Safe Votes, Sincere Votes, and Strategizing

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Safe Votes, Sincere Votes, and Strategizing"

Transcription

1 Safe Votes, Sincere Votes, and Strategizing Rohit Parikh Eric Pacuit April 7, 2005 Abstract: We examine the basic notion of strategizing in the statement of the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem and note that to talk about strategizing presumes that we already know what it means to vote sincerely. For a strategic vote is one which differs from a sincere vote, taking into account how others are voting. Now the notion of a sincere vote is clear enough in most commonly used voting systems (which we identify with the aggregation function Ag) but there is no general notion of sincerity. It follows that there cannot be a general notion of stratagizing either. In this paper we define a notion of safe vote and study its properties. Safe votes exist with plurality, approval voting and the Borda count, but not with STV The Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem 1 says that under certain circumstances, strategizing is unavoidable. In other words, sometimes a voter is better off voting something different from his/her true preference. An example might be the election of 2000 when certain voters whose top preference was Nader voted for their second preference Gore instead. Indeed, if most or all Nader voters had voted strategically in this sense, voting for their second preference, then some of them would have voted for Bush, but most for Gore and Gore would have become president. Talking this way assumes that we know what it means to vote sincerely. For Both authors are at the City University of New York. We thank Eva Antonakos, Steven Brams, John Crossley, Ron van der Meyden and Remzi Sanver for comments. The research of both authors was supported by a grant from the CUNY Research Foundation. The addresses are: rparikh@gc.cuny.edu epacuit@cs.gc.cuny.edu 1 Please see the appendix following the references. 1

2 unless we can define sincerity in some convincing sense, it makes no sense to talk of strategizing either. After all, if we think of an election as a game, then naturally each player will play her best strategy, using whatever information she has, and there need be no charge of insincerity. So how do we define sincerity in voting? Now if we have an aggregation function Ag which takes in the entire preference profile of all voters and returns a winner (breaking ties somehow) then it would seem that sincerity consists in each voter submitting his actual preference order as his vote. But is this really so obvious? Suppose for instance that Ag takes the bottom element of each ordering submitted and then declares as winner the candidate who is at the bottom of most orders submitted. Moreover, this property of Ag is common knowledge. Then surely the voters are likely to submit the reverse of their preference order as their vote and one might argue that the reverse of the preference order is in fact the sincere vote. Strategizing might then consist in not submitting the reverse of one s actual preference order. So there is some room for a discussion of what sincerity might be in a general context. Now in the example we just looked at, we could think of Ag as a function Ag, which first reverses all the orders submitted and then applies Ag. So Ag would count the tops of all orderings submitted and for Ag, it would be best to submit one s actual preference rather than its reverse. Thus in that case a reverse vote for Ag would be a conventionally sincere non-reversed vote for Ag and all would be well. But would it? After all, Ag and Ag are special in that they require actual orders as inputs and most ballots ask for much less. If Ag takes in as its input some sort of a ballot profile and returns a winner, then it is not obvious what the sincere ballot should be given a particular preference that a voter has. We illustrate this by an example. Let us suppose that there are 34 voters and 3 candidates A,B,C, of whom C is the incumbent. Voters may vote for one of A, B, who are new, or vote 2

3 against C if they feel his performance has been less than adequate 2. But only one of A, B, C, can be mentioned on the voter s ballot. Thus each voter names a name, one of A,B,C, and Ag looks at the three numbers, n = the number of times A is mentioned, m = the number of times B is mentioned, and p = 18 the number of times C is mentioned. The winner is A if n is largest, B if m is largest, and C if p is largest, i.e. if C received few negative votes compared to A and B s positive votes. Now what does sincerity mean in this context? Since it is no longer clear what sincerity means in a general context, we shall use the word safe defined precisely below. Safety is a clear, mathematically defined notion which applies generally, and coincides with sincerity when the latter makes sense. Definition 1 Given the aggregation function Ag, and a preference order P, a P -safe ballot by a voter v will be a ballot b such that regardless of how the others are voting, the voter is at least as well off voting b than not voting at all, and is strictly better off at least once. In other words, a safe vote dominates not voting. The aggregation function Ag is safe if it has a safe vote for each preference order P Note that if the aggregation function Ag takes in preference orders themselves as ballots, and is moreover invariant under permutations of candidates, then Ag is safe iff it has a P -safe ballot for some P. A safe vote respects the idea that an election is not a game but an expression of opinion. Since a safe vote allows a voter to do better than not voting, regardless of how others vote, it is not game theoretic, but rather communicative. Now going back to our example, if a voter prefers A (B), surely the safe vote is to vote for A (B). What if the voter prefers C? Clearly the voter cannot be asked to write in C s name in the name of sincerity as this will count against 2 The California election where Gray Davis was recalled and Arnold Schwarzenegger was elected was one where in fact the incumbent was treated differently from the other candidates. 3

