Equality of What? and Intergenerational Justice

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Equality of What? and Intergenerational Justice"

Transcription

1 Equality of What? and Intergenerational Justice Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen Aarhus University, Denmark ABSTRACT. Luck egalitarian accounts of distributive justice presuppose a metric in terms of which people s relative positions are determined. This article addresses the issue of the metric in an intergenerational setting focusing on two problems: expensive tastes and the slavery of the talented. First, on the assumption that later generations will have more expensive preferences than earlier generations with goods that were luxuries for past generations becoming necessities, the availability of which generates little satisfaction for later generations welfare egalitarianism recommends redistribution of resources in favour of later generations. Indeed, welfare egalitarianism allows that one generation cultivates cheap preferences among future generations thereby allowing itself to deplete natural resources. I argue that neither of these implications defeats welfare egalitarianism as an account of intergenerational justice. Second, suppose, plausibly, that work by one generation positively affects the resources at the disposal of all later generations and assume that we apply Dworkin s idea of an auction of resources to an intergenerational setting. On these assumptions, there is a sense in which, ceteris paribus, earlier generations command more resources to wit, more in terms of the internal resources that valuable labour power constitutes than later generations. Accordingly, resource-egalitarianism implies that the first generation is required to be maximally productive. This implication represents a particularly damaging version of the so-called problem of the slavery of the talented, which has exercised resource egalitarians in an intragenerational setting. Overall, this paper indirectly supports welfare egalitarianism by deflecting possible criticisms of it, and by resisting resourcist proposals as to how one should accommodate the problem of the slavery of the first generation. KEYWORDS. Dworkin, equality, expensive tastes, intergenerational justice, luck egalitarianism, welfarism ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES 19, no. 3(2012): by Centre for Ethics, KU Leuven. All rights reserved. doi: /EP

2 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 I. INTRODUCTION Patterned theories of distributive justice need, at some point, to incorporate an account of the currency, or metric, in terms of which people s positions are determined for the purpose of assessing the justice of the relevant distribution. Luck egalitarians have responded to this basic requirement with considerable care: Arneson s equality of opportunity for welfare (1989), Dworkin s equality of resources (1981a; 1981b; 2000), and Cohen s equality of access to advantage (1989) testify to this. However, their focus has been on intragenerational justice. On intergenerational justice the just distribution of goods across generations they have been less vocal. 1 Presumably this reflects the view that the shift from intragenerational to intergenerational raises no new issues. This view appears to be correct in the sense that both types of justice do not oblige us to introduce contrasting metrics: their metrics need not diverge. 2 But this does not mean that specific consideration of the intergenerational case is unnecessary. For one thing, such consideration might highlight consequences of the metric obscured or absent in the more familiar intragenerational context, and this may lead to modification of the metric itself. Second, an account of the metric of justice that is appropriately defended in the intragenerational setting may turn out to have surprising implications in the intergenerational setting. We might, on reflection, judge that we should accept these implications, even if they are at odds with our initial convictions about intergenerational justice. My goal here is explore two main problems the currency of justice is known to raise. I want to see how these problems play out in an intergenerational setting, since I believe that this focus offers a new angle on the metric of equality issue. The first main problem relates to expensive tastes and is dealt with in Sections II and III. Several theorists addressing the intragenerational issue have argued that an individual who is worse off through having expensive preferences is not worse off in terms of the relevant currency of egalitarian justice. Assuming later generations 502

3 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? tend to have more expensive preferences than earlier generations with goods that were luxuries for past generations becoming necessities, the availability of which generates little satisfaction for later generations welfarist egalitarianism would seem to recommend redistribution of resources in favour of later generations. Some might take this as an objection to the view that welfare is the currency of justice (II). Moreover, welfarist egalitarians seem to be comfortable with the notion that we might cultivate cheap preferences among future generations, thereby allowing the present generation to deplete natural resources, and some regard this as a problem with welfarist egalitarianism (III). Like the first objection, this also concerns expensive preferences, but here the focus is on one party s actively and deliberately cultivating cheap preferences in another party. The second main problem concerns the issue of the slavery of the talented (Dworkin 1981b: 90), to which Dworkinians have paid much attention in the more familiar intragenerational context. The idea is that insofar as internal resources, e.g. productive talents, are included in the measure of resources in terms of which people should be equal, one hour of leisure for a talented person will count as a much greater consumption of resources than one hour of leisure for an untalented person. Now suppose, plausibly, that work by one generation positively affects the resources available for all later generations; and suppose that all members of the first generation are untalented relative to the members of later generations in the sense that had one of the later generations been the first, the volume of resources conferred on later generations through the efforts of the first generation would have been much greater than they in fact are. On these assumptions, it seems that an intergenerational problem of the slavery of the first generation arises. I explain how this happens and discuss various resourcist responses to the problem in sections IV to VI. I argue that we make best sense of the problem from a welfarist perspective. Hence, while the article offers no direct defence of the view that welfare is the currency of intergenerational justice, it offers indirect 503

4 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 support for this view by deflecting possible criticisms thereof, and by resisting resourcist proposals as to how one should accommodate the problem of the slavery of the first generation. 3 One preliminary point: I write about redistribution across generations as if there were some way of taking resources from one generation, wherever it is located in time, and giving these to another generation, wherever it happens to be located in time. Obviously, direct backward redistribution across generations is impossible, and this, among other factors, means that the principles of regulation of intergenerational equality must differ from the fundamental principles governing that equality. My concern in the present contribution is with the latter only. Accordingly, to insist that redistribution in favour of past generations is impossible is simply no objection to the views I advance. The said impossibility does not prevent us from asking whether, if past generations had been as well off as the present generation, the world would have been more just the sort of question we ask if we are concerned with fundamental principles of justice, not principles of regulation (Cohen 2008, 5; 19-21). 4 Also, even though redistribution in favour of past generations is impossible, redistribution from present to future generations remains possible. II. THE EXPENSIVE TASTES OF FUTURE GENERATIONS One important challenge to a welfarist metric appeals to the idea of expensive tastes (Page 2007, 455). In his defence of primary goods as the currency of justice, John Rawls asks us to Imagine two persons, one satisfied with a diet of milk, bread and beans, while the other is distraught without expensive wines and exotic dishes. In short one has expensive tastes, the other does not (1982, 168). If welfare is the relevant measure of egalitarian justice, the second person merits more resources than the first, since that (unlike equal shares) will ensure equality of welfare. However, Rawls denies that this is just: As moral persons citizens have some part in forming and cultivating their final ends and preferences. It is not 504

5 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? by itself an objection to the use of primary goods that it does not accommodate those with expensive tastes (1982, 168). 5 The expensive tastes problem seems pressing in the intergenerational setting, particularly if we focus on what is now the developed world. Here, generations ago, most people would have been satisfied with milk, bread and beans. But many members of the present generation require at least occasional expensive wines and exotic dishes to get to the same level of satisfaction, and who knows what exorbitant tastes future generations will develop. 6 More generally, by saying that members of one generation, G 2, have more expensive preferences than members of another, G 1, I mean that the former would reach a lower level of satisfaction than that actually enjoyed by members of G 1 were they only to have the goods available to the latter, whereas members of G 1 would have a higher level of welfare than actually enjoyed by members of G 2 were they only to have the resources available to G 2. Before I proceed, I should say a little more about expensive tastes. Rawls s example may mislead, or even give expensive tastes a bad name, because it does not specify the grounds of the relevant satisfaction and dissatisfaction. Suppose my dissatisfaction derives from an anti-egalitarian preference to have greater satisfaction or consume more expensive goods than others. This might be an objectionable preference from an egalitarian point of view, but it does not follow that I have expensive preferences. 7 For a person to have expensive preferences, in the sense explained and shown to be theoretically fruitful by Dworkin and Cohen, is for this person to need more income, or, to put the point more generally, more resources, than others do simply to achieve the same level of [some form of] welfare as those with less expensive preferences (Dworkin 2000, 48), be that form of welfare satisfaction of preference, or selfdevelopment, or good experience, or whatever other form of welfare is brought into view (Cohen 2004, 5-6). People who are very good at converting resources into welfare may have an anti-egalitarian preference that they have more than others and still have cheap preferences overall in 505

