy, the aims of representatives could thus be both to be reelected and also to avoid popular scrutiny (Hug 2008, 261) that would withdraw their authority to act on a certain topic. At the very least, they have an incentive to collude with the actors being able to trigger a referendum, if possible, to avoid popular scrutiny (Hug 2008, 261). In this sense, the model of anticipatory representation developed by Mansbridge 15 seems to describe their role in a very relevant way. Contrary to the promissory model, which focuses on the realization of the promises made by the representatives at the time of their election, the anticipatory model highlights the importance of the potential reelection moment in they way representatives choose to act. Because of their desire for reelection, anticipatory representatives would actually act so as to please future voters namely voters at the time of the next election (Mansbridge 2003, 518, 517). Their actions would be guided by their beliefs [ ] about the future preferences of the voter (Mansbridge 2003, 517). Representatives would thus have an incentive to be in continuous communication and interaction with the voters in order to learn about and keep track of their opinions. In a prudential move to realize their goal of reelection, they would give attention to underlying interests as well as present preferences (Mansbridge 2003, ). According to Mansbridge, anticipatory representatives play a role similar to that of entrepreneurs anticipating the demands of clients : They are active, in searching out and sometimes creating new preferences (Mansbridge 2003, 518) A model to which Pitkin shortly points at when she writes that legislators often pattern their actions not on what their constituents ought to want but on what they anticipate their constituents will want [ ]. This is natural; the legislators want to be reelected (Pitkin 1967, 164). 16 The analogy of clients is quite problematic with regards to clientelism, which may sometimes be functional for democracy in that it provides a means for parties to mobilize support and for candidates to build resilient constituencies but comes with many dangers for democratic regimes (Brun and Diamond 2014, ix); Mansbridge doesn t seem to consider this in her article, but it could deserve additional considerations. 17

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Democracy and Common Valuations

Democracy and Common Valuations Democracy and Common Valuations Philip Pettit Three views of the ideal of democracy dominate contemporary thinking. The first conceptualizes democracy as a system for empowering public will, the second

More information

Political Participation under Democracy

Political Participation under Democracy Political Participation under Democracy Daniel Justin Kleinschmidt Cpr. Nr.: POL-PST.XB December 19 th, 2012 Political Science, Bsc. Semester 1 International Business & Politics Question: 2 Total Number

More information

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi

We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Clara Brandi REVIEW Clara Brandi We the Stakeholders: The Power of Representation beyond Borders? Terry Macdonald, Global Stakeholder Democracy. Power and Representation Beyond Liberal States, Oxford, Oxford University

More information

Direct Democracy Promises and Challenges

Direct Democracy Promises and Challenges Political Science Department Direct Democracy Promises and Challenges Céline Colombo University of Zurich Local-level citizen consultations. Democracy without mediation Barcelona, 18 June 2018 Overview

More information

GLOBAL DEMOCRACY THE PROBLEM OF A WRONG PERSPECTIVE

GLOBAL DEMOCRACY THE PROBLEM OF A WRONG PERSPECTIVE GLOBAL DEMOCRACY THE PROBLEM OF A WRONG PERSPECTIVE XIth Conference European Culture (Lecture Paper) Ander Errasti Lopez PhD in Ethics and Political Philosophy UNIVERSITAT POMPEU FABRA GLOBAL DEMOCRACY

More information

Idea developed Bill drafted

Idea developed Bill drafted Idea developed A legislator decides to sponsor a bill, sometimes at the suggestion of a constituent, interest group, public official or the Governor. The legislator may ask other legislators in either

More information

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: 699 708 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI 10.1007/s10982-015-9239-8 ARIE ROSEN (Accepted 31 August 2015) Alon Harel, Why Law Matters. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

Direct Democracy. A philosophical point of view. 11 April 2016

Direct Democracy. A philosophical point of view. 11 April 2016 Direct Democracy A philosophical point of view 11 April 2016 What is Democracy? Democracy (Christiano, 2015) [... ] a method of group decision making characterized by a kind of equality among the participants