4 C. It looks as if the voter should vote for one of A or B, but we will soon show that in fact there is no safe vote in this setting. Note that in some particular profile of other votes, another ballot b can be better than a safe ballot b - that is what strategizing means. But if b is not safe, then at least once, b will be worse than not voting, and b is of course at least as good as not voting. So b can never dominate b - it can only be better than b some of the time. Theorem 2 If Ag is the plurality function then the only safe vote is a vote for one s top candidate. Proof: to see that a vote for one s top candidate is safe, suppose there are k candidates, {1,..., k} and candidate 1 is some voter v s favourite. Suppose that without v s vote the votes for the candidates would be n 1,..., n k. If v votes for 1, the votes would be n 1 + 1, n 2,..., n k, and clearly 1 s chances of winning will improve. To see that this is the only safe vote, let us assume that ties are broken in favour of earlier numbered candidates. Suppose, now, that in the same context, v were to vote for some other candidate, say 2. It is then possible that n 1 = n 2 > n i for i > 2. 1 would win by the tie breaking rule. But now, after v votes for 2, n 1 < n 2 +1 and 2 will win. So in this situation v would have been better off not voting rather than voting for 2. In short, voting for 1 was the only vote which was guaranteed to be as good as or better than not voting. Remark: Naturally when one candidate s score changes by 1 point, then this situation may create a tie where there was none, or destroy one when there was one to start with. Without going into details of tie-breaking rules, we will assume that regardless of the actual rule, for any two candidates A, B, there is some situation where an increase in A s score by 1 point makes A the winner whereas without that increase, B would have been the winner. For instance if the tie breaking rule is that in case of a tie A wins, being alphabetically earlier, then a situation where A has exactly one vote less than B can be converted into one where A and B have the same scores and A wins. Whereas if the tie was supposed to be broken in B s favour, then a situation where A and B have the same score (and B winning) could be converted into 4

5 one where A wins, simply by A getting one more vote. Fishburn and Brams use a married couple (who can change a candidate s score by two) in their example described below to bypass this issue of tie-breaking. But in 1983, when [FB83] was written there still were married couples who voted the same way, so they had access to a device which we shall refrain from using. Theorem 3 If Ag is approval voting, then a safe vote is one where the voter v approves of one candidate x and all higher ranking y in v s preference ordering. Proof: Suppose that there are k candidates and assume for simplicity that v actually prefers them in the order k. Suppose that without v s vote they would have n 1,..., n k approvals respectively. Let m be the candidate who would be elected without v s vote, and suppose that v does vote, approving of candidates 1,..., r, with no gaps. Suppose moreover that v would have been better off not voting. Then it must be that after v s vote some candidate p > m, less preferred by the voter, is now elected. This means that p received an extra vote and m did not, so p r and m > r. But this is impossible given that p > m. Thus all gapless ballots are safe. Conversely, suppose that v votes with a gap, so that v votes for some candidate r but not for candidate numbered r 1. Now it could have been before v s vote that r 1 was doing as well as or better than r, but that after getting one extra point, r does better and gets elected. So v would have been better off not voting. The gap-ful strategy is not safe. In brief, the only strategies which are safe, i.e., dominate not voting are the gapless strategies, where v votes for some set 1,..., r with r < k. Theorem 4 For the Borda count procedure, sincere ballots are exactly the safe ballots. I.e., P is always P -safe. Proof Suppose (again for simplicity) that voter v s preferences are k. Suppose that without v s ballot the scores would have been 5

6 n 1,..., n k and v harms herself by voting honestly. Now with v s vote, the scores would now be n 1 + k 1,..., n i + (k i),..., n k. Since v did worse by voting, it must be that some i was elected before v s vote and some j > i is now elected. There are two kinds of tie-breaking possibilities and we consider just one. Suppose that i was leading before and j is at least even with i after v s vote. So we get, i < j, n i > n j and n i + (k i) n j + (k j). But then n i i n j j and hence n i + j n j + i which is impossible. That (for the typical systems) insincere votes can be worse than not voting, and therefore cannot be safe, is something on which we have already remarked and we skip the (easy) proof for this case. Example: Consider the following situation. There are two candidates and Ag requires as input an order among them. Ag then counts the number of times each candidate occurs at the bottom of the orders. The candidate who occurs more often is the one chosen by Ag. Note that in this case there is always a safe vote, namely to submit the reverse of one s preference order, and if one is so inclined, one could call that an insincere safe vote. So if we are not considering Plurality, Approval voting, or Borda count, then there can be safety without sincerity. Theorem 5 If Ag is the unconventional function we defined above then (i) for a voter who prefers A or B, one safe vote is a mention of that candidate. If C is the voter s last preference, then (and only then) a mention of C is another safe vote. (ii) If the voter prefers C, then there are no safe mentions. (We use the neutral term mention rather than vote as some mentions are positive and some are negative). Proof: (i) Consider the situation before v s vote. Suppose that without v s vote, A, B, C, receive m, n, p mentions respectively, and p = 18 p. If v prefers A and votes for A, then m will increase to m + 1 and there is no way that A can be harmed by this. If v mentions C, then this will decrease C s chance of winning without affecting the relative standings of A,B. This would be fine if C is v s lowest preference. But otherwise, if B, C had been tied, and A fairly low, v could get his last choice B elected. 6

7 (ii) Assume for simplicity that v s preferences are C, B, A in that order. Clearly a mention of C could harm C which v does not want. A mention of A could enable A to win out over B which would not help v. So a mention of B can be the only safe vote. However, if B and C are even, then a mention of B would give B an extra vote and thereby harm C. So in fact there is no safe vote in the case where the top preference is C. It follows from some results of Fishburn and Brams that a safe ballot (in our sense) might not always exist for all aggregation functions Ag, e.g., Hare s STV is an example of this. In our discussion below we use the figures which Fishburn and Brams [FB83] use (page 208). In their example, Mr. and Mrs. Smith s car breaks down on the way to the polls just before closing time and they are unable to vote. Their preferences, in a tight race for mayor in their town, are Mrs. Bitt (first), Mr. Huff (second) and Dr. Wogg (last). In fact the Smiths dislike Dr. Wogg. Now Mrs. Bitt is the first choice of 499 voters, Mr. Huff of 500, and Dr. Wogg of 609. Thus (without the Smiths voting) Mrs. Bitt is eliminated in the first round, and all her second votes go to the other two, 417 to Huff and 82 to Wogg. Huff is then elected. However, if the Smiths had arrived in time and voted for Mrs. Bitt as their first choice, then it would have been Mr. Huff who would have been eliminated in the first round, and his second votes, 324 and 285 respectively, would go to Wogg and Bitt respectively. So Wogg would be elected. The Smiths would have made their situation worse by voting for their favourite candidate, Mrs. Bitt, and they were lucky that their car broke down. We now show why the [FB83] result implies that there are no safe votes in STV. We note the following: 1) When there is a notion of sincerity then every safe vote must be sincere. This observation applies to plurality, approval voting, STV and Borda. Because it is clear that if you vote differently from your own preference, then it must happen at least some time that you will harm your own interest and you would have done better not voting. A non-sincere vote cannot be safe. 2) Therefore if no sincere vote is safe, no vote is safe. 7