6 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 this sense e.g. because they are very good at converting resources into welfare and because they already have more welfare than others. 8 So construed, the concept of an expensive preference is essentially comparative. It describes a relationship between the preferences of two or more persons. Accordingly, I might have preferences that are expensive relative to one person and cheap relative to another. The baseline governing whether someone has expensive preferences and the expensiveness of satisfying other people s preferences may not converge. The baseline might be expensive relative to what it might have been had this person acted differently or been subjected to different conditions. Alternatively, preferences can turn out to be expensive when the difference between the quantity of resources required to achieve a certain level of satisfaction and the minimum quantity of resources that would have been required to achieve the same level of satisfaction had the agent acted differently is higher than it is in the case of other individuals. 9 Members of the present generation may have tastes that are expensive (relative to those of previous generations) according to Dworkin s definition, but not expensive (relative to those of previous generations) according to the definition just proposed. Although members of the present generation use more resources to reach a certain level of satisfaction than members of past generations, they could not have acted differently in a way that ensured that they were capable of reaching this level of satisfaction with fewer resources, whereas members of past generations could possibly have done so. Thus far I have discussed what it means for preferences to be expensive and, more specifically, for members of one generation to have more expensive preferences than that of another. I now turn to the moral significance of the fact that someone s preferences are expensive. Unlike Rawls and Dworkin, Arneson and Cohen do not take the expensive taste objection to show that the concept of welfare needs to be removed wholesale from the metric of justice. Rather, it shows that [w]e should replace equality of welfare by equality of opportunity for welfare (Cohen 506

7 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? 2010, 11; cf. Arneson 1991; 1989; italics mine). Hence, if the person with expensive tastes and the person with inexpensive tastes initially had equal opportunities for preference satisfaction, justice does not require the person who freely adopted more costly tastes to be brought up to the level of welfare now enjoyed by the person with cheaper tastes. Cohen thinks this response is truer to the underlying motivation of the expensive taste objection. 10 Applied to intergenerational justice, this view strikes me as plausible. It seems correct to insist that we should transfer resources to future generations with preferences that are more expensive than ours only if the expensiveness of those preferences is not the result of choices freely made by members of the relevant future generations. Rawls might disagree on the grounds that his position on non-compensation for expensive preferences is informed by his view of justice as a feature of relations of social cooperation, relations that do not obtain between past generations with cheap preferences and later generations with expensive preferences. According to his view, therefore, there is no injustice in either compensating or not compensating expensive preferences across generations. This Rawlsian reply is suspect, because it ties justice to the existence of relations of social cooperation. Also, I do think we can imagine situations in which justice requires that we take into account expensive preferences and do not simply let the frustration these generate (in the absence of a greater allocation of resources) fall on those who have such preferences. Consider the following case. G(eneration) 1 can choose between two policies both of which will give G 2 and G 3 the same quantity of resources. The first policy will cause G 3 to have expensive preferences; the second policy will cause neither generation to have expensive preferences. Assuming everything else is equal, I believe it would be unjust for G 1 to choose the first policy thereby causing inequality of welfare between future generations. If so, from a third person perspective at least, an expensive preference is not, pace Rawls, simply something for which the bearer of the preference bears full responsibility

8 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 In a later treatment of the topic, Cohen (2004, 7-8) revises the position espoused in his 1989 article. First, he stresses that what matters is not whether preference holders are responsible for having the preference, but whether they can reasonably be held responsible for the fact that their preference is expensive (cf. Arneson 1991). So if I cultivate a preference for transportation by private car rather than by train, which I could not possibly have foreseen would turn out to be expensive, because of soaring oil prices, according to Cohen I may be due compensation. Second, Cohen s 2004 position distinguishes between preferences that are informed by valuational judgments and those that are not. 12 An example of the former is a preference for opera, where this preference reflects the value judgment that a good life requires acquaintance with the fine arts. An example of the latter might be a strong preference for back massage that one has simply because it is pleasant without in any way judging massage or the pleasant experiences it gives to have any value. 13 Cohen believes that someone who has an expensive preference, which is informed by valuational judgment and could be unschooled, or which the holder deliberately chose to develop, may be entitled to compensation on account of his or her expensive preference: the subject s approving identification with their expensive tastes [ ] is something that I regard as a reason for offering it, since, where identification is present, it is, standardly, the agents very bad luck that a preference with which they strongly identify happens to be expensive, and to expect them to forgo or restrict satisfaction of that preference (because it is expensive) is, therefore, to ask them to accept an alienation from what is deep in them (2004, 7). 14 Let us apply Cohen s 2004 view to the issue of intergenerational justice. More specifically, we shall consider the suggestion that, according to this view, there is very little intergenerational injustice. Our preferences may be much more expensive than those of people who lived in medieval times. To reach the same level of satisfaction prior generations reached by having Sundays off, members of the present generation need the whole weekend off as well as several weeks of summer holidays, and the 508

9 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? preferences of future generations might well be more expensive than those of the present generation. According to Cohen s 1989 view, egalitarians would be unwilling to compensate people for such preferences if they could school themselves out of them. Our greater use of resources than previous generations might, therefore, involve an injustice it will do so if we are capable of jettisoning the expensive preferences and habituating to scarcity. Similarly, there might be no injustice if our present use of resources leads to the frustration of later generations expensive preferences, as long as these are preferences our descendants will be capable of schooling themselves out of. However, on the assumption that the expensive preferences are backed by valuational judgments say, unlike previous generations we believe leisure to be important to living a good life neither of these claims follows on Cohen s 2004 view. On that view, the present generation should transfer resources to allow future generations to satisfy their very expensive preferences, because these are informed by valuational judgments. This looks like a powerful objection to Cohen s 2004 position. The implication of that position that justice is compatible with massive intergenerational inequalities provided that these are suitably related to valuational judgments is surely highly questionable and, accordingly, Cohen s 1989 position delivers a more plausible view of intergenerational justice than his 2004 view. 15 III. CAUSING FUTURE GENERATIONS TO HAVE CHEAP PREFERENCES I now wish to consider a quite separate challenge to the welfarist perspective on intergenerational justice. Suppose one generation can determine whether the next generation has expensive or inexpensive tastes or, as I shall put it, suppose one generation can engineer the next generation s tastes, e.g. through the way in which they educate its members or through autonomy-circumventing techniques such as drugs or subliminal communication techniques. Imagine G(eneration) 1 faces the following choice: to preserve equality of welfare it can either abstain from using certain 509