More information

ACCOUNTABLE DEMOCRACY

ACCOUNTABLE DEMOCRACY ACCOUNTABLE DEMOCRACY www.accountabledemocracy.org Guillem Compte CONTENTS ١. What is accountable democracy? ٢. Why accountable democracy? (Background) ٣. How does it work? ٤. Conclusion ٥. Why accountable

More information

Migrants and external voting

Migrants and external voting The Migration & Development Series On the occasion of International Migrants Day New York, 18 December 2008 Panel discussion on The Human Rights of Migrants Facilitating the Participation of Migrants in

More information

Prof. Dr. Arno Scherzberg. INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS IN GERMAN PUBLIC LAW - Paper presented at a German-Columbian Law Colloquium in Erfurt,

Prof. Dr. Arno Scherzberg. INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS IN GERMAN PUBLIC LAW - Paper presented at a German-Columbian Law Colloquium in Erfurt, Prof. Dr. Arno Scherzberg INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS IN GERMAN PUBLIC LAW - Paper presented at a German-Columbian Law Colloquium in Erfurt, 2008-1. The fundamental distinction between objective law and subjective

More information

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3 Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3 A common world is a set of circumstances in which the fulfillment of all or nearly all of the fundamental interests of each

More information

The source of authority in a referendum democracy

The source of authority in a referendum democracy The source of authority in a referendum democracy Summary We are the source of all governmental authority and power in this Republic, as set out in Article 6.1 of our Constitution. Why is that the Dáil

More information

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3

Introduction 478 U.S. 186 (1986) U.S. 558 (2003). 3 Introduction In 2003 the Supreme Court of the United States overturned its decision in Bowers v. Hardwick and struck down a Texas law that prohibited homosexual sodomy. 1 Writing for the Court in Lawrence

More information

SUMMARY REPORT KEY POINTS

SUMMARY REPORT KEY POINTS SUMMARY REPORT The Citizens Assembly on Brexit was held over two weekends in September 17. It brought together randomly selected citizens who reflected the diversity of the UK electorate. The Citizens

More information

Reading vs. Seeing. Federal and state government are often looked at as separate entities but upon

Reading vs. Seeing. Federal and state government are often looked at as separate entities but upon Reading vs. Seeing Federal and state government are often looked at as separate entities but upon combining what I experienced with what I read, I have discovered that these forms of government actually

More information

Jurisdictional control and the Constitutional court in the Tunisian Constitution

Jurisdictional control and the Constitutional court in the Tunisian Constitution Jurisdictional control and the Constitutional court in the Tunisian Constitution Xavier PHILIPPE The introduction of a true Constitutional Court in the Tunisian Constitution of 27 January 2014 constitutes

More information

Introduction to Robert's Rules of Order from:

Introduction to Robert's Rules of Order from: Introduction to Robert's Rules of Order from: http://www.robertsrules.org/rulesintro.htm 1. What is Parliamentary Procedure? 2. Why is Parliamentary Procedure Important? 3. Example of the Order of Business

More information

Problems in Contemporary Democratic Theory

Problems in Contemporary Democratic Theory Kevin Elliott KJE2106@Columbia.edu Office Hours: Wednesday 4-6, IAB 734 POLS S3310 Summer 2014 (Session D) Problems in Contemporary Democratic Theory This course considers central questions in contemporary

More information

Parliamentary vs. Presidential Systems

Parliamentary vs. Presidential Systems Parliamentary vs. Presidential Systems Martin Okolikj School of Politics and International Relations (SPIRe) University College Dublin 02 November 2016 1990s Parliamentary vs. Presidential Systems Scholars

More information

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes

Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes * Crossroads ISSN 1825-7208 Vol. 6, no. 2 pp. 87-95 Power: A Radical View by Steven Lukes In 1974 Steven Lukes published Power: A radical View. Its re-issue in 2005 with the addition of two new essays

More information

CHAPTER 9 Conclusions: Political Equality and the Beauty of Cycling

CHAPTER 9 Conclusions: Political Equality and the Beauty of Cycling CHAPTER 9 Conclusions: Political Equality and the Beauty of Cycling I have argued that it is necessary to bring together the three literatures social choice theory, normative political philosophy, and

More information

Introduction. Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes

Introduction. Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes Bernard Manin, Adam Przeworski, and Susan C. Stokes Introduction The aim of every political constitution is, or ought to be, first to obtain for rulers men who possess most wisdom to discern, and most

More information

Comments on Betts and Collier s Framework: Grete Brochmann, Professor, University of Oslo.