8 Since the sincere votes with STV are not safe there are no safe votes with STV but there are with plurality, approval voting and the Borda count. This would seem to indicate at least some advantage to approval voting over STV. Does all this mean that aggregation functions which do allow for safe votes are somehow nice? Unfortunately not always, and we offer the following example. Suppose that each voter is asked to vote by either submitting a card with an A and the name of a single candidate, or else a card with a B, and a ranking of all candidates. Ag works as follows. 1) If all cards are marked with an A then the winner is decided by plurality. 2) If at least one card is marked with a B, then all A cards are ignored, and the winner is determined by STV from all the B cards. It is clear that voting for one s favourite candidate with an A card is safe, it cannot do harm. The only way that card is counted is if all votes are on A cards, in which case plurality is used and voting for one s favourite is safe. But it is extremely unlikely that it will do any good - it takes only one B card to make all A cards useless! This construction also shows easily that all four paradoxes of [FB83] can arise also with safe aggregation functions Ag. I.e., the No-show paradox, the Thwarted-majorities paradox, the Multiple-districts paradox, and the Moreis-less paradox can all arise even with safe aggregation functions. What stronger condition than safety is needed to avoid such examples, we do not know. Conjecture: We conjecture that there is a generalization of the Gibbard- Satterthwaite theorem for general functions Ag, where there is no clear notion of sincere voting. We conjecture that with suitable conditions, there is no dominant strategy. For note that in the cases where there is a notion of sincerity (e.g., where the ballots are entire preference orders, and the preference orders are used in a reasonable way), the necessity of strategizing in some cases is equivalent to the assertion that there is no dominant strategy. If there is a dominant strategy, then when sincerity makes sense, the only dominant strategy can be sincere. If the sincere strategy is not dominant, then clearly no strategy is dominant. 8

9 Now the statement that there is no dominant strategy does not require us to have a notion of sincerity to make it, and thus the non-existence of a dominant strategy ought to be generally provable for a large class of functions Ag. However, some of the pre-conditions imposed for the Arrow and Gibbard- Satterthwaite theorems to hold, only make sense if we are working with preference orders, and it will take ingenuity to come up with their more abstract versions. References [A63] K. J. Arrow, Social choice and individual values (2nd ed.), Wiley, New York, [Ba83] S. Barbera, Strategy-Proofness and Pivotal Voters: A Direct Proof of the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem, International Economic Review, 24:2, , June [Ben02] Jean-Pierre Benoit, Strategic Manipulation in Games when Lotteries and Ties are Permitted, research report, NYU, [B94] S. Brams, Voting Procedures in Handbook of Game Theory, Elsevier, 2: , [BF94] S. Brams and P. Fishburn, Voting Procedures in Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, North-Holland, [BF83] S. Brams and P. Fishburn, Approval Voting, Birkhauser, Boston, [CPP04] S. Chopra, E. Pacuit and R. Parikh, Knowledge Theoretic Properties of Strategic Voting, Proceedings of JELIA 2004 (ed. Alferes and Leite), Springer 2004, pages [D84] M. Dummett, Voting Procedures, Clarendon Press, Oxford, [FB83] P. Fishburn and S. Brams, Paradoxes of preferential voting, Mathematics Magazine, 56: ,

10 [G73] A. Gibbard, Manipulation of Voting Schemes: Econometrica, 41:4, , A General Result, [S73] M. Satterthwaite, The Existence of a Strategy Proof Voting Procedure: a Topic in Social Choice Theory, University of Wisconsin, [S75] M. Satterthwaite, Strategy-proofness and Arrow s Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Functions, Journal of Economic Theory, 10:2, , [S70] A. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare, Holden Day, San Francisco, Appendix In this appendix we formally state the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem [G73, S73, S75]. The statement of the theorem and the notation follows that found in [Ba83]. For more information and a proof of the following theorem, the reader can consult [Ba83]. Let A = {1,..., n} be a set of agents, or voters, and O = {o 1,..., o k } a set of candidates. Each agent is assumed to have a preference over the set of candidates O. Formally, a preference for agent i A is a complete, reflexive, transitive and antisymmetric binary relation on O. Let P be the set of all such preferences. A preference profile is an element P P n. Let P P be a preference, then T op(p ) (the choice of P ), is the top element of P. Note that T op(p ) will always be a uniquely defined given our assumptions about P. Let P P n be a preference profile. Given a preference P, let P i P denote the preference profile that is just like P except that in the ith position, P i is replaced by P. Formally if P = P 1,..., P i,..., P n, then P i P = P 1,..., P i 1, P, P i+1,..., P n. A voting scheme is a function Ag : P n O. We denote the range of Ag by Ag[P n ]. We shall henceforth assume that this range, and so of course O has at least three elements. A voting scheme is dictatorial iff there is an agent i A such that for each P P n, Ag( P ) = T op(p i ). In other words, a voting scheme Ag is dictatorial 10