10 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 natural resources, which will then be available to satisfy G 2 s preferences that will be identical to those of G 1, or it can somehow ensure that G 2 develops cheap preferences, in which case G 1 can use more resources and leave fewer resources to future generations. Does G 1 act unjustly if it fixes things so that G 2 has cheap preferences? If an injustice is involved, that will count against not only equality of welfare but also equality of opportunity for welfare, since the two generations have equal opportunities for welfare (Vrousalis forthcoming, 12). 16 Call this the preference engineering objection. In my view the preference engineering objection does little to undermine welfarist egalitarianism. First, I doubt that there is an egalitarian objection to this sort of engineering. To see that the case sketched above does not give rise to an egalitarian complaint, consider a scenario in which a generation develops cheaper preferences to achieve equal satisfaction for it and future generations with expensive tastes. This seems wholly compatible with equality. If so, why should it make a difference, from an egalitarian point of view, whether a generation develops cheap preferences or engineers a future generation to have cheap preferences? Second, I do not think that engineering cheap preferences as such is objectionable. Cheap preferences, perhaps especially their cultivation, are often disparaged. This happens partly because it is assumed that such preferences differ in kind from most of our preferences. But, as a matter of fact, it is hardly surprising that few of us have the desire to direct operas, to own the largest private collection of motorcycles, or to be the first tourist who travels three times into space. Most of our preferences are to varying degrees informed by the costs of their satisfaction. This is good. It saves us a lot of frustration. 17 And in some, but by no means all, cases this is unproblematic. The cases where making people holding cheap preferences rather than expensive ones is unproblematic are those in which the preferences are non-brute, i.e. reflect valuations. Our preferences are sometimes in conflict with our evaluations e.g. the preference for meat. Engineering 510

11 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? to ensure that future generations have no such brute, expensive preferences would not be objectionable. 18 In cases where the preferences are based on valuations there is nothing problematic about ensuring that people hold cheaper preferences provided they can reach those preferences through a sound deliberative route from their present evaluations. In fact, I am inclined to take a stronger view of the range of cases in which it is permissible to engineer future generations so that they hold cheaper preferences. In this instance, we may well be not just permitted, but even morally required to cause future generations to hold cheaper preferences. Indeed some respectable environmental aims e.g. changing people s preferences in relation to private versus public transportation or in relation to air travel and holidays involve precisely this. More specifically, if we can achieve equality across generations by ensuring that future generations will have cheaper preferences than we have, we might well be morally required to do so. Note that whether a preference is classified as cheap or expensive will depend on the baseline, and in the case of future generations there are several possible suggestions as to what the relevant baseline might be. If, for instance, the baseline is how costly the relevant generations preferences would have been had we not intervened, there is an obvious question about what, exactly, is problematic about our acting with the aim of dictating whether preferences of future generations will be costly. 19 I conclude that reservations about the engineering of preferences do not generate a strong objection to welfarist metrics. In fact, this particular line of attack has nothing specifically to do with welfarism versus resourcism. If we were to determine people s share of resources through Dworkin s auction, we could imagine future generations preferences being engineered in such a way that the members of those generations do not envy the resource bundles of previous generations, in which case no inequality of resources obtains across generations. If preference engineering is a problem for welfarism, it is also a problem for Dworkinian resourcism. 20 Note, finally, that the line of argument explored in this 511

12 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 section only presupposes that some ways of engineering future generations to have cheap preferences e.g. non-autonomy-violating ways are morally permissible. Hence, it avoids commitment to the view that all ways of engineering preferences of future generations are permissible. IV. DWORKIN S RESOURCISM AND SLAVERY OF THE TALENTED I now set aside expensive preferences and turn to worries about the intergenerational variant of Dworkin s slavery of the talented: the slavery of the first generation. To understand this concern we need some background. Dworkin s favoured metric is resources. In his view, therefore, people should be equal in the quantity of resources that they command. But how do we compare different bundles of resources? According to Dworkin s view, we should apply the envy test (2000, 68-69), which says that we should distribute resources and see if anyone prefers a bundle of resources possessed by another. If this is the case, equality of resources does not obtain and we should redistribute until we reach an envy free distribution. 21 Which resources are relevant for the purpose of applying the envy test? Clearly, external resources such as land and water should be included, but what should we say about internal resources such as labour power (or organs)? The question is tricky because, on the one hand, labour power is clearly a resource, and people who command more of it, or more valuable kinds of it, than others command more resources. On the other hand, labour power is closely tied to a person s talents and personality in such a way that people possess very different amounts of it, and addressing this inequality appears problematic. It is at this point that Dworkin s concern about the slavery of the talented enters the scene. Dworkin imagines that external resources are distributed through an auction at which everyone who participates bids and where all have equal bidding power. The price of popular resources rises simply because they have many bidders. Suppose internal resources are included in the auction. Since people have very different skills and talents, talented people 512

13 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? can expect that their labour power essentially their time will cost much more than the labour power of the untalented. Hence, if I am a talented person who would like some leisure, I will have to bid at the auction for some of my own time; and because, alternatively, I could be very productive in the hours I would like to spend in leisure, others will offer high bids for those hours. Accordingly, I will have to use a lot of my bidding power to ensure that I obtain some leisure time. Similarly, if I am a talented person who wants to spend some of my time in a job I find fulfilling, but in which I am not particularly talented and which in any case results in products few wish to buy, I will need to use a lot of my bidding power to ensure that this is possible. Indeed, if we allow coalitions of buyers to pool their resources and buy the labour power of those with talent, I might end up owning none of my time, with the owners of my labour power dictating what I do. 22 This, Dworkin submits, is unfair. The result of the auction, so construed, would be [ ] that each would have to spend his life in close to the commercially most profitable manner that he could, or, at least if he is talented, suffer some very serious deprivation if he did not. For since Adrian, for example, is able to produce prodigious income from farming, others would be willing to bid a large amount to have the right to his labor and the vegetables thereof, and if he outbids them, but chooses to write indifferent poetry instead of farming full time, he will then have to spend a large part of his initial endowment on a right that will bring him little financial benefit. This is indeed the slavery of the talented (1981, ; 2000, 90). 23 For those subscribing to welfarist theories of distributive justice, the slavery of the talented objection is of perverse interest because it seems to pose no problem at all for such theories. Welfarist egalitarians think that people should be equal in terms of welfare, whether understood in terms of (ideal) preference satisfaction or in terms of pleasant mental states. They do not require talented people to have less welfare than others as a result of spending their lives close to the commercially most profitable 513

14 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 manner. They might see no injustice in talented people working more hours than untalented people if, and to the extent that, this is compatible with equality of welfare. Such compatibility might be preserved if, for example, the kind of work talented people do is typically more rewarding than the kind of work untalented people do. However, this hardly qualifies as slavery. Hence, insofar as the slavery of the talented is a problem for egalitarian theories of justice, it is a problem for resource-egalitarian theories only. As a resource-egalitarian with real concerns about the slavery of the talented, Dworkin obviously needs to address this problem. He does so by excluding internal resources, e.g. labour, from the auction and the envy test. However, before I sketch Dworkin s response to the problem of the slavery of the talented more fully in the next section, I want to consider how the problem arises in an intergenerational context. Like most theorists of justice, Dworkin focuses on intragenerational issues and, thus, does not address the problem in an intergenerational setting. So let us consider what happens when one applies the envy test and the idea of an auction to a simple intergenerational setting. Imagine a hundred generations. They do not overlap: in an admittedly far-fetched biological progression, the members of one generation die at the very moment those of the next are born. For some reason there will only be one hundred generations. Suppose, moreover, that labour expended by one generation improves the situation of all ensuing generations in that it boosts the productivity-increase of all later generations. Hence, the labour of the first generations makes a difference to the value of all later generations, and in particular it makes a tremendous accumulated difference to the value of the labour of the last few generations. The labour of the last generation makes no difference to any other generation. Suppose, finally, that members of one generation can direct members of any generation, including previous ones, to employ their labour power in whatever way they see fit provided they own it. 24 So, by analogy to the intragenerational case, if I own the labour power of a member of a previous generation I can employ it in way that benefits me the most