Comments on Betts and Collier s Framework: Grete Brochmann, Professor, University of Oslo. 1 Comments on Betts and Collier s Framework: Grete Brochmann, Professor, University of Oslo. Sustainable migration Start by saying that I am strongly in favour of this endeavor. It is visionary and bold.

More information

Phil 290, February 22, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 7

Phil 290, February 22, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 7 Phil 290, February 22, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 7 Limits to democratic authority: When the democratic assembly (positively) makes a decision that encroaches on: 1. democratic

More information

Police and crime panels. Guidance on confirmation hearings

Police and crime panels. Guidance on confirmation hearings Police and crime panels Guidance on confirmation hearings Community safety, policing and fire services This guidance has been prepared by the Centre for Public Scrutiny and the Local Government Association.

More information

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p. RAWLS Project: to interpret the initial situation, formulate principles of choice, and then establish which principles should be adopted. The principles of justice provide an assignment of fundamental

More information

Comparing Foreign Political Systems Focus Questions for Unit 1

Comparing Foreign Political Systems Focus Questions for Unit 1 Comparing Foreign Political Systems Focus Questions for Unit 1 Any additions or revision to the draft version of the study guide posted earlier in the term are noted in bold. Why should we bother comparing

More information

GCE AS 2 Student Guidance Government & Politics. Course Companion Unit AS 2: The British Political System. For first teaching from September 2008

GCE AS 2 Student Guidance Government & Politics. Course Companion Unit AS 2: The British Political System. For first teaching from September 2008 GCE AS 2 Student Guidance Government & Politics Course Companion Unit AS 2: The British Political System For first teaching from September 2008 For first award of AS Level in Summer 2009 For first award

More information

International Court of Justice (ICJ) Committee Guide

International Court of Justice (ICJ) Committee Guide International Court of Justice (ICJ) Committee Guide Committee Roles President (Moderator) The President is the Presiding Justice of the International Court of Justice (ICJ), who is elected every three

More information

For those who favor strong limits on regulation,

For those who favor strong limits on regulation, 26 / Regulation / Winter 2015 2016 DEREGULTION Using Delegation to Promote Deregulation Instead of trying to restrain agencies rulemaking power, why not create an agency with the authority and incentive

More information

24 Criteria for the Recognition of Inventors and the Procedure to Settle Disputes about the Recognition of Inventors

24 Criteria for the Recognition of Inventors and the Procedure to Settle Disputes about the Recognition of Inventors 24 Criteria for the Recognition of Inventors and the Procedure to Settle Disputes about the Recognition of Inventors Research Fellow: Toshitaka Kudo Under the existing Japanese laws, the indication of

More information

Instructor: Margaret Kohn. Fall, Thursday, Office Hours: Thursday 1:00-2:00 (SS3118)

Instructor: Margaret Kohn. Fall, Thursday, Office Hours: Thursday 1:00-2:00 (SS3118) POL 2001: 20 th Century Political Thought Instructor: Margaret Kohn Fall, Thursday, 10-12 Office Hours: Thursday 1:00-2:00 (SS3118) Email: kohn@utsc.utoronto.ca This course is a survey of leading texts

More information

Key note address. Violence and discrimination against the girl child: General introduction

Key note address. Violence and discrimination against the girl child: General introduction A parliamentary perspective on discrimination and violence against the girl child New York, 1 March 2007 A parliamentary event organized by the Inter-Parliamentary Union and the United Nations Division

More information

Viktória Babicová 1. mail:

Viktória Babicová 1. mail: Sethi, Harsh (ed.): State of Democracy in South Asia. A Report by the CDSA Team. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2008, 302 pages, ISBN: 0195689372. Viktória Babicová 1 Presented book has the format

More information

CAN FAIR VOTING SYSTEMS REALLY MAKE A DIFFERENCE?