11 iff the candidate chosen by Ag is always the top choice of a single agent i (called the dictator). A voting scheme is manipulable iff there is a profile P P n, a preference P P and an agent i A such that Ag( P i P )P i Ag( P ). Here Ag( P ) is what Ag picks if the agent submits her true preference order P and Ag( P i P ) is what Ag picks if the agent submits P instead. And the second is better for the agent according to the agent s own preference ordering P i. In short, a voting scheme is manipulable iff there is an agent i who would do better (i.e., the candidate selected by Ag under P i P is preferred by i to the candidate selected by Ag under P ) by reporting preference P. Theorem 6 (The Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem) Let Ag be a voting scheme whose range contains more than two alternatives. Then Ag is either dictatorial or manipulable. 11

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007 Computational Social Choice: Spring 2007 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 Plan for Today This lecture will be an introduction to voting

More information

Lecture 12: Topics in Voting Theory

Lecture 12: Topics in Voting Theory Lecture 12: Topics in Voting Theory Eric Pacuit ILLC, University of Amsterdam staff.science.uva.nl/ epacuit epacuit@science.uva.nl Lecture Date: May 11, 2006 Caput Logic, Language and Information: Social

More information

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision:

Voting rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision: rules: (Dixit and Skeath, ch 14) Recall parkland provision decision: Assume - n=10; - total cost of proposed parkland=38; - if provided, each pays equal share = 3.8 - there are two groups of individuals

More information

Social welfare functions

Social welfare functions Social welfare functions We have defined a social choice function as a procedure that determines for each possible profile (set of preference ballots) of the voters the winner or set of winners for the

More information

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures

Mathematics and Social Choice Theory. Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives. 4.1 Social choice procedures Mathematics and Social Choice Theory Topic 4 Voting methods with more than 2 alternatives 4.1 Social choice procedures 4.2 Analysis of voting methods 4.3 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem 4.4 Cumulative voting

More information

Elections with Only 2 Alternatives

Elections with Only 2 Alternatives Math 203: Chapter 12: Voting Systems and Drawbacks: How do we decide the best voting system? Elections with Only 2 Alternatives What is an individual preference list? Majority Rules: Pick 1 of 2 candidates

More information

Social Choice. CSC304 Lecture 21 November 28, Allan Borodin Adapted from Craig Boutilier s slides

Social Choice. CSC304 Lecture 21 November 28, Allan Borodin Adapted from Craig Boutilier s slides Social Choice CSC304 Lecture 21 November 28, 2016 Allan Borodin Adapted from Craig Boutilier s slides 1 Todays agenda and announcements Today: Review of popular voting rules. Axioms, Manipulation, Impossibility

More information

Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Kenneth Arrow. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Strategically vulnerable

Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Kenneth Arrow. Recall: Properties of ranking rules. Strategically vulnerable Outline for today Stat155 Game Theory Lecture 26: More Voting. Peter Bartlett December 1, 2016 1 / 31 2 / 31 Recall: Voting and Ranking Recall: Properties of ranking rules Assumptions There is a set Γ

More information

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing

Chapter 10. The Manipulability of Voting Systems. For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching. Chapter Briefing Chapter 10 The Manipulability of Voting Systems For All Practical Purposes: Effective Teaching As a teaching assistant, you most likely will administer and proctor many exams. Although it is tempting to

More information

The Manipulability of Voting Systems. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

The Manipulability of Voting Systems. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them. Chapter 10 The Manipulability of Voting Systems Chapter Objectives Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them. Explain what is meant by voting manipulation. Determine if a voter,

More information

Voting Criteria April

Voting Criteria April Voting Criteria 21-301 2018 30 April 1 Evaluating voting methods In the last session, we learned about different voting methods. In this session, we will focus on the criteria we use to evaluate whether

More information

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6

(67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, Lecture 6 (67686) Mathematical Foundations of AI June 18, 2008 Lecturer: Ariel D. Procaccia Lecture 6 Scribe: Ezra Resnick & Ariel Imber 1 Introduction: Social choice theory Thus far in the course, we have dealt

More information

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory

MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory MATH4999 Capstone Projects in Mathematics and Economics Topic 3 Voting methods and social choice theory 3.1 Social choice procedures Plurality voting Borda count Elimination procedures Sequential pairwise

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems Arrow s Impossibility Theorem on Social Choice Systems Ashvin A. Swaminathan January 11, 2013 Abstract Social choice theory is a field that concerns methods of aggregating individual interests to determine

More information

Complexity of Manipulating Elections with Few Candidates

Complexity of Manipulating Elections with Few Candidates Complexity of Manipulating Elections with Few Candidates Vincent Conitzer and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University 5000 Forbes Avenue Pittsburgh, PA 15213 {conitzer, sandholm}@cs.cmu.edu

More information

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8

Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, Lecture 8 Topics on the Border of Economics and Computation December 18, 2005 Lecturer: Noam Nisan Lecture 8 Scribe: Ofer Dekel 1 Correlated Equilibrium In the previous lecture, we introduced the concept of correlated

More information

answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice

answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice answers to some of the sample exercises : Public Choice Ques 1 The following table lists the way that 5 different voters rank five different alternatives. Is there a Condorcet winner under pairwise majority

More information

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan Lesson Plan For All Practical Purposes An Introduction to Social Choice Majority Rule and Condorcet s Method Mathematical Literacy in Today s World, 9th ed. Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates

More information

Introduction to Theory of Voting. Chapter 2 of Computational Social Choice by William Zwicker

Introduction to Theory of Voting. Chapter 2 of Computational Social Choice by William Zwicker Introduction to Theory of Voting Chapter 2 of Computational Social Choice by William Zwicker If we assume Introduction 1. every two voters play equivalent roles in our voting rule 2. every two alternatives