15 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? In a case like this, the value of the labour of the first generation will be much higher than that of the later generations. Many members of later generations will want to bid for first-generational labour power, so members of the first generation will be obliged to use a lot of their bidding power simply to ensure that they have any leisure at all. Indeed, if coalitions of buyers from several generations are permitted, they might find that others completely outbid them in an auction for their time. If outbid, members of later generations will then employ the labour power of the first generation in a maximally productive way, thereby conferring maximum benefits on later generation. It is important to see that in this case the first generation is not talented in any ordinary sense of the word, but in the sense that employing its labour power results in much greater benefits for others (as a result of how this employment positively affects the productivity of all later generations) than the employment of, say, the labour power of the last generation (which has no effect on the productivity of any other generation). Its members could be less talented than those of later generations, and their labour has greater value than that of later generations simply because it is positioned at the start of the biological progression, where it is for convenience, let us say super-productive f. 26 It can be seen, then, that Dworkin s slavery of talented objection arises as a variant involving super-productivity f in the intergenerational setting. Accordingly, if that objection is effective against resource-egalitarian theories of intragenerational justice, obliging us to treat labour power and other resources differently, something similar would seem to follow in the case of resource-egalitarian theories of intergenerational justice. 27 V. WHY DWORKIN S RESPONSE TO THE SLAVERY OF THE TALENTED FAILS IN THE INTERGENERATIONAL CASE Having presented the challenge of the slavery of the talented objection in an intragenerational and intergenerational setting, I now describe 515

16 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 Dworkin s response to the problem in an intragenerational setting and then explain why this response fails in an intergenerational setting and, drawing on an objection by G. A. Cohen, explain why it does so in a way that also casts doubt on whether Dworkin s response works in the intragenerational setting. As I indicated above, Dworkin seeks to avoid the problem of the slavery of the talented by excluding labour from the auction and the envy test. At the auction he settles upon, one cannot bid for the labour power of others, and when one is determining whether some envy the resource bundles of others, one should disregard the labour power they command. By making this move, Dworkin s theory avoids the problem, as he diagnoses it, but it is also clear that he runs into another. Some people might simply be endowed with high-value labour power, and Dworkin is committed to the view that justice should be endowmentinsensitive. He thus needs some mechanism to address the inequality between those who are endowed with high-value labour power and those who are not. For that purpose, he proposes an insurance scheme in which people insure themselves against deficiencies in talents. In principle, such a scheme might lead to the same problematic results as Dworkin presumes will follow if we allow people to bid for each others labour power at the auction. However, in practice it will not, since people would be unwilling to insure themselves against not being among the most talented. Supposing they were willing to do this, they would have to pay a very large premium if they turned out to be among the very most talented, in which case they would, in effect, be talented slaves. 28 In the light of this response to the slavery of the talented, one might suppose that one can make a similar move in an account of intergenerational justice by subjecting the labour of the talented to an insurance scheme rather than the envy test and an auction. Unfortunately, it is not immediately apparent that Dworkin s insurance scheme can deal adequately with the intergenerational case. For whereas people in Dworkin s scheme would insure against not being sufficiently talented in the standard sense being untalented in this sense implies having fewer 516

17 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? marketable skills and, thus, being deprived of benefits one would otherwise have had they would not insure against not being super-productive f in the way the first generation is relative to later generations. The benefits of being super-productive f accrue to others, not to those who possess super-productivity f and, accordingly, not being super-productive f does not leave one worse off than one would otherwise have been and, thus, is not a situation one would want to insure against. Indeed, assuming people are ignorant of the generation to which they belong and wish to insure against belonging to some particular generation, they will insure against belonging to the first and poorest generation. At this point, some might object against the idea of insuring against being a member of the first generation that there is no way in which intergenerational compensation can be awarded in this case; but I do not think this is true. The compensation or at least, something relevantly like (self-) compensation might take the form of the first generation using a disproportionately large quantity of natural resources, leaving much less to ensuing generations than they would have done had they merely used their equal share. 29 In any case, and as already noted, I discuss the justice of distribution irrespective of the possibility of redistribution. This discussion of Dworkin s insurance device in an intergenerational setting reveals something important: that the insurance device is not essentially tied to the elimination of inequalities of resources. One insures to guarantee some kind of compensation in disadvantageous situations. In the familiar intragenerational setting, Dworkin assumes that being untalented is a disadvantage and that people gain from being talented; but in the intergenerational setting not being super-productive f (because one belongs to the last generation) is not a disadvantage the accumulative benefits that, ex hypothesis, result from exercising this talent accrue to members of later generations. However, if the quantity of resources one commands can diverge from the extent of the advantages that one takes into account when making up one s mind about the purchasing of insurance, equality of resources does not guarantee equality of the relevant kind of advantage

18 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 By way of further support for my claim that the insurance device is not a device for ensuring equality of resources, because whether one takes out an insurance against having a particular set of productive talents is not only determined by the level of resources one commands in virtue of these talents, consider Cohen and Dworkin s disagreement regarding the difference between welfarist and resourcist conceptions of egalitarian justice in connection with a rather different sort of case. To defeat Dworkin s purely resourcist view, Cohen imagines a person who is very good at controlling the movement of his limbs and very adept at moving them. So in an important dimension he is more resourceful than the rest of us. The problem is that he experiences pain whenever he moves his limbs. In Cohen s view, this person is worse off than the rest of us in a way that is relevant from the perspective of egalitarian justice. Since he does not have fewer resources than the rest of us he is very capable of moving his body and the experience of pain is not a resource, but merely something that affects his welfare, this shows, Cohen argues, that welfare is likewise relevant from the perspective of egalitarian justice. 31 The bearing of this dispute on Dworkinian auctions whether in an intragenerational or intergenerational setting can be readily appreciated if we imagine a situation in which talented people do not need to concentrate on what they are doing in order to exercise their talents. Suppose that there are great differences in people s talents and hence productivity, but that exercising one s talents in productive labour is a bit like driving on a deserted road in that it does not require one s attention: thus, for example, a talented brain surgeon can compose and even write down poems while performing surgery. Whether or not they attend to what they are doing, non-talented people cannot perform surgery, but the talented person can do it inattentively without loss of quality or speed in his or her work. The point here is that being at work does not prevent one from doing the things one likes or prioritizes. Hence, there is no reason for talented people, who put in many hours a day, to envy untalented people, who do not. Of course, talented people do not count as less talented for 518

19 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? this reason, or as people who do not command more internal resources than untalented people. Hence, the ground for envy in Dworkin s scenario cannot be that untalented people have more resources than talented ones if labour is put up for bidding at the auction. 32 I have proposed that the envy test registers welfare as well. VI. SLAVERY OF THE FIRST GENERATION: AN OBJECTION So far I have proceeded on the assumption that resource-egalitarian accounts of justice need to avoid productivity-sensitive enslavement. But this is not something that can simply be assumed. Thus, in connection with the intragenerational case some observers have argued that Dworkin fails to give convincing egalitarian reasons for thinking that talents and labour should not be auctioned. Miriam Cohen Christofidis pursues this line of argument. In her view, the situation of the talented in intragenerational auction is nothing like slavery in the literal sense (2004, 32). Admittedly, talented people might face a severely restricted choice. They may have to devote most of their purchasing power at the auction to ensuring that they control at least some part of their time. But it is not clear that they end up worse off than others in a sense that ought to trouble egalitarians. That would follow only if all that people cared about, in relation to their jobs, was the number of hours they worked the fewer, the better. However, people care about other things too, including how fulfilling their working lives are (Christofidis 2004, 36); and since, typically, the jobs of talented people are more fulfilling than those of untalented people, it may well be that hardworking talented people are not envied by much less hardworking untalented people. Can this line of argument be pressed into service to assuage worries about the slavery of the super-productive f? I do not think so. In real life there is every reason to believe that the further back we go in history the less fulfilling jobs were. Nor would it matter if this contingent, historical claim were incorrect. We can simply stipulate that in the case of 519