CAN FAIR VOTING SYSTEMS REALLY MAKE A DIFFERENCE? CAN FAIR VOTING SYSTEMS REALLY MAKE A DIFFERENCE? Facts and figures from Arend Lijphart s landmark study: Patterns of Democracy: Government Forms and Performance in Thirty-Six Countries Prepared by: Fair

More information

Political Science 423 DEMOCRATIC THEORY. Thursdays, 3:30 6:30 pm, Foster 305. Patchen Markell University of Chicago Spring 2000

Political Science 423 DEMOCRATIC THEORY. Thursdays, 3:30 6:30 pm, Foster 305. Patchen Markell University of Chicago Spring 2000 Political Science 423 DEMOCRATIC THEORY Thursdays, 3:30 6:30 pm, Foster 305 Patchen Markell University of Chicago Spring 2000 Office: Pick 519 Phone: 773-702-8057 Email: p-markell@uchicago.edu Web: http://home.uchicago.edu/~pmarkell/

More information

Introduction. Animus, and Why It Matters. Which of these situations is not like the others?

Introduction. Animus, and Why It Matters. Which of these situations is not like the others? Introduction Animus, and Why It Matters Which of these situations is not like the others? 1. The federal government requires that persons arriving from foreign nations experiencing dangerous outbreaks

More information

Democratic Engagement

Democratic Engagement JANUARY 2010 Democratic Engagement EXECUTIVE SUMMARY PRAIRIE WILD CONSULTING CO. Together with HOLDEN & Associates Introduction Democratic Engagement has been selected as one of eight domains that comprises

More information

HIGH-LEVEL SEMINAR FOR POLICY MAKERS AND POLICY IMPLEMENTERS ON RESULTS BASED MANAGEMENT

HIGH-LEVEL SEMINAR FOR POLICY MAKERS AND POLICY IMPLEMENTERS ON RESULTS BASED MANAGEMENT African Training and Research Centre in Administration for Development Hanns Seidel Foundation HIGH-LEVEL SEMINAR FOR POLICY MAKERS AND POLICY IMPLEMENTERS ON RESULTS BASED MANAGEMENT Enhancing synergies

More information

The nuts and bolts of oppositions and appeals. Henrik Skødt, European Patent Attorney

The nuts and bolts of oppositions and appeals. Henrik Skødt, European Patent Attorney The nuts and bolts of oppositions and appeals Henrik Skødt, European Patent Attorney Overview Preparing a notice of opposition. Responding to an opposition. Oral proceedings Filing an appeal notice and

More information

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_ , 223 227 Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_1359 223..227 Annabelle Lever London School of Economics This article summarises objections to compulsory voting developed in my

More information

Defining Accountability

Defining Accountability Defining By Andreas P. Kyriacou Associate Professor of Economics, University of Girona (Spain). Background paper prepared for Aids International (AAI) workshop on May 12-13, 2008, Stockholm. I. Introduction

More information

Dr. Theresa Reidy. The Citizens Assembly

Dr. Theresa Reidy. The Citizens Assembly Paper of Dr. Theresa Reidy University College Cork delivered to The Citizens Assembly on 13 January 2018 Session 6: Citizens Initiatives Theresa Reidy, University College Cork Introduction Voters in most

More information

New Zealand Germany 2013

New Zealand Germany 2013 There is a budding campaign to change the UK electoral system from a First Past the Post system (FPTP) to one that is based on Proportional Representation (PR) 1. The campaign makes many valid points.

More information

Institutionalization: New Concepts and New Methods. Randolph Stevenson--- Rice University. Keith E. Hamm---Rice University

Institutionalization: New Concepts and New Methods. Randolph Stevenson--- Rice University. Keith E. Hamm---Rice University Institutionalization: New Concepts and New Methods Randolph Stevenson--- Rice University Keith E. Hamm---Rice University Andrew Spiegelman--- Rice University Ronald D. Hedlund---Northeastern University

More information

CONTROL ON THE ADMINISTRATIVE ACTS BY THE ADMINISTRATIVE COURTS

CONTROL ON THE ADMINISTRATIVE ACTS BY THE ADMINISTRATIVE COURTS BULGARIA CONTROL ON THE ADMINISTRATIVE ACTS BY THE ADMINISTRATIVE COURTS Scope of jurisdiction 1.1. What types are the controlled acts (bylaw/individual)? As per the Bulgarian legal theory and practice