More information

Random tie-breaking in STV

Random tie-breaking in STV Random tie-breaking in STV Jonathan Lundell jlundell@pobox.com often broken randomly as well, by coin toss, drawing straws, or drawing a high card.) 1 Introduction The resolution of ties in STV elections

More information

Approaches to Voting Systems

Approaches to Voting Systems Approaches to Voting Systems Properties, paradoxes, incompatibilities Hannu Nurmi Department of Philosophy, Contemporary History and Political Science University of Turku Game Theory and Voting Systems,

More information

Critical Strategies Under Approval Voting: Who Gets Ruled In And Ruled Out

Critical Strategies Under Approval Voting: Who Gets Ruled In And Ruled Out Critical Strategies Under Approval Voting: Who Gets Ruled In And Ruled Out Steven J. Brams Department of Politics New York University New York, NY 10003 USA steven.brams@nyu.edu M. Remzi Sanver Department

More information

Chapter 1 Practice Test Questions

Chapter 1 Practice Test Questions 0728 Finite Math Chapter 1 Practice Test Questions VOCABULARY. On the exam, be prepared to match the correct definition to the following terms: 1) Voting Elements: Single-choice ballot, preference ballot,

More information

Public Choice. Slide 1

Public Choice. Slide 1 Public Choice We investigate how people can come up with a group decision mechanism. Several aspects of our economy can not be handled by the competitive market. Whenever there is market failure, there

More information

Voter Sovereignty and Election Outcomes

Voter Sovereignty and Election Outcomes Voter Sovereignty and Election Outcomes Steven J. Brams Department of Politics New York University New York, NY 10003 USA steven.brams@nyu.edu M. Remzi Sanver Department of Economics Istanbul Bilgi University

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Some announcements Final reflections due on Monday. You now have all of the methods and so you can begin analyzing the results of your election. Today s Goals We will discuss

More information

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE

VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE N. R. Miller 05/01/97 5 th rev. 8/22/06 VOTING TO ELECT A SINGLE CANDIDATE This discussion focuses on single-winner elections, in which a single candidate is elected from a field of two or more candidates.

More information

Voting System: elections

Voting System: elections Voting System: elections 6 April 25, 2008 Abstract A voting system allows voters to choose between options. And, an election is an important voting system to select a cendidate. In 1951, Arrow s impossibility

More information

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2017

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2017 Computational Social Choice: Spring 2017 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 Plan for Today So far we saw three voting rules: plurality, plurality

More information

Simple methods for single winner elections

Simple methods for single winner elections Simple methods for single winner elections Christoph Börgers Mathematics Department Tufts University Medford, MA April 14, 2018 http://emerald.tufts.edu/~cborgers/ I have posted these slides there. 1 /

More information

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1

The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1 The mathematics of voting, power, and sharing Part 1 Voting systems A voting system or a voting scheme is a way for a group of people to select one from among several possibilities. If there are only two

More information

CS 886: Multiagent Systems. Fall 2016 Kate Larson

CS 886: Multiagent Systems. Fall 2016 Kate Larson CS 886: Multiagent Systems Fall 2016 Kate Larson Multiagent Systems We will study the mathematical and computational foundations of multiagent systems, with a focus on the analysis of systems where agents

More information

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem

1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem 1.6 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Some announcements Homework #2: Text (pages 33-35) 51, 56-60, 61, 65, 71-75 (this is posted on Sakai) For Monday, read Chapter 2 (pages 36-57) Today s Goals We will discuss

More information

CSC304 Lecture 14. Begin Computational Social Choice: Voting 1: Introduction, Axioms, Rules. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

CSC304 Lecture 14. Begin Computational Social Choice: Voting 1: Introduction, Axioms, Rules. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1 CSC304 Lecture 14 Begin Computational Social Choice: Voting 1: Introduction, Axioms, Rules CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1 Social Choice Theory Mathematical theory for aggregating individual preferences into collective

More information

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE

Social Choice Theory. Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE A brief and An incomplete Introduction Introduction to to Social Choice Theory Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE What is Social Choice Theory? Aim: study decision problems in which a group has to take a decision

More information

Voting Protocols. Introduction. Social choice: preference aggregation Our settings. Voting protocols are examples of social choice mechanisms

Voting Protocols. Introduction. Social choice: preference aggregation Our settings. Voting protocols are examples of social choice mechanisms Voting Protocols Yiling Chen September 14, 2011 Introduction Social choice: preference aggregation Our settings A set of agents have preferences over a set of alternatives Taking preferences of all agents,

More information

The Mathematics of Voting

The Mathematics of Voting The Mathematics of Voting Voting Methods Summary Last time, we considered elections for Math Club President from among four candidates: Alisha (A), Boris (B), Carmen (C), and Dave (D). All 37 voters submitted

More information

VOTING SYSTEMS AND ARROW S THEOREM

VOTING SYSTEMS AND ARROW S THEOREM VOTING SYSTEMS AND ARROW S THEOREM AKHIL MATHEW Abstract. The following is a brief discussion of Arrow s theorem in economics. I wrote it for an economics class in high school. 1. Background Arrow s theorem

More information

Convergence of Iterative Voting

Convergence of Iterative Voting Convergence of Iterative Voting Omer Lev omerl@cs.huji.ac.il School of Computer Science and Engineering The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Jerusalem 91904, Israel Jeffrey S. Rosenschein jeff@cs.huji.ac.il

More information

Complexity of Terminating Preference Elicitation

Complexity of Terminating Preference Elicitation Complexity of Terminating Preference Elicitation Toby Walsh NICTA and UNSW Sydney, Australia tw@cse.unsw.edu.au ABSTRACT Complexity theory is a useful tool to study computational issues surrounding the