20 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 super-productivity f the jobs of the first generation are less fulfilling than later jobs without exception. The ideal of equality of resource should give the right answer in this hypothetical case as well. It does not. Christofidisstyle doubts about the slavery of the super-productive f cannot be marshalled at this point. Let me summarize the discussion of the two last sections. We have been concerned with resource-egalitarian accounts of distributive justice. Many believe that, in the intragenerational setting, these accounts have a problem avoiding the enslavement of the talented. If that is so, then, in the intergenerational setting specifically, in the far-fetched case involving one hundred generations we have described there is a similar problem with the slavery of the first generation, or as we have put it, the super-productive f. While the problem may be softened in the case of talented people, because they tend to have more fulfilling jobs, there is no analogous way of softening it in relation to the super-productive f. Moreover, it is not clear how Dworkin s insurance scheme can be applied in an intergenerational setting. In fact, insurance seems to be problematic in both intragenerational and intergenerational settings. I conclude that the slavery of the first generation, or the super-productive f, constitutes an important challenge to Dworkin s resourcist position. VII. CONCLUSION I have argued that two objections to welfarist accounts of the metric of (intergenerational) justice, one from expensive tastes and the other from the engineering of preferences, are unsuccessful. I have also presented reasons for thinking that Dworkin s resourcist metric is incapable of handling a variant of the slavery of the talented what I have called the slavery of the first generation, or of super-productivity f convincingly

21 KASPER LIPPERT-RASMUSSEN EQUALITY OF WHAT? WORKS CITED Arneson, Richard Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare. Philosophical Studies 56: Arneson, Richard Liberalism, Distributive Subjectivism, and Equal Opportunity for Welfare. Philosophy & Public Affairs 19/2: Arneson, Richard Welfare Should Be the Currency of Justice. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30/4: Cohen, G. A On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics 99: (reprinted in Cohen 2010, 3-43). Cohen, G. A Expensive Tastes Ride Again. In Dworkin and His Critics. Edited by Justine Burley, Oxford: Blackwell. Cohen, G. A Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Cohen, G. A On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Cohen Christofidis, Miriam Talent, Slavery, and Envy. In Dworkin and His Critics. Edited by Justine Burley, Oxford: Blackwell. Dworkin, Ronald. 1981a. What is Equality? Part I: Equality of Welfare. Philosophy & Public Affairs 10: (reprinted in Dworkin 2000, 11-64). Dworkin, Ronald. 1981b. What is Equality? Part I: Equality of Resources. Philosophy & Public Affairs 10: (reprinted in Dworkin 2000, ). Dworkin, Ronald Sovereign Virtue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dworkin, Ronald Replies. In Dworkin and His Critics. Edited by Justine Burley, Oxford: Blackwell. Elster, Jon Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hansen, Rasmus Sommer and Søren Flinch Midtgaard Sinking Cohen s Flagship or Why People with Expensive Tastes Should Not Be Compensated. Journal of Applied Philosophy 28: Keller, Simon Expensive Tastes and Distributive Justice. Social Theory and Practice 28: Knight, Carl Egalitarian Justice and Valuational Judgment. Journal of Moral Philosophy 6: McMahan, Jeff The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Page, Edward Intergenerational Justice of What: Welfare, Resources or Capabilities? Environmental Politics 16: Rawls, John Social Unity and Primary Goods. In Utilitarianism and Beyond. Edited by Bernard Williams and Amartya Sen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Scanlon, Thomas M Preference and Urgency. Journal of Philosophy 72:

22 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES SEPTEMBER 2012 Schaller, Walter E Expensive Preferences and the Priority of Right: A Critique of Welfare-Egalitarianism. Journal of Political Philosophy 5: Sumner, L. Wayne Happiness, Welfare, and Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon. Vrousalis, Nicholas. Meeting Posterity s Needs: Flourishing, Sustainability, and the Metrics Question. Forthcoming. NOTES 1. An exception is Page (2007). 2. If they did, might not the metric of life-time equality similarly differ from the metric of time-slice equality? And might not the relevant metric for comparing G n with G n+1 differ from the relevant metric for comparing G n+2 with G n+3? 3. Ultimately, I am not certain that welfare is the metric of justice. The intrinsic preferences people have for states of affairs other than those that involve their self-interest may count as well from the point of view of egalitarian justice. In a world in which people have only other-regarding preferences for species of non-human animals, it might be unjust if some people s preferences in favour of penguins welfare are satisfied, while other people s preferences in favour of pigs welfare are unsatisfied. I do not address this issue elsewhere in this paper. 4. I assume that an unjust distribution can arise even if everyone acts in the best way possible to promote justice. Hence, I depart from a Dworkinian statist view, according to which justice is primarily concerned with whether the state treats its citizens with equal concern and respect. I believe this view is too narrow anyway (e.g. it does not allow us to ask questions about international distributive justice). 5. Dworkin (2000, 48-59) presses a similar objection to equality of welfare. 6. While my argument does not rest on an empirical claim to the effect that later generations tend to have more expensive preferences than earlier ones, the well-known mechanism of adaptive preferences (Elster 1983, ) supports this claim, given economic growth. 7. Even if the preference represents an objectionable stance, it remains unclear that egalitarians will not want to accommodate it. Similarly, a preference that one has less satisfaction than others is an anti-egalitarian preference. It would, ironically, qualify as an expensive preference if it is expensive to (reliably) satisfy, say, because comparisons of levels of satisfaction are very costly. 8. A hyper-egalitarian preference is one that is informed by the desire to have no greater satisfaction, or not to consume more expensive goods, than others. 9. According to Cohen s view of the normative significance of expensive tastes, this concept of expensive tastes might be normatively more relevant than the concept Dworkin defines. 10. Dworkin thinks otherwise. For him identification rather than choice is of the essence (cf. Scanlon [1975] on pilgrimage and compensation). 11. Normally, expensive preferences are discussed in relation to cases in which it is the bearer of the preference who can cultivate it or refrain from so doing. 12. Cohen does not say what kind of valuational judgment he has in mind: prudential value judgments or just any kind of value judgment, e.g. a judgment to the effect that although the 522

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.).

S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: (hbk.). S.L. Hurley, Justice, Luck and Knowledge, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 341 pages. ISBN: 0-674-01029-9 (hbk.). In this impressive, tightly argued, but not altogether successful book,

More information

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism?

Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Western University Scholarship@Western 2014 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2014 Is Rawls s Difference Principle Preferable to Luck Egalitarianism? Taylor C. Rodrigues Western University,

More information

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy

Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Rawls versus the Anarchist: Justice and Legitimacy Walter E. Schaller Texas Tech University APA Central Division April 2005 Section 1: The Anarchist s Argument In a recent article, Justification and Legitimacy,

More information

1100 Ethics July 2016

1100 Ethics July 2016 1100 Ethics July 2016 perhaps, those recommended by Brock. His insight that this creates an irresolvable moral tragedy, given current global economic circumstances, is apt. Blake does not ask, however,

More information

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p.