More information

Scenario 1: Municipal Decision-Making

Scenario 1: Municipal Decision-Making Scenario 1: Municipal Decision-Making Facilitator: Judith Innes Panelists: Josh Cohen, Archon Fung, David Laws, Carolyn Lukensmeyer, Jane Mansbridge, Nancy Roberts, Jay Rothman Scenario: A local government

More information

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent? Chapter 1 Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent? Cristina Lafont Introduction In what follows, I would like to contribute to a defense of deliberative democracy by giving an affirmative answer

More information

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at International Phenomenological Society Review: What's so Rickety? Richardson's Non-Epistemic Democracy Reviewed Work(s): Democratic Autonomy: Public Reasoning about the Ends of Policy by Henry S. Richardson

More information

Congressional Investigations:

Congressional Investigations: Congressional Investigations: INNER WORKINGS JERRY VooRRist ONGRESSIONAL investigations have a necessary and important place in the American scheme of government. First, such investigations should probably

More information

Jürgen Kohl March 2011

Jürgen Kohl March 2011 Jürgen Kohl March 2011 Comments to Claus Offe: What, if anything, might we mean by progressive politics today? Let me first say that I feel honoured by the opportunity to comment on this thoughtful and

More information

Swiss Party System, Political Processes and Interaction with Society Presentation held by Claude Longchamp

Swiss Party System, Political Processes and Interaction with Society Presentation held by Claude Longchamp Swiss Party System, Political Processes and Interaction with Society Presentation held by Claude Longchamp Referent: Claude Longchamp, Political Scientist, Head of the Research Institute gfs.bern, Lecturer

More information

Summary by M. Vijaybhasker Srinivas (2007), Akshara Gurukulam

Summary by M. Vijaybhasker Srinivas (2007), Akshara Gurukulam Participation and Development: Perspectives from the Comprehensive Development Paradigm 1 Joseph E. Stiglitz Participatory processes (like voice, openness and transparency) promote truly successful long

More information

DPA/EAD input to OHCHR draft guidelines on effective implementation of the right to participation in public affairs May 2017

DPA/EAD input to OHCHR draft guidelines on effective implementation of the right to participation in public affairs May 2017 UN Department of Political Affairs (UN system focal point for electoral assistance): Input for the OHCHR draft guidelines on the effective implementation of the right to participate in public affairs 1.

More information

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle

Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle Problems with the one-person-one-vote Principle [Please note this is a very rough draft. A polished and complete draft will be uploaded closer to the Congress date]. In this paper, I highlight some normative

More information

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon PHILIP PETTIT The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon In The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy, Christopher McMahon challenges my claim that the republican goal of promoting or maximizing

More information

Judicial Reform in Germany

Judicial Reform in Germany Judicial Reform in Germany Prof. Juergen Meyer In Germany, the civil law system is about to undergo a number of far-reaching changes. The need for reform has been the subject of debate for a number of

More information

Section A: General Assembly, Economic and Social Council, Security Council, Ad Hoc GA Committee on Middle Eastern Security, and Human Rights Council

Section A: General Assembly, Economic and Social Council, Security Council, Ad Hoc GA Committee on Middle Eastern Security, and Human Rights Council Section A: General Assembly, Economic and Social Council, Security Council, Ad Hoc GA Committee on Middle Eastern Security, and Human Rights Council Since LEBMUN seeks to simulate the real United Nations,

More information

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models

Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models Voters Interests in Campaign Finance Regulation: Formal Models Scott Ashworth June 6, 2012 The Supreme Court s decision in Citizens United v. FEC significantly expands the scope for corporate- and union-financed

More information

Democracy, understood as collective self-rule, requires

Democracy, understood as collective self-rule, requires Can Deliberative Minipublics Address the Cognitive Challenges of Democratic Citizenship? Mark E. Warren, University of British Columbia John Gastil, The Pennsylvania State University Democracy asks its

More information

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Bryan Smyth, University of Memphis 2011 APA Central Division Meeting // Session V-I: Global Justice // 2. April 2011 I am

More information

Hosted by the Department of Government Listening to One's Constituents? Now, There's an Idea