More information

Rationality of Voting and Voting Systems: Lecture II

Rationality of Voting and Voting Systems: Lecture II Rationality of Voting and Voting Systems: Lecture II Rationality of Voting Systems Hannu Nurmi Department of Political Science University of Turku Three Lectures at National Research University Higher

More information

Introduction to the Theory of Voting

Introduction to the Theory of Voting November 11, 2015 1 Introduction What is Voting? Motivation 2 Axioms I Anonymity, Neutrality and Pareto Property Issues 3 Voting Rules I Condorcet Extensions and Scoring Rules 4 Axioms II Reinforcement

More information

The Impossibilities of Voting

The Impossibilities of Voting The Impossibilities of Voting Introduction Majority Criterion Condorcet Criterion Monotonicity Criterion Irrelevant Alternatives Criterion Arrow s Impossibility Theorem 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. Slide

More information

Varieties of failure of monotonicity and participation under five voting methods

Varieties of failure of monotonicity and participation under five voting methods Theory Dec. (2013) 75:59 77 DOI 10.1007/s18-012-9306-7 Varieties of failure of monotonicity and participation under five voting methods Dan S. Felsenthal Nicolaus Tideman Published online: 27 April 2012

More information

Economics 470 Some Notes on Simple Alternatives to Majority Rule

Economics 470 Some Notes on Simple Alternatives to Majority Rule Economics 470 Some Notes on Simple Alternatives to Majority Rule Some of the voting procedures considered here are not considered as a means of revealing preferences on a public good issue, but as a means

More information

Voting and Complexity

Voting and Complexity Voting and Complexity legrand@cse.wustl.edu Voting and Complexity: Introduction Outline Introduction Hardness of finding the winner(s) Polynomial systems NP-hard systems The minimax procedure [Brams et

More information

Possible voting reforms in the United States

Possible voting reforms in the United States Possible voting reforms in the United States Since the disputed 2000 Presidential election, there have numerous proposals to improve how elections are conducted. While most proposals have attempted to

More information

Social Choice & Mechanism Design

Social Choice & Mechanism Design Decision Making in Robots and Autonomous Agents Social Choice & Mechanism Design Subramanian Ramamoorthy School of Informatics 2 April, 2013 Introduction Social Choice Our setting: a set of outcomes agents

More information

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem

Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem Notes for Session 7 Basic Voting Theory and Arrow s Theorem We follow up the Impossibility (Session 6) of pooling expert probabilities, while preserving unanimities in both unconditional and conditional

More information

Rock the Vote or Vote The Rock

Rock the Vote or Vote The Rock Rock the Vote or Vote The Rock Tom Edgar Department of Mathematics University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana October 27, 2008 Graduate Student Seminar Introduction Basic Counting Extended Counting Introduction

More information

Voting Systems That Combine Approval and Preference

Voting Systems That Combine Approval and Preference Voting Systems That Combine Approval and Preference Steven J. Brams Department of Politics New York University New York, NY 10003 USA steven.brams@nyu.edu M. Remzi Sanver Department of Economics Istanbul

More information

Voting and preference aggregation

Voting and preference aggregation Voting and preference aggregation CSC200 Lecture 38 March 14, 2016 Allan Borodin (adapted from Craig Boutilier slides) Announcements and todays agenda Today: Voting and preference aggregation Reading for

More information

Voting and preference aggregation

Voting and preference aggregation Voting and preference aggregation CSC304 Lecture 20 November 23, 2016 Allan Borodin (adapted from Craig Boutilier slides) Announcements and todays agenda Today: Voting and preference aggregation Reading

More information

Voter Response to Iterated Poll Information

Voter Response to Iterated Poll Information Voter Response to Iterated Poll Information MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Annemieke Reijngoud (born June 30, 1987 in Groningen, The Netherlands) under the supervision of Dr. Ulle Endriss, and

More information

Mathematical Thinking. Chapter 9 Voting Systems

Mathematical Thinking. Chapter 9 Voting Systems Mathematical Thinking Chapter 9 Voting Systems Voting Systems A voting system is a rule for transforming a set of individual preferences into a single group decision. What are the desirable properties

More information

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/36

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/36 Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems Voting I 1/36 Each even year every member of the house is up for election and about a third of the senate seats are up for grabs. Most people do not realize that there

More information

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/31

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems. Voting I 1/31 Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems Voting I 1/31 In 2014 every member of the house is up for election and about a third of the senate seats will be up for grabs. Most people do not realize that there

More information

Math116Chap1VotingPart2.notebook January 12, Part II. Other Methods of Voting and Other "Fairness Criteria"

Math116Chap1VotingPart2.notebook January 12, Part II. Other Methods of Voting and Other Fairness Criteria Part II Other Methods of Voting and Other "Fairness Criteria" Plurality with Elimination Method Round 1. Count the first place votes for each candidate, just as you would in the plurality method. If a

More information

The search for a perfect voting system. MATH 105: Contemporary Mathematics. University of Louisville. October 31, 2017

The search for a perfect voting system. MATH 105: Contemporary Mathematics. University of Louisville. October 31, 2017 The search for a perfect voting system MATH 105: Contemporary Mathematics University of Louisville October 31, 2017 Review of Fairness Criteria Fairness Criteria 2 / 14 We ve seen three fairness criteria

More information

Towards an Information-Neutral Voting Scheme That Does Not Leave Too Much To Chance

Towards an Information-Neutral Voting Scheme That Does Not Leave Too Much To Chance Towards an Information-Neutral Voting Scheme That Does Not Leave Too Much To Chance Presented at the Midwest Political Science Association 54th Annual Meeting, April 18-20, 1996 Lorrie Faith Cranor Department

More information

c M. J. Wooldridge, used by permission/updated by Simon Parsons, Spring

c M. J. Wooldridge, used by permission/updated by Simon Parsons, Spring Today LECTURE 8: MAKING GROUP DECISIONS CIS 716.5, Spring 2010 We continue thinking in the same framework as last lecture: multiagent encounters game-like interactions participants act strategically We

More information

Desirable properties of social choice procedures. We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures:

Desirable properties of social choice procedures. We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures: Desirable properties of social choice procedures We now outline a number of properties that are desirable for these social choice procedures: 1. Pareto [named for noted economist Vilfredo Pareto (1848-1923)]

More information

Name Date I. Consider the preference schedule in an election with 5 candidates.