Definition: Institution public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers and immunities p. RAWLS Project: to interpret the initial situation, formulate principles of choice, and then establish which principles should be adopted. The principles of justice provide an assignment of fundamental

More information

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle

What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-018-00053-5 What Is Unfair about Unequal Brute Luck? An Intergenerational Puzzle Simon Beard 1 Received: 16 November 2017 /Revised: 29 May 2018 /Accepted: 27 December 2018

More information

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement:

Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Views of Rawls s achievement: 1 Philosophy 285 Fall, 2007 Dick Arneson Overview of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice Views of Rawls s achievement: G. A. Cohen: I believe that at most two books in the history of Western political philosophy

More information

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE

John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE John Rawls THEORY OF JUSTICE THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised

More information

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of

When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 1: Introduction. Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of When Does Equality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Lecture 1: Introduction Our country, and the world, are marked by extraordinarily high levels of inequality. This inequality raises important empirical questions,

More information

When bad things happen to good people: luck egalitarianism and costly rescues

When bad things happen to good people: luck egalitarianism and costly rescues When bad things happen to good people: luck egalitarianism and costly rescues Jens Damgaard Thaysen and Andreas Albertsen, Department of Political Science, Aarhus BSS, Aarhus University aba@ps.au.dk This

More information

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as. free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his theory of justice, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair cooperation among persons thus

More information

Equality of Resources. In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of

Equality of Resources. In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of Justice, Fall 2002, 1 Equality of Resources 1. Why Equality? In discussing libertarianism, I distinguished two kinds of criticisms of programs of law and public policy that aim to address inequalities

More information

WHAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this

WHAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 19, Number 1, 2011, pp. 64 89 Symposium: Ownership and Self-ownership Left-Libertarianism: Rawlsian Not Luck Egalitarian Jonathan Quong Politics, University

More information

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness.

RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS. John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. RECONCILING LIBERTY AND EQUALITY: JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS 1. Two Principles of Justice John Rawls s A Theory of Justice presents a theory called justice as fairness. That theory comprises two principles of

More information

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism?

The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism. Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism? The Value of Equality and Egalitarianism Lecture 3 Why not luck egalitarianism? The plan for today 1. Luck and equality 2. Bad option luck 3. Bad brute luck 4. Democratic equality 1. Luck and equality

More information

Luck Egalitarianism and Democratic Equality

Luck Egalitarianism and Democratic Equality Luck Egalitarianism and Democratic Equality Kevin Michael Klipfel Thesis submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for

More information

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE

CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE CONTEXTUALISM AND GLOBAL JUSTICE 1. Introduction There are two sets of questions that have featured prominently in recent debates about distributive justice. One of these debates is that between universalism

More information

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a

In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a Justice, Fall 2003 Feminism and Multiculturalism 1. Equality: Form and Substance In his account of justice as fairness, Rawls argues that treating the members of a society as free and equal achieving fair

More information

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled

A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled Volume 9 Issue 1 Philosophy of Disability Article 5 1-2008 A Rawlsian Perspective on Justice for the Disabled Adam Cureton University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Follow this and additional works at:

More information

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism

Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism Global Justice and Two Kinds of Liberalism Christopher Lowry Dept. of Philosophy, Queen s University christopher.r.lowry@gmail.com Paper prepared for CPSA, June 2008 In a recent article, Nagel (2005) distinguishes

More information

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_

Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_ , 223 227 Controversy Liberalism, Democracy and the Ethics of Votingponl_1359 223..227 Annabelle Lever London School of Economics This article summarises objections to compulsory voting developed in my

More information

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice-

-Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- UPF - MA Political Philosophy Modern Political Philosophy Elisabet Puigdollers Mas -Capitalism, Exploitation and Injustice- Introduction Although Marx fiercely criticized the theories of justice and some

More information

Is Dworkin a luck egalitarian? Matr

Is Dworkin a luck egalitarian? Matr Dipartimento di Scienze politiche Cattedra di Filosofia politica Is Dworkin a luck egalitarian? RELATORE Prof. Sebastiano Maffettone CANDIDATO Miryam Magro Matr.068902 ANNO ACCADEMICO 2013/2014 Contents

More information

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of The limits of background justice Thomas Porter Rawls says that the primary subject of justice is what he calls the basic structure of society. The basic structure is, roughly speaking, the way in which

More information

Two Models of Equality and Responsibility

Two Models of Equality and Responsibility Two Models of Equality and Responsibility The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Published Version Accessed

More information

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1

AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 AN EGALITARIAN THEORY OF JUSTICE 1 John Rawls THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be

More information

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality

Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality 24.231 Ethics Handout 18 Rawls, Classical Utilitarianism and Nagel, Equality The Utilitarian Principle of Distribution: Society is rightly ordered, and therefore just, when its major institutions are arranged

More information

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged

Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain Annual Conference New College, Oxford 1-3 April 2016 Between Equality and Freedom of Choice: Educational Policy for the Least Advantaged Mr Nico Brando

More information

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY

DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY The Philosophical Quarterly 2007 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.495.x DEMOCRACY AND EQUALITY BY STEVEN WALL Many writers claim that democratic government rests on a principled commitment

More information

Princeton University Press

Princeton University Press Princeton University Press Justice: Means versus Freedoms Author(s): Amartya Sen Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 19, No. 2 (Spring, 1990), pp. 111-121 Published by: Blackwell

More information

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction

Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Introduction to Equality and Justice: The Demands of Equality, Peter Vallentyne, ed., Routledge, 2003. The Demands of Equality: An Introduction Peter Vallentyne This is the second volume of Equality and

More information

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press

The limits of background justice. Thomas Porter. Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2. Cambridge University Press The limits of background justice Thomas Porter Social Philosophy & Policy volume 30, issues 1 2 Cambridge University Press Abstract The argument from background justice is that conformity to Lockean principles

More information

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY

RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY RAWLS DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE: ABSOLUTE vs. RELATIVE INEQUALITY Geoff Briggs PHIL 350/400 // Dr. Ryan Wasserman Spring 2014 June 9 th, 2014 {Word Count: 2711} [1 of 12] {This page intentionally left blank

More information

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG

POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG SYMPOSIUM POLITICAL LIBERALISM VS. LIBERAL PERFECTIONISM POLITICAL AUTHORITY AND PERFECTIONISM: A RESPONSE TO QUONG JOSEPH CHAN 2012 Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Vol. 2, No. 1 (2012): pp.

More information

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

On Original Appropriation. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia On Original Appropriation Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia in Malcolm Murray, ed., Liberty, Games and Contracts: Jan Narveson and the Defence of Libertarianism (Aldershot: Ashgate Press,

More information

Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia

Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia Capabilities vs. Opportunities for Well-being Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri-Columbia Short Introduction for reprint in Capabilities, edited by Alexander Kaufman: Distributive justice is concerned

More information

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Libertarianism. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION Libertarianism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe L ibertarianism is a moral, social, and political doctrine that considers the liberty of individual citizens the absence of external restraint and coercion

More information

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production

24.03: Good Food 3/13/17. Justice and Food Production 1. Food Sovereignty, again Justice and Food Production Before when we talked about food sovereignty (Kyle Powys Whyte reading), the main issue was the protection of a way of life, a culture. In the Thompson

More information

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism

Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism Phil 115, May 24, 2007 The threat of utilitarianism Review: Alchemy v. System According to the alchemy interpretation, Rawls s project is to convince everyone, on the basis of assumptions that he expects

More information

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison

Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory. Jaime Ahlberg. University of Wisconsin Madison Educational Adequacy, Educational Equality, and Ideal Theory Jaime Ahlberg University of Wisconsin Madison Department of Philosophy University of Wisconsin - Madison 5185 Helen C. White Hall 600 North

More information

Do we have a strong case for open borders?