Hosted by the Department of Government Listening to One's Constituents? Now, There's an Idea Hosted by the Department of Government Listening to One's Constituents? Now, There's an Idea Professor Jane Mansbridge Charles F. Adams Professor of Political Leadership and Democratic Values, Harvard

More information

RE-AMP ORGANIZING HUB. Coalition Ground Rules Discussion Guide A badly illustrated guide to setting good coalition ground rules

RE-AMP ORGANIZING HUB. Coalition Ground Rules Discussion Guide A badly illustrated guide to setting good coalition ground rules RE-AMP ORGANIZING HUB Coalition Ground Rules Discussion Guide A badly illustrated guide to setting good coalition ground rules 2015 About RE-AMP RE-AMP is an active network of nearly 160 nonprofits and

More information

Philosophy 383 SFSU Rorty

Philosophy 383 SFSU Rorty Reading SAL Week 15: Justice and Health Care Stein brook: Imposing Personal Responsibility for Health (2006) There s an assumption that if we live right we ll live longer and cost less. As a result there

More information

Repeat Voting: Two-Vote May Lead More People To Vote

Repeat Voting: Two-Vote May Lead More People To Vote Repeat Voting: Two-Vote May Lead More People To Vote Sergiu Hart October 17, 2017 Abstract A repeat voting procedure is proposed, whereby voting is carried out in two identical rounds. Every voter can

More information

Comment. Draft National Policy on Mass Communication for Timor Leste

Comment. Draft National Policy on Mass Communication for Timor Leste Comment on the Draft National Policy on Mass Communication for Timor Leste ARTICLE 19 London September 2009 ARTICLE 19 Free Word Centre 60 Farringdon Road London EC1R 3GA United Kingdom Tel: +44 20 7324

More information

CARLETON ECONOMIC PAPERS

CARLETON ECONOMIC PAPERS CEP 17-06 In Defense of Majoritarianism Stanley L. Winer March 2017 CARLETON ECONOMIC PAPERS Department of Economics 1125 Colonel By Drive Ottawa, Ontario, Canada K1S 5B6 In Defense of Majoritarianism

More information

LGST 226: Markets, Morality, and Capitalism Robert Hughes Fall 2016 Syllabus

LGST 226: Markets, Morality, and Capitalism Robert Hughes Fall 2016 Syllabus LGST 226: Markets, Morality, and Capitalism Robert Hughes Fall 2016 Syllabus Class meetings: JMHH F65, TR 1:30-3:00 Instructor email: hughesrc@wharton.upenn.edu Office hours: JMHH 668, Tuesdays 3-4:30

More information

GUIDELINES ON ELECTIONS. Adopted by the Venice Commission at its 51 st Plenary Session (Venice, 5-6 July 2002)

GUIDELINES ON ELECTIONS. Adopted by the Venice Commission at its 51 st Plenary Session (Venice, 5-6 July 2002) Strasbourg, 10 July 2002 CDL-AD (2002) 13 Or. fr. Opinion no. 190/2002 EUROPEAN COMMISSION FOR DEMOCRACY THROUGH LAW (VENICE COMMISSION) GUIDELINES ON ELECTIONS Adopted by the Venice Commission at its

More information

Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation

Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation Kristen A. Harkness Princeton University February 2, 2011 Research Note: Toward an Integrated Model of Concept Formation The process of thinking inevitably begins with a qualitative (natural) language,

More information

In Defense of Majoritarianism

In Defense of Majoritarianism Carleton University, Ottawa March 2-4, 2017 In Defense of Majoritarianism Stanley L. Winer, Carleton University Conference Sponsor(s): Faculty of Public Affairs Partners: Presenting sponsor: Version /

More information

Participation in European Parliament elections: A framework for research and policy-making

Participation in European Parliament elections: A framework for research and policy-making FIFTH FRAMEWORK RESEARCH PROGRAMME (1998-2002) Democratic Participation and Political Communication in Systems of Multi-level Governance Participation in European Parliament elections: A framework for

More information

Arguments for and against electoral system change in Ireland

Arguments for and against electoral system change in Ireland Prof. Gallagher Arguments for and against electoral system change in Ireland Why would we decide to change, or not to change, the current PR-STV electoral system? In this short paper we ll outline some

More information

Chapter 7: Legislatures

Chapter 7: Legislatures Chapter 7: Legislatures Objectives Explain the role and activities of the legislature. Discuss how the legislatures are organized and how they operate. Identify the characteristics of the state legislators.