Name Date I. Consider the preference schedule in an election with 5 candidates. Name Date I. Consider the preference schedule in an election with 5 candidates. 1. How many voters voted in this election? 2. How many votes are needed for a majority (more than 50% of the vote)? 3. How

More information

Voting Methods

Voting Methods 1.3-1.5 Voting Methods Some announcements Homework #1: Text (pages 28-33) 1, 4, 7, 10, 12, 19, 22, 29, 32, 38, 42, 50, 51, 56-60, 61, 65 (this is posted on Sakai) Math Center study sessions with Katie

More information

Categoric and Ordinal Voting: An Overview

Categoric and Ordinal Voting: An Overview Categoric and Ordinal Voting: An Overview Harrie de Swart 1, Ad van Deemen 2, Eliora van der Hout 1 and Peter Kop 3 1 Tilburg University, Faculty of Philosophy, P.O. Box 90153 5000 LE Tilburg, The Netherlands;

More information

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc.

Section Voting Methods. Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc. Section 15.1 Voting Methods INB Table of Contents Date Topic Page # February 24, 2014 Test #3 Practice Test 38 February 24, 2014 Test #3 Practice Test Workspace 39 March 10, 2014 Test #3 40 March 10, 2014

More information

Math Circle Voting Methods Practice. March 31, 2013

Math Circle Voting Methods Practice. March 31, 2013 Voting Methods Practice 1) Three students are running for class vice president: Chad, Courtney and Gwyn. Each student ranked the candidates in order of preference. The chart below shows the results of

More information

Strategic Voting and Strategic Candidacy

Strategic Voting and Strategic Candidacy Strategic Voting and Strategic Candidacy Markus Brill and Vincent Conitzer Department of Computer Science Duke University Durham, NC 27708, USA {brill,conitzer}@cs.duke.edu Abstract Models of strategic

More information

Voting. Suppose that the outcome is determined by the mean of all voter s positions.

Voting. Suppose that the outcome is determined by the mean of all voter s positions. Voting Suppose that the voters are voting on a single-dimensional issue. (Say 0 is extreme left and 100 is extreme right for example.) Each voter has a favorite point on the spectrum and the closer the

More information

Social choice theory

Social choice theory Social choice theory A brief introduction Denis Bouyssou CNRS LAMSADE Paris, France Introduction Motivation Aims analyze a number of properties of electoral systems present a few elements of the classical

More information

9.3 Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates

9.3 Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates 9.3 Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates With three or more candidates, there are several additional procedures that seem to give reasonable ways to choose a winner. If we look closely at

More information

What is the Best Election Method?

What is the Best Election Method? What is the Best Election Method? E. Maskin Harvard University Gorman Lectures University College, London February 2016 Today and tomorrow will explore 2 Today and tomorrow will explore election methods

More information

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream The application of mathematics to the study of human beings their behavior, values, interactions, conflicts, and methods of making decisions is generally

More information

Voting Systems for Social Choice

Voting Systems for Social Choice Hannu Nurmi Public Choice Research Centre and Department of Political Science University of Turku 20014 Turku Finland Voting Systems for Social Choice Springer The author thanks D. Marc Kilgour and Colin

More information

Lecture 16: Voting systems

Lecture 16: Voting systems Lecture 16: Voting systems Economics 336 Economics 336 (Toronto) Lecture 16: Voting systems 1 / 18 Introduction Last lecture we looked at the basic theory of majority voting: instability in voting: Condorcet

More information

Many Social Choice Rules

Many Social Choice Rules Many Social Choice Rules 1 Introduction So far, I have mentioned several of the most commonly used social choice rules : pairwise majority rule, plurality, plurality with a single run off, the Borda count.

More information

Main idea: Voting systems matter.

Main idea: Voting systems matter. Voting Systems Main idea: Voting systems matter. Electoral College Winner takes all in most states (48/50) (plurality in states) 270/538 electoral votes needed to win (majority) If 270 isn t obtained -

More information

How Should Members of Parliament (and Presidents) Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study

How Should Members of Parliament (and Presidents) Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study How Should Members of Parliament (and Presidents) Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study What s wrong with this picture? 2005 U.K. General Election Constituency of Croyden Central vote totals

More information

The Process of Electing a President

The Process of Electing a President 1 of 12 9/1/2011 1:30 PM The Process of Electing a President The issue of how to equalize the influence of people in different parts of the country in the selection of party candidates is a complex one,

More information

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems 3 March 2014 Voting I 3 March 2014 1/27 In 2014 every member of the house is up for election and about a third of the senate seats will be up for grabs. Most people

More information

Voting Methods for Municipal Elections: Propaganda, Field Experiments and what USA voters want from an Election Algorithm

Voting Methods for Municipal Elections: Propaganda, Field Experiments and what USA voters want from an Election Algorithm Voting Methods for Municipal Elections: Propaganda, Field Experiments and what USA voters want from an Election Algorithm Kathryn Lenz, Mathematics and Statistics Department, University of Minnesota Duluth

More information

: It is mathematically impossible for a democratic voting method to satisfy all of the fairness criteria was proven in 1949.