Do we have a strong case for open borders? Do we have a strong case for open borders? Joseph Carens [1987] challenges the popular view that admission of immigrants by states is only a matter of generosity and not of obligation. He claims that the

More information

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information

Cambridge University Press The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Edited by Jon Mandle and David A. Reidy Excerpt More information A in this web service in this web service 1. ABORTION Amuch discussed footnote to the first edition of Political Liberalism takes up the troubled question of abortion in order to illustrate how norms of

More information

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global

An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global BOOK SYMPOSIUM: ON GLOBAL JUSTICE On Collective Ownership of the Earth Anna Stilz An appealing and original aspect of Mathias Risse s book On Global Justice is his argument for humanity s collective ownership

More information

NORMATIVITY, EQUAL ACCESS TO BIOTECHNOLOGIES, AND ANTI- PERFECTIONISM

NORMATIVITY, EQUAL ACCESS TO BIOTECHNOLOGIES, AND ANTI- PERFECTIONISM 383 Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 3, pp. 383-395 NORMATIVITY, EQUAL ACCESS TO BIOTECHNOLOGIES, AND ANTI- PERFECTIONISM ANDRES MOLES Departments of Political Science and Philosophy

More information

Reply to Arneson. Russel Keat. 1. The (Supposed) Non Sequitur

Reply to Arneson. Russel Keat. 1. The (Supposed) Non Sequitur Analyse & Kritik 01/2009 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 153157 Russel Keat Reply to Arneson Abstract: Arneson says that he disagrees both with the main claims of Arneson (1987) and with my criticisms

More information

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan*

Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* 219 Two Pictures of the Global-justice Debate: A Reply to Tan* Laura Valentini London School of Economics and Political Science 1. Introduction Kok-Chor Tan s review essay offers an internal critique of

More information

Property and Progress

Property and Progress Property and Progress Gordon Barnes State University of New York, Brockport 1. Introduction In a series of articles published since 1990, David Schmidtz has argued that the institution of property plays

More information

Democracy As Equality

Democracy As Equality 1 Democracy As Equality Thomas Christiano Society is organized by terms of association by which all are bound. The problem is to determine who has the right to define these terms of association. Democrats

More information

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things

Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate things Self-Ownership Type of Ethics:??? Date: mainly 1600s to present Associated With: John Locke, libertarianism, liberalism Definition: Property rights in oneself comparable to property rights in inanimate

More information

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the

Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Nozick s Entitlement Theory of Justice: A Response to the Objection of Arbitrariness Though several factors contributed to the eventual conclusion of the Cold War, one of the

More information

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views

The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views The Provision of Public Goods, and the Matter of the Revelation of True Preferences: Two Views Larry Levine Department of Economics, University of New Brunswick Introduction The two views which are agenda

More information

Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment

Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment Serene J. Khader, Adaptive Preferences and Women's Empowerment, Oxford University Press, 2011, 238pp., $24.95 (pbk), ISBN 9780199777877. Reviewed byann E. Cudd,

More information

LECTURE NOTES PHILOSOPHY 167 DWORKIN AND CRITICS

LECTURE NOTES PHILOSOPHY 167 DWORKIN AND CRITICS 1 LECTURE NOTES PHILOSOPHY 167 DWORKIN AND CRITICS 1. A taxonomy of views. What do we owe one another? One view is that we should always respect everyone's Lockean rights. (One respects a right by not

More information

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY

Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Facts and Principles in Political Constructivism Michael Buckley Lehman College, CUNY Abstract: This paper develops a unique exposition about the relationship between facts and principles in political

More information

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE Vol.I - Economic Justice - Hon-Lam Li ECONOMIC JUSTICE Hon-Lam Li Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong Keywords: Analytical Marxism, capitalism, communism, complex equality, democratic socialism, difference principle, equality, exploitation,

More information

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007

Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007 Notes from discussion in Erik Olin Wright Lecture #2: Diagnosis & Critique Middle East Technical University Tuesday, November 13, 2007 Question: In your conception of social justice, does exploitation

More information

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35

Normative Frameworks 1 / 35 Normative Frameworks 1 / 35 Goals of this part of the course What are the goals of public policy? What do we mean by good public policy? Three approaches 1. Philosophical: Normative political theory 2.

More information

Resources versus Capabilities: Social Endowments in Egalitarian Theory

Resources versus Capabilities: Social Endowments in Egalitarian Theory Resources versus Capabilities: Social Endowments in Egalitarian Theory Roland Pierik and Ingrid Robeyns Radboud University Nijmegen POLITICAL STUDIES: 2007 VOL 55, 133 152 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9248.2007.00646.x

More information

VI. Rawls and Equality

VI. Rawls and Equality VI. Rawls and Equality A society of free and equal persons Last time, on Justice: Getting What We Are Due 1 Redistributive Taxation Redux Can we justly tax Wilt Chamberlain to redistribute wealth to others?

More information

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy

Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy 1 Paper to be presented at the symposium on Democracy and Authority by David Estlund in Oslo, December 7-9 2009 (Draft) Proceduralism and Epistemic Value of Democracy Some reflections and questions on

More information

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW

Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI /s ARIE ROSEN BOOK REVIEW Law and Philosophy (2015) 34: 699 708 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 DOI 10.1007/s10982-015-9239-8 ARIE ROSEN (Accepted 31 August 2015) Alon Harel, Why Law Matters. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice

Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Politics (2000) 20(1) pp. 19 24 Incentives and the Natural Duties of Justice Colin Farrelly 1 In this paper I explore a possible response to G.A. Cohen s critique of the Rawlsian defence of inequality-generating

More information

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3

Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3 Phil 290, February 8, 2011 Christiano, The Constitution of Equality, Ch. 2 3 A common world is a set of circumstances in which the fulfillment of all or nearly all of the fundamental interests of each

More information

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality

Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality Richard W. Miller Spring 2011 Social and Political Philosophy Philosophy 4470/6430, Government 4655/6656 (Thursdays, 2:30-4:25, Goldwin Smith 348) Topic for Spring 2011: Equality What role should the reduction

More information

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction

Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction Part III Immigration Policy: Introduction Despite the huge and obvious income differences across countries and the natural desire for people to improve their lives, nearly all people in the world continue

More information

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition

John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition From the SelectedWorks of Greg Hill 2010 John Rawls's Difference Principle and The Strains of Commitment: A Diagrammatic Exposition Greg Hill Available at: https://works.bepress.com/greg_hill/3/ The Difference

More information

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization"

RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization RESPONSE TO JAMES GORDLEY'S "GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT LAW: The Problem of Profit Maximization" By MICHAEL AMBROSIO We have been given a wonderful example by Professor Gordley of a cogent, yet straightforward

More information

Self-Ownership and Equality: Brute Luck, Gifts, Universal Dominance, and Leximin* Peter Vallentyne (April 6, 2013)

Self-Ownership and Equality: Brute Luck, Gifts, Universal Dominance, and Leximin* Peter Vallentyne (April 6, 2013) Self-Ownership and Equality: Brute Luck, Gifts, Universal Dominance, and Leximin* Peter Vallentyne (April 6, 2013) 1. Introduction During the last twenty years or so egalitarian political theorists have

More information

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the

Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon. Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes. It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the Why Does Inequality Matter? T. M. Scanlon Chapter 8: Unequal Outcomes It is well known that there has been an enormous increase in inequality in the United States and other developed economies in recent

More information

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism

New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism New Directions for the Capability Approach: Deliberative Democracy and Republicanism Rutger Claassen Published in: Res Publica 15(4)(2009): 421-428 Review essay on: John. M. Alexander, Capabilities and

More information

Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy I

Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy I Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy Joshua Cohen In this essay I explore the ideal of a 'deliberative democracy'.1 By a deliberative democracy I shall mean, roughly, an association whose affairs are

More information

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility

Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility Phil 115, June 13, 2007 The argument from the original position: set-up and intuitive presentation and the two principles over average utility What is the role of the original position in Rawls s theory?