More information

An Implementation Protocol to Unblock the Brexit Process

An Implementation Protocol to Unblock the Brexit Process An Implementation Protocol to Unblock the Brexit Process A proposal for a legal bridge between a revised Political Declaration and the Withdrawal Agreement Discussion Paper Kenneth Armstrong Professor

More information

Lessons from Brexit Negotiations

Lessons from Brexit Negotiations This note is not intended as an argument for or against Brexit, it simply draws on my training course for Medical Students, who need to learn something about international negotiations to participate in

More information

Office of the Compliance Officer and Community Liaison (COCL)

Office of the Compliance Officer and Community Liaison (COCL) Office of the Compliance Officer and Community Liaison (COCL) Rosenbaum & Watson, LLP COCL Office: Dennis Rosenbaum, Ph.D. 525 NE Oregon, Suite 250 Amy Watson, Ph.D. Portland, OR 97232 Thomas Christoff,

More information

Part Three (continued): Electoral Systems & Linkage Institutions

Part Three (continued): Electoral Systems & Linkage Institutions Part Three (continued): Electoral Systems & Linkage Institutions Our political institutions work remarkably well. They are designed to clang against each other. The noise is democracy at work. -- Michael

More information

Chapter 2: American Citizens and Political Culture Test Bank. Multiple Choice

Chapter 2: American Citizens and Political Culture Test Bank. Multiple Choice Chapter 2: American Citizens and Political Culture Test Bank Multiple Choice 1. What s at Stake? at the beginning of Chapter 2 shows that immigration reform. a. is a very important issue b. is not an important

More information

What Should We Know About American Government?

What Should We Know About American Government? American Government: Brief Version 6/e 1 What Should We Know About American Government? I. Reviewing the Chapter Chapter Focus Study Outline The purpose of this chapter is to give you an understanding

More information

idolatry. Claro Mayo Recto 10 Institute for Political and Electoral Reform

idolatry. Claro Mayo Recto 10 Institute for Political and Electoral Reform In truth, actual events tamper with the Constitution. History reveals its defects and dangers. I believe we can do better service to the Constitution by remedying its defects and meeting the criticisms

More information

APPLICATION FORM FOR PROSPECTIVE WORKSHOP DIRECTORS

APPLICATION FORM FOR PROSPECTIVE WORKSHOP DIRECTORS APPLICATION FORM FOR PROSPECTIVE WORKSHOP DIRECTORS If you wish to apply to direct a workshop at the Joint Sessions in Helsinki, Finland in Spring 2007, please first see the explanatory notes, then complete

More information

DEMOCRACY AND THE COMMON GOOD D A W S O N C O L L E G E / 1 1 / 1 3 B Y R O B E R T R O Y

DEMOCRACY AND THE COMMON GOOD D A W S O N C O L L E G E / 1 1 / 1 3 B Y R O B E R T R O Y DEMOCRACY AND THE COMMON GOOD D A W S O N C O L L E G E 2 0 1 2 / 1 1 / 1 3 B Y R O B E R T R O Y PRESENTATION PLAN 1 Context 2 Democracy s Challenges 3 Democracy and the Common Good 4 Hints for Solutions

More information

Lecture Outline: Chapter 2

Lecture Outline: Chapter 2 Lecture Outline: Chapter 2 Constitutional Foundations I. The U.S. Constitution has been a controversial document from the time it was written. A. There was, of course, very strong opposition to the ratification

More information

What comes next when. Resources

What comes next when. Resources Resources State Government General Website: www.ohio.gov Ohio House of Representatives: www.house.state.oh.us Ohio Senate: www.senate.state.oh.us You ve learned about the candidates And cast your vote