: It is mathematically impossible for a democratic voting method to satisfy all of the fairness criteria was proven in 1949. Chapter 1 Notes from Voting Theory: the mathematics of the intricacies and subtleties of how voting is done and the votes are counted. In the early 20 th century, social scientists and mathematicians working

More information

CSC304 Lecture 16. Voting 3: Axiomatic, Statistical, and Utilitarian Approaches to Voting. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

CSC304 Lecture 16. Voting 3: Axiomatic, Statistical, and Utilitarian Approaches to Voting. CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1 CSC304 Lecture 16 Voting 3: Axiomatic, Statistical, and Utilitarian Approaches to Voting CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1 Announcements Assignment 2 was due today at 3pm If you have grace credits left (check MarkUs),

More information

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued

Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued Voting: Issues, Problems, and Systems, Continued 7 March 2014 Voting III 7 March 2014 1/27 Last Time We ve discussed several voting systems and conditions which may or may not be satisfied by a system.

More information

Democratic Rules in Context

Democratic Rules in Context Democratic Rules in Context Hannu Nurmi Public Choice Research Centre and Department of Political Science University of Turku Institutions in Context 2012 (PCRC, Turku) Democratic Rules in Context 4 June,

More information

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice.

Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice. Chapter 4: Voting and Social Choice. Topics: Ordinal Welfarism Condorcet and Borda: 2 alternatives for majority voting Voting over Resource Allocation Single-Peaked Preferences Intermediate Preferences

More information

NP-Hard Manipulations of Voting Schemes

NP-Hard Manipulations of Voting Schemes NP-Hard Manipulations of Voting Schemes Elizabeth Cross December 9, 2005 1 Introduction Voting schemes are common social choice function that allow voters to aggregate their preferences in a socially desirable

More information

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here?

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here? The Arrow Impossibility Theorem: Where Do We Go From Here? Eric Maskin Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton Arrow Lecture Columbia University December 11, 2009 I thank Amartya Sen and Joseph Stiglitz

More information

Social Choice: The Impossible Dream. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them.

Social Choice: The Impossible Dream. Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them. Chapter Objectives Check off these skills when you feel that you have mastered them. Analyze and interpret preference list ballots. Explain three desired properties of Majority Rule. Explain May s theorem.

More information

Lecture 11. Voting. Outline

Lecture 11. Voting. Outline Lecture 11 Voting Outline Hanging Chads Again Did Ralph Nader cause the Bush presidency? A Paradox Left Middle Right 40 25 35 Robespierre Danton Lafarge D L R L R D A Paradox Consider Robespierre versus

More information

Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures*

Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures* Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures* Steven J. Brams Department of Politics New York University New York, NY 10012 *This essay is adapted, with permission, from

More information

Voting Systems. High School Circle I. June 4, 2017

Voting Systems. High School Circle I. June 4, 2017 Voting Systems High School Circle I June 4, 2017 Today we are going to start our study of voting systems. Put loosely, a voting system takes the preferences of many people, and converted them into a group

More information

Explaining the Impossible: Kenneth Arrow s Nobel Prize Winning Theorem on Elections

Explaining the Impossible: Kenneth Arrow s Nobel Prize Winning Theorem on Elections Explaining the Impossible: Kenneth Arrow s Nobel Prize Winning Theorem on Elections Dr. Rick Klima Appalachian State University Boone, North Carolina U.S. Presidential Vote Totals, 2000 Candidate Bush

More information

Australian AI 2015 Tutorial Program Computational Social Choice

Australian AI 2015 Tutorial Program Computational Social Choice Australian AI 2015 Tutorial Program Computational Social Choice Haris Aziz and Nicholas Mattei www.csiro.au Social Choice Given a collection of agents with preferences over a set of things (houses, cakes,

More information

Completion of Gibbard-Satterthwaite impossibility theorem; range voting and voter honesty

Completion of Gibbard-Satterthwaite impossibility theorem; range voting and voter honesty Completion of Gibbard-Satterthwaite impossibility theorem; range voting and voter honesty Warren D. Smith warren.wds at gmail.com October 23, 2006 Abstract Let S be a reasonable single-winner voting system.

More information

Only a Dictatorship is Efficient or Neutral

Only a Dictatorship is Efficient or Neutral NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository New York University Law and Economics Working Papers New York University School of Law 12-28-2006 Only a Dictatorship is Efficient or Neutral Jean-Pierre Benoit

More information

Vote budgets and Dodgson s method of marks

Vote budgets and Dodgson s method of marks Vote budgets and Dodgson s method of marks Walter Bossert Centre Interuniversitaire de Recherche en Economie Quantitative (CIREQ) P.O. Box 618, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca

More information

Is Majority Rule the Best Voting Method? Partha Dasgupta and Eric Maskin

Is Majority Rule the Best Voting Method? Partha Dasgupta and Eric Maskin Is Majority Rule the Best Voting Method? by Partha Dasgupta and Eric Maskin June 2003 The authors are, respectively, the Frank Ramsey Professor of Economics at the University of Cambridge, UK, and the

More information

Introduction to Social Choice

Introduction to Social Choice for to Social Choice University of Waterloo January 14, 2013 Outline for 1 2 3 4 for 5 What Is Social Choice Theory for Study of decision problems in which a group has to make the decision The decision

More information

Head-to-Head Winner. To decide if a Head-to-Head winner exists: Every candidate is matched on a one-on-one basis with every other candidate.

Head-to-Head Winner. To decide if a Head-to-Head winner exists: Every candidate is matched on a one-on-one basis with every other candidate. Head-to-Head Winner A candidate is a Head-to-Head winner if he or she beats all other candidates by majority rule when they meet head-to-head (one-on-one). To decide if a Head-to-Head winner exists: Every

More information