More information

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice

Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Commentary on Idil Boran, The Problem of Exogeneity in Debates on Global Justice Bryan Smyth, University of Memphis 2011 APA Central Division Meeting // Session V-I: Global Justice // 2. April 2011 I am

More information

Equality: The Recent History of an Idea 1

Equality: The Recent History of an Idea 1 Wolff, J; (2007) Equality: The recent history of an idea. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (1) 125-136. 10.1177/1740468107077389 ARTICLE Equality: The Recent History of an Idea 1 Jonathan Wolff Pre-Nozickian

More information

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon

The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon PHILIP PETTIT The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon In The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy, Christopher McMahon challenges my claim that the republican goal of promoting or maximizing

More information

Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners

Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners Co-national Obligations & Cosmopolitan Obligations towards Foreigners Ambrose Y. K. Lee (The definitive version is available at www.wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/ponl) This paper targets a very specific

More information

Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will

Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will Priority or Equality for Possible People? Alex Voorhoeve and Marc Fleurbaey Suppose that you must make choices that may influence the well-being and the identities of the people who will exist, though

More information

A Response to Tan. Christian Schemmel. University of Frankfurt; Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy

A Response to Tan. Christian Schemmel. University of Frankfurt; Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy LUCK EGALITARIANISM AS DEMOCRATIC RECIPROCITY? A Response to Tan Christian Schemmel University of Frankfurt; schemmel@soz.uni-frankfurt.de Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy Introduction Kok-Chor

More information

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions

1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions Date:15/7/15 Time:00:43:55 Page Number: 18 1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions David O. Brink It would be hard to overstate the philosophical significance of John Rawls s TJ. 1

More information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Rawls's Egalitarianism Alexander Kaufman Excerpt More Information Introduction This study focuses on John Rawls s complex understanding of egalitarian justice. Rawls addresses this subject both in A Theory of Justice andinmanyofhisarticlespublishedbetween1951and1982.inthese

More information

Penalizing Public Disobedience*

Penalizing Public Disobedience* DISCUSSION Penalizing Public Disobedience* Kimberley Brownlee I In a recent article, David Lefkowitz argues that members of liberal democracies have a moral right to engage in acts of suitably constrained

More information

Playing Fair and Following the Rules

Playing Fair and Following the Rules JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY brill.com/jmp Playing Fair and Following the Rules Justin Tosi Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan jtosi@umich.edu Abstract In his paper Fairness, Political Obligation,

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Justice, Fairness, and World Ownership Author(s): Cecile Fabre Source: Law and Philosophy, Vol. 21, No. 3 (May, 2002), pp. 249-273 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3505205

More information

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017

What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017 What is Fairness? Allan Drazen Sandridge Lecture Virginia Association of Economists March 16, 2017 Everyone Wants Things To Be Fair I want to live in a society that's fair. Barack Obama All I want him

More information

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War

Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory 121 126 Jus in Bello through the Lens of Individual Moral Responsibility: McMahan on Killing in War David Lefkowitz * A review of Jeff McMahan, Killing in War (Oxford

More information

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the

Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1. (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the Equality, Justice and Legitimacy in Selection 1 (This is the pre-proof draft of the article, which was published in the Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9 (2012), 8-30. Matthew Clayton University of Warwick

More information

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness

The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 5-8-2009 The Proper Metric of Justice in Justice as Fairness Charles Benjamin Carmichael Follow

More information

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts)

Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical (Excerpts) primarysourcedocument Justice As Fairness: Political, Not Metaphysical, Excerpts John Rawls 1985 [Rawls, John. Justice As Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14, no. 3.

More information

Knight, C. (2013) Luck egalitarianism. Philosophy Compass, 8(10), pp

Knight, C. (2013) Luck egalitarianism. Philosophy Compass, 8(10), pp Knight, C. (2013) Luck egalitarianism. Philosophy Compass, 8(10), pp. 924-934. Copyright 2013 The Author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission

More information

Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried

Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried PETER VALLENTYNE, HILLEL STEINER, AND MICHAEL OTSUKA Why Left-Libertarianism Is Not Incoherent, Indeterminate, or Irrelevant: A Reply to Fried Over the past few decades, there has been increasing interest

More information

Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 10, No. 4. (Autumn, 1981), pp

Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 10, No. 4. (Autumn, 1981), pp What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources Ronald Dworkin Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 10, No. 4. (Autumn, 1981), pp. 283-345. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0048-3915%28198123%2910%3a4%3c283%3awiep2e%3e2.0.co%3b2-3

More information

DEFENDING LUCK EGALITARIANISM. Nicholas Barry. This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The University of Western Australia.

DEFENDING LUCK EGALITARIANISM. Nicholas Barry. This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The University of Western Australia. DEFENDING LUCK EGALITARIANISM Nicholas Barry This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of The University of Western Australia. School of Social and Cultural Studies Political Science

More information

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy

Politics between Philosophy and Democracy Leopold Hess Politics between Philosophy and Democracy In the present paper I would like to make some comments on a classic essay of Michael Walzer Philosophy and Democracy. The main purpose of Walzer

More information

Complementarity of Resource and Capability: Economic. Philosophical Discussions about Distribution Rule in Global

Complementarity of Resource and Capability: Economic. Philosophical Discussions about Distribution Rule in Global Complementarity of Resource and Capability: Economic Philosophical Discussions about Distribution Rule in Global Justice Shinji MURAKAMI* *The Health Care Science Institute Research Fellow, Tokyo, Japan

More information

Poverty--absolute and relative Inequalities of income and wealth

Poverty--absolute and relative Inequalities of income and wealth Development Ethics The task: provide a normative basis for guiding development decisions Development as a historical process Development as the result of policy choices A role for ethics Normative issues

More information

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED

LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED LEGAL POSITIVISM AND NATURAL LAW RECONSIDERED David Brink Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER David Brink examines the views of legal positivism and natural law theory

More information

Social Contract Theory

Social Contract Theory Social Contract Theory Social Contract Theory (SCT) Originally proposed as an account of political authority (i.e., essentially, whether and why we have a moral obligation to obey the law) by political

More information

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent?

Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent? Chapter 1 Is the Ideal of a Deliberative Democracy Coherent? Cristina Lafont Introduction In what follows, I would like to contribute to a defense of deliberative democracy by giving an affirmative answer

More information

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for

VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER. A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy. in conformity with the requirements for VALUING DISTRIBUTIVE EQUALITY by CLAIRE ANITA BREMNER A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen s University Kingston,

More information

Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1. T. M. Scanlon

Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1. T. M. Scanlon Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy 1 T. M. Scanlon Equality of opportunity is widely agreed to be important, but surprisingly little is said about why this should be so. In this lecture I will

More information