More information

PETER SUTHERLAND DISMISSES FEARS THAT THE WORLD TRADE ORGANIZATION WILL INFRINGE NATIONAL SOVEREIGNTY AS UNFOUNDED

PETER SUTHERLAND DISMISSES FEARS THAT THE WORLD TRADE ORGANIZATION WILL INFRINGE NATIONAL SOVEREIGNTY AS UNFOUNDED CENTRE WILLIAM-RAPPARD, RUE DE LAUSANNE 154, 1211 GENÈVE 21. TÉL. 022 73951 11 GATT/1634 30 May 1994 ft PETER SUTHERLAND DISMISSES FEARS THAT THE WORLD TRADE ORGANIZATION WILL INFRINGE NATIONAL SOVEREIGNTY

More information

1100 Ethics July 2016

1100 Ethics July 2016 1100 Ethics July 2016 perhaps, those recommended by Brock. His insight that this creates an irresolvable moral tragedy, given current global economic circumstances, is apt. Blake does not ask, however,

More information

FINAL REPORT OF THE CHARTER REVISION COMMISSION July 31, 2008

FINAL REPORT OF THE CHARTER REVISION COMMISSION July 31, 2008 FINAL REPORT OF THE 2007 2008 CHARTER REVISION COMMISSION July 31, 2008 This Charter Revision Commission was appointed by the Town Board of Directors on May 15, 2007. Appointed to the Commission were:

More information

Basic Robert s Rules of Order as used by the Savary Island Committee.

Basic Robert s Rules of Order as used by the Savary Island Committee. Basic Robert s Rules of Order as used by the Savary Island Committee. Revised and explained, in green text below. 1. Introduction of Business. 1.1 All business should be brought before the assembly in

More information

Chapter 2 The Electoral College Today

Chapter 2 The Electoral College Today Chapter 2 The Electoral College Today Abstract Today s Electoral College and the one created by the Founding Fathers are two different election mechanisms. The Founding Fathers might have expected that

More information

The Politics of Emotional Confrontation in New Democracies: The Impact of Economic

The Politics of Emotional Confrontation in New Democracies: The Impact of Economic Paper prepared for presentation at the panel A Return of Class Conflict? Political Polarization among Party Leaders and Followers in the Wake of the Sovereign Debt Crisis The 24 th IPSA Congress Poznan,

More information

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic

Democracy, and the Evolution of International. to Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs. Tom Ginsburg* ... National Courts, Domestic The European Journal of International Law Vol. 20 no. 4 EJIL 2010; all rights reserved... National Courts, Domestic Democracy, and the Evolution of International Law: A Reply to Eyal Benvenisti and George

More information

Introduction to Robert s Rules of Order

Introduction to Robert s Rules of Order Introduction to Robert s Rules of Order 1 1. Introduction of Business 1.1 All business should be brought before the assembly in the form of a motion. 1.2 Before a member can make a motion or address the

More information

A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS

A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS A COMPARISON BETWEEN TWO DATASETS Bachelor Thesis by S.F. Simmelink s1143611 sophiesimmelink@live.nl Internationale Betrekkingen en Organisaties Universiteit Leiden 9 June 2016 Prof. dr. G.A. Irwin Word

More information

Independence, Accountability and Human Rights

Independence, Accountability and Human Rights NOTE: This article represents the views of the author and not the Department of Justice, Yukon Government. Independence, Accountability and Human Rights by Lorne Sossin 1 As part of the Yukon Human Rights

More information

NEW YORK CITY PARALEGAL ASSOCIATION - BYLAWS

NEW YORK CITY PARALEGAL ASSOCIATION - BYLAWS NEW YORK CITY PARALEGAL ASSOCIATION - BYLAWS INDEX TO AMENDED AND RESTATED BY-LAWS OF NEW YORK CITY PARALEGAL ASSOCIATION, INC. PAGE ARTICLE I NAME AND CERTIFICATE OF INCORPORATION 3 1.01 NAME 1.02 CERTIFICATE

More information

Bylaws of the University of Alaska Fairbanks Staff Council Effective 9/12/2016 Revised 9/21/2016

Bylaws of the University of Alaska Fairbanks Staff Council Effective 9/12/2016 Revised 9/21/2016 Bylaws of the University of Alaska Fairbanks Staff Council Effective 9/12/2016 Revised 9/21/2016 Section 1. Preamble The UAF Staff Council is a representative organization for all APT and Classified employees

More information